Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, Spi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, Spi

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, Spi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, Spi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics Alexis Burgess, Herman Cappelen, and David Plunkett 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © the several contributors 2020 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2020 Impression: 1 Some rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, for commercial purposes, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. This is an open access publication, available online and distributed under the terms of a Creative Commons Attribution – Non Commercial – No Derivatives 4.0 International licence (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0), a copy of which is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of this licence should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2019946746 ISBN 978–0–19–880185–6 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198801856.003.0001 Printed and bound in Great Britain by Clays Ltd, Elcograf S.p.A. Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials contained in any third party website referenced in this work. OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Contents Note to Readers vii Contributors ix Acknowledgements xi 1. Introduction: A Guided Tour of Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics 1 Herman Cappelen and David Plunkett Abstracts of Chapters 27 2. Revisionary Analysis without Meaning Change (Or, Could Women Be Analytically Oppressed?) 35 Derek Ball 3. Minimal Substantivity 59 Delia Belleri 4. Reactive Concepts: Engineering the Concept C 79 David Braddon-Mitchell 5. Strategic Conceptual Engineering for Epistemic and Social Aims 100 Ingo Brigandt and Esther Rosario 6. Never Say ‘Never Say “Never”’? 125 Alexis Burgess 7. Conceptual Engineering: The Master Argument 132 Herman Cappelen 8. Preliminary Scouting Reports from the Outer Limits of Conceptual Engineering 152 Josh Dever 9. Descriptive vs. Ameliorative Projects: The Role of Normative Considerations 170 E. Díaz-León 10. Variance Theses in Ontology and Metaethics 187 Matti Eklund 11. Neutralism and Conceptual Engineering 205 Patrick Greenough 12. Going On, Not in the Same Way 230 Sally Haslanger 13. The Theory–Theory Approach to Ethics 261 Frank Jackson OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi vi 14. Conceptual Ethics and the Methodology of Normative Inquiry 274 Tristram McPherson and David Plunkett 15. Conceptual Evaluation: Epistemic 304 Alejandro Pérez Carballo 16. Analyzing Concepts and Allocating Referents 333 Philip Pettit 17. The A-project and the B-project 358 Mark Richard 18. Talk and Thought 379 Sarah Sawyer 19. Philosophy as the Study of Defective Concepts 396 Kevin Scharp 20. Linguistic Intervention and Transformative Communicative Disruptions 417 Rachel Katharine Sterken 21. A Pragmatic Method for Normative Conceptual Work 435 Amie L. Thomasson Index 459 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Note to Readers No perfect partition of the table of contents emerged in the editing process. This reflects the fact that we have a rich field on our hands, with a variety of cross-cutting themes. The Introduction details many of these. But here we want to offer some brief guidance for readers eager to dig in. (An important proviso: the chapters listed below are obvious places to start; they aren’t meant to imply that no other chapters contain material relevant to the indicated topics.) If you’re coming to the volume unsure about the status or nature of the whole field, you might start with, in addition to the Introduction, the chapters by Braddon- Mitchell, Cappelen, Pérez Carballo, Pettit, Richard, Thomasson, Sawyer, and Scharp. The chapters by Cappelen, Sawyer, Scharp, and Thomasson generally represent a pro-attitude toward the field, while chapters by Ball and Greenough develop some skepticism. The chapters by Burgess, Dever, and Sterken take up various methodological challenges for doing conceptual engineering and conceptual ethics. If you’re coming to the volume with more applied interests, you might consult the chapters by Belleri, Eklund, and Thomasson for work on metaphysics, or the chapters by Brigandt and Rosario, Díaz-León, Haslanger, Jackson, McPherson and Plunkett, and Pettit for work on ethics and social/political philosophy. OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Contributors D B is a Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of St Andrews. D B is a fixed-term Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the University of Vienna. D B-M is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Sydney. I B is Professor in philosophy and Canada Research Chair in philoso- phy of biology at the University of Alberta. A B is an independent philosopher. H