The APA Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The APA Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy 2013 The APA GUide To GraduatE ProGrAms in PhilosoPhy University of Delaware Newark, DE 19716 www.apaonline.org All data collected by the American Philosophical Association. The data in this publication have been provided by the departments and programs listed; in the cases where no response was received to repeated requests for information, the most recent data provided, if any, can be found in the previous edition. The APA cannot guarantee the accuracy of this report; because all information has been self- reported, there may be errors or inconsistencies in these data. Readers should therefore examine the available data closely to ensure that any comparisons are made in a fair and reasonable manner. Errors or inconsistencies should be brought to the attention of the American Philosophical Association by email to [email protected]. For clarification, correction, updating, or supplementation of the information provided, contact the department(s) in question. © 2012 The American Philosophical Association This publication of the American Philosophical Association may not be reproduced for sale or future distribution without the express written consent of the executive director. Inquiries should be directed as follows: The American Philosophical Association University of Delaware, 31 Amstel Avenue, Newark, DE 19716 Phone (302) 831-1112 • Fax (302) 831-8690 [email protected] Last updated February 3, 2013 About the Grad Guide The Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy, originally published biennially until the early 2000s, was relaunched in 2012 as an annual online resource. The guide compiles data on both doctoral and master’s degree programs in philosophy at institutions throughout the US and Canada, offering prospective students, job candidates, and other members of the profession a rich resource on post- graduate education and employment in philosophy. This year’s guide has been expanded to include more demographic data on each program as well as information on faculty, degree requirements, entry requirements, financial aid, placements, and more. All data in the guide are self-reported by representatives of the institutions, and data are included only for institutions that completed the Grad Guide survey. Using the Grad Guide The Grad Guide is a useful starting point for prospective graduate students and job candidates, but the APA recommends additional consultation with advisers and people directly involved with programs of interest. Further, as all information in the guide is self-reported by representatives of the institutions, readers should examine the data closely to ensure that any comparisons are made in a fair and reasonable manner. Please note that the APA does not rank philosophy programs or institutions. Read the APA statement on rankings of departments. Demographic Data In the survey that underlies the 2013 edition, we requested information on race and LGBT status of students and faculty. We thank the APA Committee on the Status of Women for providing the demographic data survey instrument that was incorporated into the Grad Guide survey. There is no widely accepted standard for collecting such data, however, and the availability and thoroughness of data varies greatly. Some schools do not (or cannot) track this information. For these reasons, we provide the data we received with the understanding that this data should not be used for quantitative evaluation of the diversity of programs or institutions. Though the demographic information is inconsistent, it is included in the Grad Guide because collecting and providing these data supports ongoing efforts to increase the diversity of the profession by making existing information more widely available and raising awareness about the need for additional data on diversity. Previous Editions • 2012 Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy (PDF) Corrections and Feedback If your institution is not included in the guide and would like to be, if you would like to report errors or inconsistencies in the data, or if you have suggestions for future editions of the Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy, please submit a Grad Guide Feedback Form. Boston College Report year: 2013 Website http://www.bc.edu/schools/cas/philosophy/ Department name Philosophy Department chair Arthur Madigan, S. J., Professor and Chair Faculty James Bernauer, S. J., Professor • Oliva Blanchette, Professor • Jeffrey Bloechl, Assoc. Professor • Aspen Brinton, Assistant Professor (appointment beginning 2013-14) • Sarah Byers, Assistant Professor • Patrick Byrne, Professor • Jorge Garcia, Professor • Gary Gurtler, S.J., Assoc. Professor • David W. Johnson, Assistant Professor (appointment beginning 2013-14) • Richard Kearney, Charles Seelig Professor in Philosophy • Peter Kreeft, Professor • Micah Lott, Assistant Professor • Arthur Madigan, S.J., Fitzgibbons Professor and Chair • Marina McCoy, Associate Professor • Daniel McKaughan, Assistant Professor • David Rasmussen, Professor • Vanessa Rumble, Associate Professor • John Sallis, Frederick J. Adelmann S. J. Professor of Philosophy • Jean-Luc Solere, Associate Professor • Andrea Staiti, Assistant Professor • Marius Stan, Assistant Professor • Eileen Sweeney, Professor • Ronald Tacelli, S.J., Assoc. Professor • Jonathan Trejo-Mathys, Assistant Professor Efforts to increase inclusiveness The department made two tenure track appointments for 2013-14, one a woman and another an Asian-American. Since 2000 the department has granted doctoral degrees to 8 African African Americans, 5 Hispanics, 4 Asian Asian Americans, 1 Native American, and 10 women. Faculty Tenured Tenure-track Non-tenure Degrees offered: Ph.D. Master's track Women 3 1 2 Financial Aid Men 13 4 4 Teaching fellowships 15 Other gender 0 0 0 Non-teaching fellowships 10 African, 1 0 0 Teaching assistantships 0 African-American Scholarships 40 Asian 0 0 0 Students teaching their own classes 24 Native American 0 0 0 Other financial information Hispanic or Latin 0 0 0 Pacific Islander 0 0 0 Multi-racial 0 0 0 Other race 0 0 0 LGBT 0 0 0 Disablity status 0 0 0 Total women Total men Total other Total faculty gender 6 21 0 27 Boston College Report year: 2013 Ph.D. program strengths The department offers a comprehensive Program in the history and problems of philosophy, allowing for concentration in the following areas: Ancient Philosophy, Medieval Philosophy, Continental Philosophy from Kant to the present, Social and Political Philosophy, and Philosophy of Science. A significant feature of the Program is the extensive and diverse range of courses available to graduate students every semester. Ph.D. Students 2012 - 2013 Ph.D. tuition In state: $1,344/credit hour Women Men Other gender (Year ending) (Year ending) (Year ending) Out of state:$1,344/credit hour 2012 2013 2012 2013 2012 2013 Courses required for Ph.D. 16 African, 0 0 4 4 0 0 African-American Degrees awarded Asian 0 0 2 2 0 0 2009 2010 2011 2012 2013 Degrees awarded 12 4 7 8 6 Native American 0 0 0 0 0 0 Time to completion 7.75 6.75 7.5 7.6 6.2 Hispanic or Latino 0 0 4 3 0 0 Pacific Islander 0 0 0 0 0 0 Ph.D. program entry requirements Transcripts: Yes Multi-racial 0 0 0 0 0 0 Writing sample: Yes Other race 1 1 0 1 0 0 GPA: LGBT 0 0 0 0 0 0 TOEFL score: Disability status 0 0 1 1 0 0 Letters of recommendation: 3 GRE score: Totals 1 1 10 10 0 0 Other requirements: Total Ph.D. 11 Total Ph.D. 11 Students 2012 Students 2013 2 year teaching seminar, logic requirement, 2 foreign languages MA Students 2012 - 2013 MA tuition In state $1,344/credit hour Women Men Other gender (Year ending) (Year ending) (Year ending) Out of state $1,344/credit hour 2012 2013 2012 2013 2012 2013 Types of MA offered African, 0 0 0 0 0 0 Terminal MA Non-terminal MA African-American The APA defines a terminal master's degree as one that can be Asian 0 0 0 0 0 0 pursued without enrolling in a Ph.D. program. Courses required for MA: 10 Native American 0 0 0 0 0 0 Hispanic or Latino 0 0 0 0 0 0 MA program entry requirements Transcripts: Yes Pacific Islander 0 0 0 0 0 0 Writing sample: Yes Multi-racial 0 0 0 0 0 0 GPA: Other race 0 0 0 0 0 0 TOEFL score: LGBT 0 0 0 0 0 0 Letters of recommendation 3 Disability status 0 0 0 0 0 0 GRE score Other requirements: Totals 0 0 0 0 0 0 Total MA 0 Total MA 0 Students 2012 Students 2013 Boston College Report year: 2013 Placement Summary of Ph.D. Students 2008 to 2013 Data not provided Summary of MA Students 2008 to 2013 Data not provided Bowling Green State University-Main Campus Report year: 2013 Website http://www.bgsu.edu/departments/phil Department name Philosophy Department chair Michael Weber, Associate Professor Faculty Donald Callen, Assistant Professor • Christian Coons, Associate Professor • Albert Dzur, Professor • Louis Katzner, Professor Trustee • Kevin Vallier, Assistant Professor • Michael Weber, Associate Professor, Chair • Sara Worley, Associate Professor • Richard Yetter Chappell, Assistant Professor • Helen Yetter-Chappell, Assistant Professor Efforts to increase inclusiveness None provided Faculty Tenured Tenure-track Non-tenure Degrees offered: Ph.D. Master's track Women 1 1 0 Financial Aid Men 5 2 2 Teaching fellowships 0 Other gender 0 0 0 Non-teaching fellowships 1 African, 0 0 0 Teaching assistantships 23 African-American Scholarships 1 Asian 0 0 0 Students teaching their own classes 12 Native American 0 0 0 Other financial information Hispanic or Latin 0 0 0 na Pacific Islander 0 0 0 Multi-racial 0 0 0 Other race 0 0 0 LGBT 0 0 0 Disablity status 0 0 0 Total women Total men Total other Total faculty gender 2 9 0 11 Bowling Green State University-Main Campus Report year: 2013 Ph.D. program strengths Moral and Political Philosophy, Applied Ethics Ph.D.
