Irony and Accessibility the Death of Socrates and the Life of Philosophy: an Interpretation of Plato's Phaedo by Peter J

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Irony and Accessibility the Death of Socrates and the Life of Philosophy: an Interpretation of Plato's Phaedo by Peter J Irony and Accessibility The Death of Socrates and the Life of Philosophy: An Interpretation of Plato's Phaedo by Peter J. Ahrensdorf The War Lover: A Study of Plato's Republic by Leon Harold Craig Plato's World: Man's Place in the Cosmos by Joseph Cropsey Review by: David Roochnik Source: Political Theory, Vol. 25, No. 6 (Dec., 1997), pp. 869-885 Published by: Sage Publications, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/191963 Accessed: 20-08-2014 17:09 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Sage Publications, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Political Theory. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Wed, 20 Aug 2014 17:09:55 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions REVIEW ESSAY IRONY AND ACCESSIBILITY THE DEATH OF SOCRATESAND THE LIFE OF PHILOSOPHY:AN INTERPRETATIONOF PLATO'SPHAEDO by PeterJ. Ahrensdorf.Albany: State University of New YorkPress, 1995. 238 + x pp. THE WARLOVER: A STUDY OF PLATO'SREPUBLIC by Leon Harold Craig. Toronto:University of TorontoPress, 1994. 439 + xxxviii pp. PLATO'SWORLD: MAN'S PLACE IN THE COSMOSby Joseph Cropsey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995. 227 + x pp. During the fall semester of 1995, I taught Plato's Republic to a class of freshmen.The next spring,I workedthrough it with graduatestudents. These autobiographicaldetails are worthnoting because even if what they reportis common, it is nonethelessstartling: Plato's greatestdialogue can be success- fully taught both to beginners and to sophisticatedstudents. The Republic, whose philosophicalrichness and complexity are undeniable,is nonetheless uniquely accessible. Althoughbefuddled by, say, the divided line, the begin- ning student can still read the dialogue with pleasure and profit. With the possible exceptionof sectionsfrom Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, the same cannot be said for other philosophicalmasterworks. The severe difficulties of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason, Hegel's Phenomenology,or Wittgen- stein's Tractatuslie forbiddinglyon the surface.By contrast,the surface of the Republic, as is true of so many Platonicdialogues, is welcoming.1 Plato himself, throughhis characterSocrates, may well addressthe source of this phenomenon.In his famous diatribeagainst writing in the Phaedrus, Socrates says this: Writing,Phaedrus, has this strangequality, and is very like painting;for the creaturesof paintingstand like living beings, but if one asks them a question,they preservea solemn silence. And so it is with writtenwords (logoi); you might thinkthey spoke as if they had intelligence, but if you questionthem, wishing to know abouttheir sayings, they always POLITICALTHEORY, Vol. 25 No. 6, December 1997 869-885 ? 1997 Sage Publications,Inc. 869 This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Wed, 20 Aug 2014 17:09:55 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 870 POLITICALTHEORY / December 1997 say only one and the same thing. And every word, when once it is written,is bandied aboutalike amongthose who understandand those for whom it is not fittingand it knows not to whom to speak or not to speak. (275d-e)2 As opposed to the "living, breathing"(276a) words of a speakinghuman being who stands before and hence can direct an appropriatelycrafted message to a particularaudience, a writtenwork indiscriminatelyputs forth the same words to every reader. An inference is obvious: since this critique of writing is itself written, Platonicdialogues must have been conceived with an eye to overcomingthis very deficiency. Plato strove, in other words, to make his writing able to discriminateamong its readers(i.e., to know to whom to speak and to whom to be silent).3The dialoguesare multilayered, and this is one reasonwhy they are able to address,for example, both freshmenand graduatestudents. But how exactly do they accomplish this? A widely accepted answer would be Socraticirony. Simply put, Socratesdoes not say exactly what he means. Instead,cognizant of what his interlocutorcan comprehend,Socrates says different things to different people. If the interlocutoris not able to follow a complex line of thinking, then Socrates may address him in an appropriatelycomprehensible manner. To the grief-strickenand manifestly unphilosophicalCrito, for example,Socrates may well withholdhis complex thoughts about the relationshipbetween positive law and justice itself and instead simply encourage his friend to obey the rulings of the Athenians. Socrates may argue thus even if such a straightforwardstatement does not adequatelyexpress his own far more subtle position. If this is the case, and if such ironic withholdingis characteristicof the dialogues themselves, then a possible answer(or at least the beginningof one) would be suppliedto the question of how a philosophical work as the Republic becomes uniquely accessible. Probablyno moderncommentator has made irony and the multiplelayers of Platonic writing more central to a reading of the dialogues than Leo Strauss.In The Cityand Man, he begins his well-knownchapter, "On Plato's Republic,"with an analysis of Phaedrus 275 and concludes, "The Platonic dialogue, if properlyread, reveals itself to possess the flexibility or adapt- ability of oral communication."The dialogue, Strauss