C is a Professor of Philosophy at the University of Oslo, and at the University of St Andrews (1/5th time). J D is a Professor of Philosophy at the University of Texas. E. D´-Ló is an Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Barcelona. M E is Professor of Philosophy at Uppsala University. P G is a Senior Lecturer in Logic and Metaphysics at the University of St Andrews. S H is the Ford Professor of Philosophy in the Department of Linguistics and Philosophy at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. F J is Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at the Australian National University, Canberra. T MP is Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Ohio State University. A P´ C is Assistant Professor in Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts, Amherst. P P is L.S. Rockefeller University Professor of Human Values at Princeton University and Distinguished University Professor of Philosophy at the Australian National University, Canberra. D P is Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Dart- mouth College. M R is Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Harvard University. E R is a PhD student in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Alberta. OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi x S S is a Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Sussex. K S is Reader in Philosophy and Director of Arché at the University of St Andrews. R K S is an Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy at the University of Oslo. A L. T is Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Dartmouth College. OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi Acknowledgements Many friends, colleagues, and institutions helped us put this volume together. ConceptLab at the University of Oslo was particularly important: in the spring of 2016, ConceptLab hosted a workshop where many of the papers were presented and discussed. Several of the contributions were also discussed in other events hosted by ConceptLab. We are particularly grateful to Derek Ball, David Braddon-Mitchell, Matti Eklund, Øystein Linnebo, Tristram McPherson, Olav Gjelsvik, Kevin Scharp, Rachel Sterken, Tim Sundell, and Amie Thomasson. We are also grateful to Matthew McKeever for his help throughout the process of putting this volume together, and to Ira Richardson and Max Frye for their help with the index. Finally, we got invaluable help from our editor at OUP, Peter Momtchiloff. OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 17/12/2019, SPi 1 Introduction A Guided Tour of Conceptual Engineering and Conceptual Ethics Herman Cappelen and David Plunkett Introduction In The Will to Power, Nietzsche writes the following: Philosophers ...have trusted in concepts as completely as they have mistrusted the senses: they have not stopped to consider that concepts and words are our inheritance from ages in which thinking was very modest and unclear. ...What dawns on philosophers last of all: they must no longer accept concepts as a gift, nor merely purify and polish them, but first make and create them, present them and make them convincing. Hitherto one has generally trusted one’s concepts as if they were a wonderful dowry from some sort of wonderland: but they are, after all, the inheritance from our most remote, most foolish as well as most intelligent ancestors. ... What is needed above all is an absolute skepticism toward all inherited concepts.¹ Nietzsche here articulates a radical skepticism about all inherited concepts. Philo- sophers should question whether the concepts we have are good enough and should engage in conceptual critique. What emerges, thinks Nietzsche, is the following: we should not just improve the concepts we’ve been given, reforming or “polishing” them in minor ways, but also create new ones—concepts not tainted by the “most foolish of our ancestors”. Even if you think Nietzsche’s claim is more than a bit hyperbolic, you might think some more moderate version of his view is justified. For example: maybe some of the concepts we have inherited are defective, or at least not as good as they could be for our current purposes.
Recommended publications
  • Conceptual Engineering, Truth, and Efficacy