Recommended publications
  • Articles Revisiting the Logical Empiricist Criticisms of Vitalism Bohang Chen1 Abstract
    Revisiting the Logical Empiricist Criticisms of Vitalism Bohang Chen Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science 2019 (7): 1-17 ISSN 2526-2270 www.historiographyofscience.org Belo Horizonte – MG / Brazil © The Author 2019 – This is an open access article Articles Revisiting the Logical Empiricist Criticisms of Vitalism Bohang Chen1 Abstract: Vitalism claims that biological organisms are governed by nonmaterial agents like entelechies. The received view today rejects vitalism by presupposing metaphysical materialism (or physicalism). Metaphysical materialism maintains that the world is ultimately material (or physical), and it, therefore, repudiates the existence of nonmaterial entelechies. However, this marks a shift compared with the arguments against vitalism developed by logical empiricists, who were indifferent to metaphysical issues and were only concerned with logical and empirical matters in the sciences. Logical empiricists rejected the concept of the entelechy (vitalism), because vital laws confirmed by biological phenomena were unavailable; in contrast, they accepted the concept of the atom (materialism), since it constituted physical laws and was therefore associated with verifiable results in modern physics. 1 Keywords: Vitalism; Materialism (or Physicalism); Logical Empiricism; Entelechy; Atom Received: 27 June 2019. Reviewed: 13 October 2019. Accepted: 17 October 2019. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.24117/2526-2270.2019.i7.03 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. _______________________________________________________________________ Introduction: The Metaphysical Refutation of Vitalism Today most biologists and philosophers understand vitalism as a heretical doctrine in the history of biology, originally proposed by Hans Driesch in the early twentieth century. 2 According to Driesch’s doctrine of vitalism, biological organisms are governed by nonmaterial vital agents termed entelechies (Driesch 1929; Churchill 1969; Allen 2008).
    [Show full text]
  • Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, Spi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, Spi
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics Alexis Burgess, Herman Cappelen, and David Plunkett 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © the several contributors 2020 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2020 Impression: 1 Some rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, for commercial purposes, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. This is an open access publication, available online and distributed under the terms of a Creative Commons Attribution – Non Commercial – No Derivatives 4.0 International licence (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0), a copy of which is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of this licence should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2019946746 ISBN 978–0–19–880185–6 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198801856.003.0001 Printed and bound in Great Britain by Clays Ltd, Elcograf S.p.A.
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism in Biology
    pdf version of the entry Reductionism in Biology http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/reduction-biology/ Reductionism in Biology from the Summer 2012 Edition of the First published Tue May 27, 2008; substantive revision Mon Apr 30, 2012 Stanford Encyclopedia Reductionism encompasses a set of ontological, epistemological, and methodological claims about the relations between different scientific of Philosophy domains. The basic question of reduction is whether the properties, concepts, explanations, or methods from one scientific domain (typically at higher levels of organization) can be deduced from or explained by the properties, concepts, explanations, or methods from another domain of science (typically one about lower levels of organization). Reduction is Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen John Perry germane to a variety of issues in philosophy of science, including the Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor structure of scientific theories, the relations between different scientific Editorial Board disciplines, the nature of explanation, the diversity of methodology, and http://plato.stanford.edu/board.html the very idea of theoretical progress, as well as to numerous topics in Library of Congress Catalog Data metaphysics and philosophy of mind, such as emergence, mereology, and ISSN: 1095-5054 supervenience. Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem- In recent philosophy of biology (1970s to the 1990s), the primary debate bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized about reduction has focused on the question of whether and in what sense distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the classical genetics can be reduced to molecular biology.
    [Show full text]
  • What Can the Philosophy of Biology Learn from the History of Biology?