continues, "says differentthings to differentpeople-not accidentally,as every writingdoes, but thatit is so contrivedas to say differentthings to differentpeople, or that it is radicallyironical." From this, Straussinfers that "the properwork of a writingis trulyto talk, or to reveal the truth,to some while leading othersto salutoryopinions."4 This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Wed, 20 Aug 2014 17:09:55 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions REVIEWESSAY 871 The political corollary of such a hermeneuticalposition is readily forth- coming: "Ironyis essentially relatedto the fact that there is a naturalorder of rank among men."5There are those few capable of understandingphilo- sophical difficulties and those many who do better with less than the truth (i.e., with "salutoryopinions"). Freshmen with no inclinationto advance in philosophy may leave a readingof the Crito with the superficialimpression that all forms of civil disobedienceare simply bad. They are therebyencour- aged to obey the law. By contrast,the advancedstudent should be urged to explore what appearsto be a contradictionlying just beneaththe surface of the dialogue.After all, at 46b Socratessays thathe is a manwho obeys nothing but reason. Why, then, does he also say one should always obey the law? Crito does not ask what the properresponse is to a law thatis not reasonable. The elitism implicit in Strauss'shermeneutic presupposes a radical gulf between those capableof miningfor the truthand those in need of superficial opinion. The true teaching of the dialogue is hidden from those who would neitherunderstand nor benefit from it (and who, for reasons to be discussed shortly, would, if exposed to the philosophicalteaching, bring harm to the philosophers). The three books here underreview follow Strauss'slead, for each distin- guishes between a surfaceteaching and a hiddenor buried,a more genuinely Platonic,depth. While each is in its own way helpful, all are finally deficient, and this is precisely because they misconstruethe meaning of the surface- depthrelationship in a Platonicdialogue. These authorsdenigrate the surface by treating it as a philosophically insignificant facade. They disconnect surface from depth and thereby disrupt the structuralcontinuity that, I propose, is the dialogues' most notable achievement. In the course of discussing these books, I offer a proposal that aims to preserve the integrity of the dialogues' surface. Far from being superficial cant, and as opposed to being a screen or a disguise, the surface must be respected as a significant dimension of the philosophical content of the dialogue itself. I do not imply that the Platonic dialogues have no depths to be mined or that,ultimately, such depthsare accessible only to a few. Instead, I hold that the surface of the dialogue is a phenomenon that must be philosophicallypreserved. Even if the surfaceis transfiguredas the result of a philosophicalinterpretation of the dialogueas a whole, such transfiguration must be conceived as anAufhebung, a dialecticalsublation that does not only simply negate but also preserveswhat is being negatedby elevating it. My proposal also has a political correlate.The sensibility suggested by what I offer should perhapsbe describedas more "liberal"or "democratic" This content downloaded from 128.197.26.12 on Wed, 20 Aug 2014 17:09:55 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 872 POLITICALTHEORY / December 1997 than that implicit in the books here underreview, for I insist that beginning readers, ordinarycitizens, must be invited to read furtherand to enter the projectof philosophy.In otherwords, the commentatormust assume thatthe superficialreader can be taught,and such teachingshould begin with a clear articulationof the surface.This surfacedepicts characters, deeds, places, and times, as
Recommended publications
  • Emily Wilson's the Death of Socrates
    Wilson, Emily. The Death of Socrates. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2007. Socrates would be an important figure in the history of philosophy even if all we knew about him was what Aristotle tells us: “[H]e occupied himself with ethics even though he said nothing about the universe, but in the course of his activities he searched for the general (to katholou) and was the first to understand about the concept of boundaries (horismn)” (Metaphysics 987b.1-4). Poets and thinkers before him had thought about ethics. But what made Socrates different is that he was able to devise a process for discovering it that caused him to move away from particulars to general definitions. Without that significant step forward in thought, Plato could never have devised his theory of forms, and Aristotle could not have written his treatises on ethics. But it is not because of his thinking that Socrates has been remembered, as Emily Wilson demonstrates in her lively and entertaining book. Rather, Socrates has remained an inspiration to politicians, thinkers, and artists for more than two millennia because of his death. If he had not died as he did, we would be talking about pre-Platonic rather than pre-Socratic philosophers. But as Plato describes him in the Apology and the Crito, Socrates did nothing to stop himself from being executed. He did not try to flatter and appease the jury. When given an opportunity to propose an alternative punishment, he offered only the trivial sum of one mina. His friend Crito devised a plan that would have allowed him to escape from prison and live the rest of his life in exile, but Socrates again refused to cooperate.