    Conceptual engineering, truth, and efficacy Jennifer Nado Synthese An International Journal for Epistemology, Methodology and Philosophy of Science ISSN 0039-7857 Synthese DOI 10.1007/s11229-019-02096-x 1 23 Your article is protected by copyright and all rights are held exclusively by Springer Nature B.V.. This e-offprint is for personal use only and shall not be self-archived in electronic repositories. If you wish to self-archive your article, please use the accepted manuscript version for posting on your own website. You may further deposit the accepted manuscript version in any repository, provided it is only made publicly available 12 months after official publication or later and provided acknowledgement is given to the original source of publication and a link is inserted to the published article on Springer's website. The link must be accompanied by the following text: "The final publication is available at link.springer.com”. 1 23 Author's personal copy Synthese https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02096-x S.I. : KNOWLEDGE AND JUSTIFICATION, NEW PERSPECTIVES Conceptual engineering, truth, and efficacy Jennifer Nado1 Received: 18 October 2017 / Accepted: 16 January 2019 © Springer Nature B.V. 2019 Abstract Traditional views on philosophical methodology characterize our primary philosoph- ical goal as production of a successful conceptual analysis. The notion of conceptual analysis, however, faces several challenges—from experimental philosophy to more traditional worries such as the paradox of analysis. This paper explores an alternate
    [Show full text]
  • Articles Revisiting the Logical Empiricist Criticisms of Vitalism Bohang Chen1 Abstract
    Revisiting the Logical Empiricist Criticisms of Vitalism Bohang Chen Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science 2019 (7): 1-17 ISSN 2526-2270 www.historiographyofscience.org Belo Horizonte – MG / Brazil © The Author 2019 – This is an open access article Articles Revisiting the Logical Empiricist Criticisms of Vitalism Bohang Chen1 Abstract: Vitalism claims that biological organisms are governed by nonmaterial agents like entelechies. The received view today rejects vitalism by presupposing metaphysical materialism (or physicalism). Metaphysical materialism maintains that the world is ultimately material (or physical), and it, therefore, repudiates the existence of nonmaterial entelechies. However, this marks a shift compared with the arguments against vitalism developed by logical empiricists, who were indifferent to metaphysical issues and were only concerned with logical and empirical matters in the sciences. Logical empiricists rejected the concept of the entelechy (vitalism), because vital laws confirmed by biological phenomena were unavailable; in contrast, they accepted the concept of the atom (materialism), since it constituted physical laws and was therefore associated with verifiable results in modern physics. 1 Keywords: Vitalism; Materialism (or Physicalism); Logical Empiricism; Entelechy; Atom Received: 27 June 2019. Reviewed: 13 October 2019. Accepted: 17 October 2019. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.24117/2526-2270.2019.i7.03 This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. _______________________________________________________________________ Introduction: The Metaphysical Refutation of Vitalism Today most biologists and philosophers understand vitalism as a heretical doctrine in the history of biology, originally proposed by Hans Driesch in the early twentieth century. 2 According to Driesch’s doctrine of vitalism, biological organisms are governed by nonmaterial vital agents termed entelechies (Driesch 1929; Churchill 1969; Allen 2008).
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism in Biology
    pdf version of the entry Reductionism in Biology http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/reduction-biology/ Reductionism in Biology from the Summer 2012 Edition of the First published Tue May 27, 2008; substantive revision Mon Apr 30, 2012 Stanford Encyclopedia Reductionism encompasses a set of ontological, epistemological, and methodological claims about the relations between different scientific of Philosophy domains. The basic question of reduction is whether the properties, concepts, explanations, or methods from one scientific domain (typically at higher levels of organization) can be deduced from or explained by the properties, concepts, explanations, or methods from another domain of science (typically one about lower levels of organization). Reduction is Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen John Perry germane to a variety of issues in philosophy of science, including the Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor structure of scientific theories, the relations between different scientific Editorial Board disciplines, the nature of explanation, the diversity of methodology, and http://plato.stanford.edu/board.html the very idea of theoretical progress, as well as to numerous topics in Library of Congress Catalog Data metaphysics and philosophy of mind, such as emergence, mereology, and ISSN: 1095-5054 supervenience. Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem- In recent philosophy of biology (1970s to the 1990s), the primary debate bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized about reduction has focused on the question of whether and in what sense distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the classical genetics can be reduced to molecular biology.
    [Show full text]
  • What Can the Philosophy of Biology Learn from the History of Biology?