    What can the Philosophy of Biology learn from the History of Biology? 19‐20 March 2016, Utrecht University (Sweelinckzaal, Drift 21), The Netherlands Questions about the interrelation between the history of science and the philosophy of science have received renewed attention in recent years. This workshop focuses on the life sciences and asks how we might employ historical findings and approaches in order to shed light on questions in the philosophy of biology. The workshop aims to take stock of previous work in this domain, to highlight current lines of research, and to identify challenges and opportunities for the future. This is the first Utrecht Workshop in Philosophy of the Life Sciences. It is hosted by the Descartes Centre for the History and Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities. 19 March 9.30‐10.30 Sabina Leonelli (Exeter) The Epistemology of Data‐Intensive Science: Integrating History, Philosophy and Social Studies of Data Practices 10.30‐11.30 Bert Theunissen (Utrecht) The role of genetics theory in animal breeding 11.30‐12.00 Coffee 12.00‐13.00 William Bechtel (San Diego) What can the history of biology teach philosophy about representing biological knowledge? 13.00‐14.00 Lunch 14.00‐15.00 Ingo Brigandt (Alberta) Research on developmental constraints in the 1980s, and its relevance to current work on evolvability 15.00‐16.00 Raphael Scholl (Cambridge) Rethinking the relationship between history and philosophy of biology 16.00‐17.00 Plenary Discussion 17.00 End 20 March 9.30‐10.30 Joeri Witteveen (Utrecht) Rethinking ‘population thinking’ 10.30‐11.30 Kärin Nickelsen (Munich) Research fields and research collectives: The case of photosynthesis studies, 1930s‐1950s 11.30‐12.00 Coffee 12.00‐13.00 Sahotra Sarkar (Austin) Reductionism in the Philosophy of Biology: What a Little History Does to the Debates 13.00‐14.00 Lunch 14.00‐15.00 Plenary Discussion 15.00 End of Workshop The event is free and open to all.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae of Ingo Brigandt
    Curriculum Vitae Ingo Brigandt Department of Philosophy Email: [email protected] University of Alberta Phone: +1 780-492-9030 2-40 Assiniboia Hall Webpage: http://www.ualberta.ca/~brigandt Edmonton, AB T6G 2E7 Canada Citizenship: Canadian and German citizen AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Philosophy of Biology, Feminist Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mind AREAS OF COMPETENCE Philosophy of Science, Socially Relevant Philosophy of Science, Bioethics, Philosophy of Language, Epistemology, History of Biology, Science Education ACADEMIC POSITIONS 07/2017 – Professor of Philosophy, University of Alberta 07/2015 – 06/2021 Associate Chair (Graduate Studies), Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta (on leave from July to December 2019) 04/2014 – 03/2024 Canada Research Chair in Philosophy of Biology, University of Alberta 08/2019 – 12/2019 Visiting Fellow, Centre for Advanced Study at the Norwegian Academy of Science and Letters, Oslo 2012 – 2017 Associate Professor of Philosophy (with tenure), University of Alberta 03/2015 – 05/2015 Visiting Scholar, Sydney Centre for the Foundations of Science, University of Sydney 09/2014 – 12/2014 Visiting Fellow, Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh 2008 – 2012 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Alberta (hired in 2006, appointment deferred for 2 years to take up a postdoctoral fellowship) 2006 – 2008 Izaak Walton Killam Memorial Postdoctoral Fellow, University of Alberta EDUCATION 2000 – 2006 Ph.D. in History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh
    [Show full text]
  • Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change
    Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change Ingo Brigandt Department of History and Philosophy of Science 1017 Cathedral of Learning University of Pittsburgh Pittsburgh, PA 15260 E-mail: [email protected] To be presented at the 4th Congress of the Spanish Society for Analytic Philosophy Murcia (Spain), 16-18 December 2004 paper: 2997 words abstract: 150 words Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change Abstract The paper discusses concept individuation in the context of scientific concepts and conceptual change in science. It is argued that some concepts can be individuated in different ways. A particular term may be viewed as corresponding to a single concept (which is ascribed to every person from a whole scientific field). But at the same time, we can legitimately individuate in a more fine grained manner, i.e., this term can also be considered as corresponding to two or several concepts (so that each of these concepts is attributed to a smaller group of persons only). The reason is that there are different philosophical and explanatory interests that underlie a particular study of the change of a scientific term. These interests determine how a concept is to be individuated; and as the same term can be subject to different philosophical studies and interests, its content can be individuated in different ways. HOLISM, CONCEPT INDIVIDUATION, AND CONCEPTUAL CHANGE 1 The topic of the present discussion is the individuation of concepts. I am primarily interested in scientific concepts and the phenomenon of conceptual change. My account will be based on a moderate holism about concept, using a conceptual role semantics—an approach that I view as fruitful for studying and explaining conceptual change in science, at least in biology.1 In order to motivate my position, I will briefly look at some recent debates about conceptual role semantics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Levels of Organization in the Biological Sciences