    [Show full text]
  • The Minotaur in Phaedo's Labyrinth: Philosophy's Necessary Myth
    Trinity College Trinity College Digital Repository Trinity Publications (Newspapers, Yearbooks, The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) Catalogs, etc.) 2016 The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth Gregory Convertito Trinity College, Hartford Connecticut Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Convertito, Gregory, "The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth". The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) (2016). Trinity College Digital Repository, Hartford, CT. https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers/43 The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth Gregory Convertito Plato’s Phaedo is a confusing dialogue. It takes place after the Apology and the Crito, on Socrates’s last night before his execution; Socrates has been waiting in prison for a long time due to an Athenian law barring executions during the annual ritual to celebrate Theseus’s mythical victory over the Minotaur. This story of the death of Socrates is embedded in a narration by Phaedo himself, who is relating the story to Echecrates. Socrates, after discussing the soul, the self, immortality, and death with Simmias and Cebes, Pythagorean acquaintances who have come to visit him, drinks the φαρμακον and dies. The myth of the Minotaur—a monster which has the body of a man and the head of a bull—is explicitly invoked in the text, which structurally mirrors this myth. Each has a monster, fourteen characters, and a thread which leads out of a labyrinth. In the myth, Theseus and the others are taken into the labyrinth wherein the Minotaur resides as tribute, as dictated by the Delphic Oracle, and the princess Ariadne gives Theseus a ball of thread to attach to the entrance, so he may find his way out again.
    [Show full text]
  • The Prosecutors of Socrates and the Political Motive Theory
    Portland State University PDXScholar Dissertations and Theses Dissertations and Theses 2-1981 The prosecutors of Socrates and the political motive theory Thomas Patrick Kelly Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/open_access_etds Part of the Intellectual History Commons, and the Political History Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Kelly, Thomas Patrick, "The prosecutors of Socrates and the political motive theory" (1981). Dissertations and Theses. Paper 2692. https://doi.org/10.15760/etd.2689 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF Thomas Patrick Kelly for the Master of Arts in History presented February 26, 1981. Title: The Prosecutors of Socrates and The Political Motive Theory. APPROVED BY MEMBERS OF THE THESIS CO~rnITTEE: ~~varnos, Cha1rman Charles A. Le Guin Roderlc D1man This thesis presents a critical analysis of the histor- ical roles assigned to the prosecutors of Socrates by modern historians. Ancient sources relating to the trial and the principles involved, and modern renditions, especially those of John Burnet and A. E. Taylor, originators of the theory that the trial of Socrates was politically motivated, are critically 2 analyzed and examined. The thesis concludes that the political motive theory is not supported by the evidence on which it relies. THE PROSECUTORS OF SOCRATES AND THE POLITICAL MOTIVE THEORY by THOMAS PATRICK KELLY A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS in HISTORY Portland State University 1981 TO THE OFFICE OF GRADUATE STUDIES AND RESEARCH: The members of the Committee approve the thesis of Thomas Patrick Kelly presented February 26, 1981.