    What can the Philosophy of Biology learn from the History of Biology? 19‐20 March 2016, Utrecht University (Sweelinckzaal, Drift 21), The Netherlands Questions about the interrelation between the history of science and the philosophy of science have received renewed attention in recent years. This workshop focuses on the life sciences and asks how we might employ historical findings and approaches in order to shed light on questions in the philosophy of biology. The workshop aims to take stock of previous work in this domain, to highlight current lines of research, and to identify challenges and opportunities for the future. This is the first Utrecht Workshop in Philosophy of the Life Sciences. It is hosted by the Descartes Centre for the History and Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities. 19 March 9.30‐10.30 Sabina Leonelli (Exeter) The Epistemology of Data‐Intensive Science: Integrating History, Philosophy and Social Studies of Data Practices 10.30‐11.30 Bert Theunissen (Utrecht) The role of genetics theory in animal breeding 11.30‐12.00 Coffee 12.00‐13.00 William Bechtel (San Diego) What can the history of biology teach philosophy about representing biological knowledge? 13.00‐14.00 Lunch 14.00‐15.00 Ingo Brigandt (Alberta) Research on developmental constraints in the 1980s, and its relevance to current work on evolvability 15.00‐16.00 Raphael Scholl (Cambridge) Rethinking the relationship between history and philosophy of biology 16.00‐17.00 Plenary Discussion 17.00 End 20 March 9.30‐10.30 Joeri Witteveen (Utrecht) Rethinking ‘population thinking’ 10.30‐11.30 Kärin Nickelsen (Munich) Research fields and research collectives: The case of photosynthesis studies, 1930s‐1950s 11.30‐12.00 Coffee 12.00‐13.00 Sahotra Sarkar (Austin) Reductionism in the Philosophy of Biology: What a Little History Does to the Debates 13.00‐14.00 Lunch 14.00‐15.00 Plenary Discussion 15.00 End of Workshop The event is free and open to all.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae of Ingo Brigandt
    Curriculum Vitae Ingo Brigandt Department of Philosophy Email: [email protected] University of Alberta Phone: +1 780-492-9030 2-40 Assiniboia Hall Webpage: http://www.ualberta.ca/~brigandt Edmonton, AB T6G 2E7 Canada Citizenship: Canadian and German citizen AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Philosophy of Biology, Feminist Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mind AREAS OF COMPETENCE Philosophy of Science, Socially Relevant Philosophy of Science, Bioethics, Philosophy of Language, Epistemology, History of Biology, Science Education ACADEMIC POSITIONS 07/2017 – Professor of Philosophy, University of Alberta 07/2015 – 06/2021 Associate Chair (Graduate Studies), Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta (on leave from July to December 2019) 04/2014 – 03/2024 Canada Research Chair in Philosophy of Biology, University of Alberta 08/2019 – 12/2019 Visiting Fellow, Centre for Advanced Study at the Norwegian Academy of Science and Letters, Oslo 2012 – 2017 Associate Professor of Philosophy (with tenure), University of Alberta 03/2015 – 05/2015 Visiting Scholar, Sydney Centre for the Foundations of Science, University of Sydney 09/2014 – 12/2014 Visiting Fellow, Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh 2008 – 2012 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Alberta (hired in 2006, appointment deferred for 2 years to take up a postdoctoral fellowship) 2006 – 2008 Izaak Walton Killam Memorial Postdoctoral Fellow, University of Alberta EDUCATION 2000 – 2006 Ph.D. in History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh
    [Show full text]
  • Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change
    Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change Ingo Brigandt Department of History and Philosophy of Science 1017 Cathedral of Learning University of Pittsburgh Pittsburgh, PA 15260 E-mail: [email protected] To be presented at the 4th Congress of the Spanish Society for Analytic Philosophy Murcia (Spain), 16-18 December 2004 paper: 2997 words abstract: 150 words Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change Abstract The paper discusses concept individuation in the context of scientific concepts and conceptual change in science. It is argued that some concepts can be individuated in different ways. A particular term may be viewed as corresponding to a single concept (which is ascribed to every person from a whole scientific field). But at the same time, we can legitimately individuate in a more fine grained manner, i.e., this term can also be considered as corresponding to two or several concepts (so that each of these concepts is attributed to a smaller group of persons only). The reason is that there are different philosophical and explanatory interests that underlie a particular study of the change of a scientific term. These interests determine how a concept is to be individuated; and as the same term can be subject to different philosophical studies and interests, its content can be individuated in different ways. HOLISM, CONCEPT INDIVIDUATION, AND CONCEPTUAL CHANGE 1 The topic of the present discussion is the individuation of concepts. I am primarily interested in scientific concepts and the phenomenon of conceptual change. My account will be based on a moderate holism about concept, using a conceptual role semantics—an approach that I view as fruitful for studying and explaining conceptual change in science, at least in biology.1 In order to motivate my position, I will briefly look at some recent debates about conceptual role semantics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Levels of Organization in the Biological Sciences
    The Concept of Levels of Organization in the Biological Sciences PhD Thesis Submitted August 2014 Revised June 2015 Daniel Stephen Brooks Department of Philosophy Bielefeld University Reviewers: Martin Carrier, Maria Kronfeldner Dedicated in friendship to Jan and Magga “He who has suffer'd you to impose on him knows you.” Table of Contents Table of Contents........................................................................................................................1 Chapter One: The Intuitive Appeal and Ubiquity of 'Levels of Organization'............................5 1.1 Introduction ................................................................................................................5 1.2 Analyzing 'Levels of Organization' in Biological Science..........................................7 1.2.1 Level Claims.....................................................................................................10 1.2.2 Wimsatt’s Characterization of Levels ..............................................................14 1.3 Initial Distinctions.....................................................................................................16 1.3.1 Erroneous Concepts of Levels...........................................................................18 1.4 Depictions of Levels in Biological Textbooks...........................................................20 1.4.1 The Character of 'Levels' in Biological Science................................................24 1.4.2 The Significance of 'Levels' in Biological Science...........................................30