    The Concept of Levels of Organization in the Biological Sciences PhD Thesis Submitted August 2014 Revised June 2015 Daniel Stephen Brooks Department of Philosophy Bielefeld University Reviewers: Martin Carrier, Maria Kronfeldner Dedicated in friendship to Jan and Magga “He who has suffer'd you to impose on him knows you.” Table of Contents Table of Contents........................................................................................................................1 Chapter One: The Intuitive Appeal and Ubiquity of 'Levels of Organization'............................5 1.1 Introduction ................................................................................................................5 1.2 Analyzing 'Levels of Organization' in Biological Science..........................................7 1.2.1 Level Claims.....................................................................................................10 1.2.2 Wimsatt’s Characterization of Levels ..............................................................14 1.3 Initial Distinctions.....................................................................................................16 1.3.1 Erroneous Concepts of Levels...........................................................................18 1.4 Depictions of Levels in Biological Textbooks...........................................................20 1.4.1 The Character of 'Levels' in Biological Science................................................24 1.4.2 The Significance of 'Levels' in Biological Science...........................................30
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism in Biology - Philosophy - Oxford Bibliographies
    Reductionism in Biology - Philosophy - Oxford Bibliographies Reductionism in Biology Sahotra Sarkar, Alan Love, William Wimsatt LAST MODIFIED: 11 JANUARY 2018 DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195396577-0359 Introduction Reductionism concerns a set of ontological and epistemological claims, and methodological strictures based on them, about the relationship between two different scientific domains. The critical assumption is that one of these domains is privileged over the other in the sense that the concepts, rules, laws, and other elements of the privileged domain can be used to specify, constitute, or account for those of the other “reduced” domain. This specification often consists of explanation, such that the “reducing” domain is epistemically privileged over the reduced one. Explanations of this type are “reductionist” (or, are “reductions”) and reductionism is then the thesis that such explanations will always be forthcoming or at least are possible in principle. Reductionism is most plausible if the entities of the reduced domain can be interpreted as arising from (e.g., as aggregates of) entities of the reduced domain. This ontological claim is controversial but motivates many reductionist theses and associated scientific research programs. Thus, epistemological and ontological claims about reductionism have the methodological implication that they should govern and guide scientific research. When such research proves to be fruitless over a period of time, the associated reductionist claims themselves become suspect. Although issues connected with reductionism arise in the physical and social sciences, most attention to reductionism in philosophy of science over the last few decades has focused on the biological sciences, especially after the advent of molecular biology made it plausible to believe that biological phenomena can be uniformly explained (in detail) from their physical basis.
    [Show full text]
  • A Theory of Conceptual Advance
    A THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL ADVANCE : EXPLAINING CONCEPTUAL CHANGE IN EVOLUTIONARY, MOLECULAR, AND EVOLUTIONARY DEVELOPMENTAL BIOLOGY by Ingo Brigandt M.Sc. in Mathematics, University of Konstanz, 1999 M.A. in Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2005 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Faculty of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH FACULTY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Ingo Brigandt It was defended on August 2, 2006 and approved by Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh James G. Lennox Professor of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh Sandra D. Mitchell Professor of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh G¨unter P. Wagner Alison Richard Professor of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, Yale University Dissertation Directors: Anil Gupta Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Paul E. Griffiths ARC Federation Fellow, Professor of Philosophy, University of Queensland ii Copyright c by Ingo Brigandt 2006 iii A THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL ADVANCE : EXPLAINING CONCEPTUAL CHANGE IN EVOLUTIONARY, MOLECULAR, AND EVOLUTIONARY DEVELOPMENTAL BIOLOGY Ingo Brigandt, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Abstract The theory of concepts advanced in the dissertation aims at accounting for a) how a concept makes successful practice possible, and b) how a scientific concept can be subject to rational change in the course of history. Traditional accounts in the philosophy of science have usually studied concepts in terms only of their reference; their concern is to establish a stability of reference in order to address the incommensurability problem.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Thirty Years of Biology & Philosophy: Philosophy of Which