    [Show full text]
  • The Trial of Socrates 399 BCE
    The Trial of Socrates 399 BCE 2 WHY? The trial and execution of Socrates in Athens in 399 B.C.E. puzzles historians What did Socrates say or do that prompted a jury to send a seventy- year-old philosopher to his death? Finding an answer is complicated by the two surviving accounts of the defense They were written by Socrates disciples, Plato and Xenophon Their accounts probably were trying to show their master in a favorable light They failed to present the most damning evidence against Socrates 3 The decisions to prosecute and ultimately convict Socrates had a lot to do with the turbulent history of Athens in the several years preceding his trial An examination of that history may not provide final answers, but it does provide important clues 4 As a young man, Socrates saw the rise to power of Pericles He brought on the dawning of the "Golden Age of Greece." Pericles--perhaps history's first liberal politician-- acted on his belief that the masses deserved liberty Pericles used the public treasury to promote the arts He pushed a building program designed to demonstrate the glory that was Greece It also ensured full employment and opportunities for the lower classes Pericles rebuilt the Acropolis and constructed the Parthenon 5 Parthenon 6 SOCRATES’ BELIEFS Meanwhile, Socrates developed a set of values and beliefs that would put him at odds with most Athenians 7 Socrates was not a democrat To him, the people should not be self-governing They were like a herd of sheep that needed a wise shepherd He denied that citizens had basic virtue
    [Show full text]
  • Plato Crito (The Death of Socrates)
    1 Plato Crito (The Death of Socrates) Plato (428-347? BCE) was the son of a wealthy Athenian who, as a youth, became one of the followers of the notorious Socrates. Socrates was well-known by his fellow Athenians for his love of oral debate and his penchant for discomfiting those he debated, especially those who claimed to be authorities on moral or political affairs. During the height of its power, Athens had been inundated by many foreigners, a number of whom set themselves up as teachers of the sons of the wealthy. Specifically, they taught the arts of rhetoric and oratory (valuable for becoming a leader in a democracy) and were known as sophists. When the Athenians lost the Peloponnesian war in 404, the so-called “tyranny of the thirty” was established by the Spartans to rule Athens after they departed. However, these aristocrats, who had little love for the Athenian democracy, instituted what might be called a reign of terror, and within a year they were overthrown and the Athenian democracy re-established. Casting about for someone to blame for the catastrophe of the war and the tyranny, the Athenians looked to the hangers-on and followers of Socrates, many of whom, like Plato, were from the upper class and suspected of anti-democratic leanings. So, in 399, Socrates himself was put on trial for disrespecting the gods of the state and leading its youth astray. After mounting a spirited defense, reconstructed by Plato in The Apology, Socrates was found guilty and condemned to execution. His death, as retold by Plato in the Crito, has become famous because he was given a chance to escape (the authorities would have looked the other way) but refused because, as he explained to his attending companions, he had lived his whole life in Athens and had urged his fellow citizens of the democracy to abide by her laws.
    [Show full text]
  • Literary Quarrels
    Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics (1) The Cicala's Song: Plato in the Aetia Benjamin Acosta-Hughes University of Michigan, Ann Arbor Version 1.2 © Benjamin Acosta-Hughes, [email protected] (2) Literary Quarrels Susan Stephens Stanford University Version 1.0 © Susan Stephens Abstract: Scholars have long noted Platonic elements or allusions in Callimachus' poems, particularly in the Aetia prologue and the 13th Iambus that center on poetic composition. Following up on their work, Benjamin Acosta-Hughes and Susan Stephens, in a recent panel at the APA, and in papers that are about to appear in Callimachea II. Atti della seconda giornata di studi su Callimaco (Rome: Herder), have argued not for occasional allusions, but for a much more extensive influence from the Phaedo and Phaedrus in the Aetia prologue (Acosta-Hughes) and the Protagoras, Ion, and Phaedrus in the Iambi (Stephens). These papers are part of a preliminary study to reformulate Callimachus' aesthetic theory. 1 The Cicala's Song: Plato in the Aetia* This paper prefigures a larger study of Callimachus and Plato, a study on which my Stanford colleague Susan Stephens and I have now embarked in our co-authored volume on Callimachus.1 Awareness of Platonic allusion in Callimachus is not new, although its significance has not really been appreciateda close reading of the two authors remains a real desideratum, and it is indeed this need that we hope our work will one day fulfill. The main focal points of the present paper are two passages of Callimachus, and two passages of Plato, that, read together, configure a remarkable intertextual dialogue on poetry, reading, and the inspired voice.
    [Show full text]
  • The Uses and Disadvantages of Socrates *
    Histos () – THE USES AND DISADVANTAGES OF SOCRATES * Abstract : Socrates was and is one of the most influential figures in the history of Western philosophy. Yet it remains an open question just what the real, historical Socrates stood for: he wrote nothing, and none even of our most ancient sources can probably be relied upon to give us anything like an accurate picture of his ideas and methods. As if to fill the gap, successive individual philosophers and philosophical traditions—from Plato to Nietzsche and beyond—construct a range of different Socrateses, to serve either as a model for emulation or as a target of attack. Nevertheless, the single most vivid picture of Socrates is that provided by Plato, who was his immediate philosophical successor, and who gave the character ‘Socrates’ the leading role in the majority of his fictional dia- logues. What is this Socrates like, and does he have any use for us? When I was planning this lecture, I was asked if I needed any audio-visual aids, and I said no. But I decided I would bring along one visual aid: a statu- ette of Socrates, which stands in my study as it used to stand on the desk of J. B. Skemp, a distinguished holder of the Chair of Greek in which I now sit. (Enoch Powell was, I understand, almost another of my predecessors: ap- pointed to the Chair around the outbreak of the war, he joined the army in- stead.) The statue is a modern reproduction of a Roman copy of a Hellenis- tic original, itself partly deriving from a massive literary and philosophical tradition which grew up around Socrates after his execution in Athens in BCE .