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism in Biology - Philosophy - Oxford Bibliographies
    Reductionism in Biology - Philosophy - Oxford Bibliographies Reductionism in Biology Sahotra Sarkar, Alan Love, William Wimsatt LAST MODIFIED: 11 JANUARY 2018 DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195396577-0359 Introduction Reductionism concerns a set of ontological and epistemological claims, and methodological strictures based on them, about the relationship between two different scientific domains. The critical assumption is that one of these domains is privileged over the other in the sense that the concepts, rules, laws, and other elements of the privileged domain can be used to specify, constitute, or account for those of the other “reduced” domain. This specification often consists of explanation, such that the “reducing” domain is epistemically privileged over the reduced one. Explanations of this type are “reductionist” (or, are “reductions”) and reductionism is then the thesis that such explanations will always be forthcoming or at least are possible in principle. Reductionism is most plausible if the entities of the reduced domain can be interpreted as arising from (e.g., as aggregates of) entities of the reduced domain. This ontological claim is controversial but motivates many reductionist theses and associated scientific research programs. Thus, epistemological and ontological claims about reductionism have the methodological implication that they should govern and guide scientific research. When such research proves to be fruitless over a period of time, the associated reductionist claims themselves become suspect. Although issues connected with reductionism arise in the physical and social sciences, most attention to reductionism in philosophy of science over the last few decades has focused on the biological sciences, especially after the advent of molecular biology made it plausible to believe that biological phenomena can be uniformly explained (in detail) from their physical basis.
    [Show full text]
  • A Theory of Conceptual Advance
    A THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL ADVANCE : EXPLAINING CONCEPTUAL CHANGE IN EVOLUTIONARY, MOLECULAR, AND EVOLUTIONARY DEVELOPMENTAL BIOLOGY by Ingo Brigandt M.Sc. in Mathematics, University of Konstanz, 1999 M.A. in Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2005 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Faculty of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2006 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH FACULTY OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Ingo Brigandt It was defended on August 2, 2006 and approved by Robert B. Brandom Distinguished Service Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh James G. Lennox Professor of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh Sandra D. Mitchell Professor of History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh G¨unter P. Wagner Alison Richard Professor of Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, Yale University Dissertation Directors: Anil Gupta Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Paul E. Griffiths ARC Federation Fellow, Professor of Philosophy, University of Queensland ii Copyright c by Ingo Brigandt 2006 iii A THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL ADVANCE : EXPLAINING CONCEPTUAL CHANGE IN EVOLUTIONARY, MOLECULAR, AND EVOLUTIONARY DEVELOPMENTAL BIOLOGY Ingo Brigandt, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2006 Abstract The theory of concepts advanced in the dissertation aims at accounting for a) how a concept makes successful practice possible, and b) how a scientific concept can be subject to rational change in the course of history. Traditional accounts in the philosophy of science have usually studied concepts in terms only of their reference; their concern is to establish a stability of reference in order to address the incommensurability problem.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Thirty Years of Biology & Philosophy: Philosophy of Which
    Thirty years of Biology & Philosophy: Philosophy of which biology? Final draft. To appear in Biology and Philosophy. Thomas Pradeu - ImmunoConcept, CNRS & University of Bordeaux, 146 rue Léo Saignat 33076 Bordeaux, France - Institut d’histoire et de philosophie des sciences et des techniques, CNRS & Panthéon-Sorbonne University, 11 rue du Four 75006, France Email: [email protected] Phone: +33-5-5757-9547 Fax: +33-5-5757-1472 Abstract Which domains of biology do philosophers of biology primarily study? The fact that philosophy of biology has been dominated by an interest for evolutionary biology is widely admitted, but it has not been strictly demonstrated. Here I analyse the topics of all the papers published in Biology & Philosophy, just as the journal celebrates its thirtieth anniversary. I then compare the distribution of biological topics in Biology & Philosophy with that of the scientific journal Proceedings of the National Academy of Science of the USA, focusing on the recent period 2003-2015. This comparison reveals a significant mismatch between the distributions of these topics. I examine plausible explanations for that mismatch. Finally, I argue that many biological topics underrepresented in philosophy of biology raise important philosophical issues and should therefore play a more central role in future philosophy of biology. Keywords Biology & Philosophy; Philosophy of biology; History of philosophy of biology. Acknowledgments I would like to thank Jean Gayon for his inspiring work. In addition, I would like to thank Lynn Chiu, Jean Gayon, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Matt Haber, Philippe Huneman, Maureen O’Malley, Sahotra Sarkar, and two anonymous referees for their comments on previous drafts.