    Thirty years of Biology & Philosophy: Philosophy of which biology? Final draft. To appear in Biology and Philosophy. Thomas Pradeu - ImmunoConcept, CNRS & University of Bordeaux, 146 rue Léo Saignat 33076 Bordeaux, France - Institut d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences et des techniques, CNRS & Panthéon-Sorbonne University, 11 rue du Four 75006, France Email: [email protected] Phone: +33-5-5757-9547 Fax: +33-5-5757-1472 Abstract Which domains of biology do philosophers of biology primarily study? The fact that philosophy of biology has been dominated by an interest for evolutionary biology is widely admitted, but it has not been strictly demonstrated. Here I analyse the topics of all the papers published in Biology & Philosophy, just as the journal celebrates its thirtieth anniversary. I then compare the distribution of biological topics in Biology & Philosophy with that of the scientific journal Proceedings of the National Academy of Science of the USA, focusing on the recent period 2003-2015. This comparison reveals a significant mismatch between the distributions of these topics. I examine plausible explanations for that mismatch. Finally, I argue that many biological topics underrepresented in philosophy of biology raise important philosophical issues and should therefore play a more central role in future philosophy of biology. Keywords Biology & Philosophy; Philosophy of biology; History of philosophy of biology. Acknowledgments I would like to thank Jean Gayon for his inspiring work. In addition, I would like to thank Lynn Chiu, Jean Gayon, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Matt Haber, Philippe Huneman, Maureen O’Malley, Sahotra Sarkar, and two anonymous referees for their comments on previous drafts.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Reduction and Pluralism: Toward an Epistemology of Explanatory Integration in Biology
    Beyond Reduction and Pluralism: Toward an Epistemology of Explanatory Integration in Biology Ingo Brigandt Department of Philosophy University of Alberta 2-40 Assiniboia Hall Edmonton, AB T6G 2E7 Canada Tel: +1 780-492-0623 Fax: +1 780-492-9160 Email: [email protected] Abstract The paper works towards an account of explanatory integration in biology, using as a case study explanations of the evolutionary origin of novelties—a problem requiring the integration of several biological fields and approaches. In contrast to the idea that fields studying lower level phenomena are always more fundamental in explanations, I argue that the particular combination of disciplines and theoretical approaches needed to address a complex biological problem and which among them is explanatorily more fundamental varies with the problem pursued. Solving a complex problem need not require theoretical unification or the stable synthesis of different biological fields, as items of knowledge from traditional disciplines can be related solely for the purposes of a specific problem. Apart from the development of genuine interfield theories, successful integration can be effected by smaller epistemic units (concepts, methods, explanations) being linked. Unification or integration is not an aim in itself, but needed for the aim of solving a particular scientific problem, where the problem’s nature determines the kind of intellectual integration required. TOWARD AN EPISTEMOLOGY OF EXPLANATORY INTEGRATION IN BIOLOGY 2 1 Introduction Explanatory integration as a philosophical issue can be motivated by looking back at recent debates about reductionism in biology—often taking place in a dialectic between reductionism and pluralism. The traditional model about the relation of different scientific disciplines or domains of knowledge was ‘theory reduction’, which construed reduction as a deductive relation between theories conceived of as axiomatic systems including laws.
    [Show full text]
  • Downloaded on 19Th June 2013))
    The Structured Uses of Concepts as Tools Comparing fMRI Experiments that Investigate either Mental Imagery or Hallucinations Eden Tariq Smith ORCID iD: 0000-0003-4058-6619 Doctor of Philosophy September 2018 History and Philosophy of Science School of Historical and Philosophical Studies The University of Melbourne Submitted in total fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Abstract Sensations can occur in the absence of perception and yet be experienced ‘as if’ seen, heard, tasted, or otherwise perceived. Two concepts used to investigate types of these sensory-like mental phenomena (SLMP) are mental imagery and hallucinations. Mental imagery is used as a concept for investigating those SLMP that merely resemble perception in some way. Meanwhile, the concept of hallucinations is used to investigate those SLMP that are, in some sense, compellingly like perception. This may be a difference of degree. Attempts to reliably differentiate between instances of each type of SLMP remain unresolved. Despite this, the concepts of mental imagery and hallucinations are each routinely used independently of the other. These uses are especially interesting in those published accounts of experiments where equivalent findings about the neuroanatomical correlates of SLMP are reported in support of diverging knowledge-claims about the role of SLMP in neurocognitive processes. This practice presents a puzzle. To examine one aspect of this puzzle, I compare the uses of these two scientific concepts in three ways: examining their roles in differentiating between types of SLMP; exploring how their respective historical developments intersect; and analysing their contributions in neuroimaging experiments. In presenting this series of comparative analyses, I will draw on three themes from historical, philosophical, and social studies of scientific practices: interest in material contributions to knowledge; accounts of how concepts are used in experiments; and explorations of the historical conditions within which current practices emerge.
    [Show full text]