    [Show full text]
  • Timeline Jean François Pierre Peyron Socrates in the Arts Rivalry With
    Jean François Pierre Peyron a biography Socrates in the Arts Timeline Jean François Pierre Peyron, a French Neoclassical painter, was born on December 15, 1744, into a prosperous family was not without competition; throughout Socrates (c. 470–399 BCE) was a Greek philosopher who devoted his life to the investigation of proper conduct. in Aix-en-Provence, France. Following his family’s wish, he studied law until his father’s death in 1765. He enrolled his time in Rome, and for several years A native of Athens, his interest in moral philosophy gained him wide recognition and infamy as a questioner of in the Ecole de Dessin at Aix-en-Provence where he learned from history painter and etcher Michel-François afterward, he counted renowned painter everyone and everything. Socrates was an enigmatic figure; he wrote nothing and therefore is known primarily Dandré-Bardon (1700–1783) before entering the Paris atelier of Rococo painter Louis Jean François Lagrenée Jacques-Louis David (1748–1825) as his through the accounts of later classical writers, like his student Plato (428/427—348/347 BCE). Through his 1744 Jean François Pierre (1725–1805) in 1767. From his early student days, Peyron’s work reflected his teachers’ interests in moving away primary rival. In 1782, Peyron returned portrayal in these writings as a man of great integrity, insight, and argumentative skill, Socrates has become Peyron was born on December 15 from lighthearted Rococo subjects to the classical tastes of the seventeenth century. to Paris. Despite the success of his Death renowned for his contributions to the fields of ethics and epistemology (the branch of philosophy concerned in Aix-en Provence, France With his work The Death of Seneca (1773), Peyron won the 1773 Prix de Rome, the French Academy’s Grand of Alcestes (1785) at the Salon of 1785, with the theory of knowledge or what it means to know something) and for laying the foundation of Western Prize for art students wherein winners were given a scholarship to study in Rome.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates' Understanding of His Trial: the Political Presentation of Philosophy
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by eScholarship@BC Socrates' Understanding of his Trial: The Political Presentation of Philosophy Author: Kazutaka Kondo Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3926 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2011 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Political Science SOCRATES’ UNDERSTANDING OF HIS TRIAL: THE POLITICAL PRESENTATION OF PHILOSOPHY a dissertation by KAZUTAKA KONDO submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 2011 © copyright by KAZUTAKA KONDO 2011 Abstract Socrates’ Understanding of his Trial: The Political Presentation of Philosophy Kazutaka Kondo Dissertation Advisor: Robert C. Bartlett This dissertation investigates how Socrates understands his trial. It is a well-known fact that Socrates is accused of impiety and corruption of the young and is subsequently executed. Unlike an ordinary defendant who is supposed to make every effort to be acquitted, Socrates, behaving provocatively, seems even to induce the death penalty. By reading Plato’s and Xenophon’s works, this dissertation clarifies his thoughts on the trial that must be the basis of his conduct and explains how he achieves his aim. To deal with Socrates’ view of the trial as a whole, this study examines three questions. First, does he believe in his own innocence? I argue that before and even at the trial, Socrates does not intend to prove his innocence effectively.
    [Show full text]
  • MOCT TRIAL: Socrates You Have Recently Read About the Greek Philosopher That Have Contributed to Both Greece and the World’S Development in Thought
    9H World History Name: ______________________ Role: __________________ MOCT TRIAL: Socrates You have recently read about the Greek philosopher that have contributed to both Greece and the world’s development in thought. What we will be engaging in now is a mock trial for Socrates. We know that he was found guilty of the charges set against him and executed, but did it have to happen that way? Let’s see if your carrying out of this trial could produce a different outcome…. You will have time today to work on preparation and hopefully start the trial today. The Roles Explaining this part is key to any debate, project, or mock trial. The Jury - During the trial, the jury fills out the Jury Sheet and at the end, deliberates. - You will be graded based on the notes that you take during the trial, and your participation in the deliberations afterwards. - The most important part of the jury is that you can only use information brought out during the trial. This is hard because of the work you did prior to the trial. That gives you background to know what's true and what's not, but if the Prosecution or Defense doesn't bring out an important fact, then the jury can't either. The Prosecution - Meletus - Lycon - Anytus - Prosecution Lawyer - The Prosecution must prove that Socrates beyond a reasonable doubt is guilty of the two charges against him. They do this through: opening and closing statements and witnesses (it's a trial). It is not so important that the witnesses know their character's entire life story.