    [Show full text]
  • The APA Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy
    2013 The APA GUide To GraduatE ProGrAms in PhilosoPhy University of Delaware Newark, DE 19716 www.apaonline.org All data collected by the American Philosophical Association. The data in this publication have been provided by the departments and programs listed; in the cases where no response was received to repeated requests for information, the most recent data provided, if any, can be found in the previous edition. The APA cannot guarantee the accuracy of this report; because all information has been self- reported, there may be errors or inconsistencies in these data. Readers should therefore examine the available data closely to ensure that any comparisons are made in a fair and reasonable manner. Errors or inconsistencies should be brought to the attention of the American Philosophical Association by email to [email protected]. For clarification, correction, updating, or supplementation of the information provided, contact the department(s) in question. © 2012 The American Philosophical Association This publication of the American Philosophical Association may not be reproduced for sale or future distribution without the express written consent of the executive director. Inquiries should be directed as follows: The American Philosophical Association University of Delaware, 31 Amstel Avenue, Newark, DE 19716 Phone (302) 831-1112 • Fax (302) 831-8690 [email protected] Last updated February 3, 2013 About the Grad Guide The Guide to Graduate Programs in Philosophy, originally published biennially until the early 2000s, was relaunched in 2012 as an annual online resource. The guide compiles data on both doctoral and master’s degree programs in philosophy at institutions throughout the US and Canada, offering prospective students, job candidates, and other members of the profession a rich resource on post- graduate education and employment in philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Reduction and Pluralism: Toward an Epistemology of Explanatory Integration in Biology
    Beyond Reduction and Pluralism: Toward an Epistemology of Explanatory Integration in Biology Ingo Brigandt Department of Philosophy University of Alberta 2-40 Assiniboia Hall Edmonton, AB T6G 2E7 Canada Tel: +1 780-492-0623 Fax: +1 780-492-9160 Email: [email protected] Abstract The paper works towards an account of explanatory integration in biology, using as a case study explanations of the evolutionary origin of novelties—a problem requiring the integration of several biological fields and approaches. In contrast to the idea that fields studying lower level phenomena are always more fundamental in explanations, I argue that the particular combination of disciplines and theoretical approaches needed to address a complex biological problem and which among them is explanatorily more fundamental varies with the problem pursued. Solving a complex problem need not require theoretical unification or the stable synthesis of different biological fields, as items of knowledge from traditional disciplines can be related solely for the purposes of a specific problem. Apart from the development of genuine interfield theories, successful integration can be effected by smaller epistemic units (concepts, methods, explanations) being linked. Unification or integration is not an aim in itself, but needed for the aim of solving a particular scientific problem, where the problem’s nature determines the kind of intellectual integration required. TOWARD AN EPISTEMOLOGY OF EXPLANATORY INTEGRATION IN BIOLOGY 2 1 Introduction Explanatory integration as a philosophical issue can be motivated by looking back at recent debates about reductionism in biology—often taking place in a dialectic between reductionism and pluralism. The traditional model about the relation of different scientific disciplines or domains of knowledge was ‘theory reduction’, which construed reduction as a deductive relation between theories conceived of as axiomatic systems including laws.
    [Show full text]