    [Show full text]
  • Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols
    Friedrich Nietzsche Twilight of t he Idols Translated by Richard Polt Introduction by Tracy Strong Twilight-00Book Page i Monday, August 24, 2009 4:52 PM Twilight of the Idols Black process 45.0° 133.0 LPI Twilight-00Book Page iii Monday, August 24, 2009 4:52 PM FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE Twilight of the Idols Or, How to Philosophize with the Hammer Translated by Richard Polt Introduction by Tracy Strong Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. Indianapolis/Cambridge Black process 45.0° 133.0 LPI Friedrich Nietzsche: 1844–1900 Twilight of the Idols was first published in 1889. Copyright © 1997 by Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. All Rights Reserved Cover Design by Listenberger Design & Associates Interior Design by Dan Kirklin Printed in the United States of America 4 5 6 7 10 09 For further information, please address Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. P. O. Box 44937 Indianapolis, Indiana 46244–0937 www.hackettpublishing.com Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, 1844–1900. [Götzendämmerung. English] Twilight of the idols, or, How to philosophize with the hammer/ [by Friedrich Nietzsche]; translated by Richard Polt; introduction by Tracy Strong. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-87220-355-7 ISBN 0-87220-354-9 (pbk.) 1. Philosophy. I. Title. B3313.G6713 1997 193—dc21 96-40331 CIP ISBN-13: 978-0-87220-355-6 (cloth) ISBN-13: 978-0-87220-354-9 (pbk.) Adobe PDF ebook ISBN: 978-1-60384-880-0 Twilight-00Book Page v Monday, August 24, 2009 4:52 PM Contents Introduction by Tracy Strong............................................................. vii Bibliography on Nietzsche..............................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Daimonion of Socrates: a Search for Definition and an Epistemological Assessment
    THE DAIMONION OF SOCRATES: A SEARCH FOR DEFINITION AND AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL ASSESSMENT by ALTON R. POPE B.M.E. , Cornell University, 1951 S.T.B. , Boston University, 1957 A MASTER'S THESIS submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree MASTER OF ARTS Department of Philosophy KANSAS STATE UNIVERSITY Manhattan, Kansas 1969 Approved by: Major Professor TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter Page I. INTRODUCTION 1 PART I. NECESSARY BACKGROUNDS II. THE RELIGIOUS INHERITANCE OF FIFTH CENTURY GREECE 14 Gods and Daimons, and Their Relation to Human Beings Popular Religious Practices Grammatical Considerations III. SOCRATES: THE MAN AND HIS MISSION 27 His Mission Personal Characteristics and Behavior His Beliefs His Trial and Death PART II. THE DAIMONION OF SOCRATES IV. THE DAIMONION IN PLATO 82 The Eight Dialogs The Effect of Plato's Own Views V. THE DAIMONION IN XENOPHON AND OTHER PRIMARY SOURCES 115 The Daimonion in Xenophon Other Contemporary Sources: Aristophanes and Aeschines Noncontemporary Sources: Cicero and Plutarch VI. DEVELOPMENT BY EARLY PHILOSOPHERS AND PLATONISTS 139 Cicero Plutarch Apuleius Proclus Summary ii iii Chapter Page VII. COMMENTARY BY MODERN PHILOSOPHERS 159 Descartes Hegel Nietzsche Kierkegaard Others VIII. INTERPRETATION BY MODERN SOCRATIC SCHOLARS . 184 Naive Interpretations The Voice of Reason The Voice of the Sub-conscious The Voice of God The Daimonion in Psychology IX. THE DEFINITION OF SOCRATES' DAIMONION .... 233 Limitations of Socrates' Own Definition Review and Evaluation of Others' Definitions A Definition of the Daimonion PART III. AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL ASSESSMENT X. SOCRATES' EXPERIENCE OF THE DAIMONION .... 266 Experience of the Daimonion: Parapsy- chological and Religious Similar Experiences of Others Pragmatic Evaluation Theoretical Evaluation XI.
    [Show full text]