Socrates' Understanding of His Trial: the Political Presentation of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Socrates' Understanding of His Trial: the Political Presentation of Philosophy View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by eScholarship@BC Socrates' Understanding of his Trial: The Political Presentation of Philosophy Author: Kazutaka Kondo Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3926 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2011 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Political Science SOCRATES’ UNDERSTANDING OF HIS TRIAL: THE POLITICAL PRESENTATION OF PHILOSOPHY a dissertation by KAZUTAKA KONDO submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy August 2011 © copyright by KAZUTAKA KONDO 2011 Abstract Socrates’ Understanding of his Trial: The Political Presentation of Philosophy Kazutaka Kondo Dissertation Advisor: Robert C. Bartlett This dissertation investigates how Socrates understands his trial. It is a well-known fact that Socrates is accused of impiety and corruption of the young and is subsequently executed. Unlike an ordinary defendant who is supposed to make every effort to be acquitted, Socrates, behaving provocatively, seems even to induce the death penalty. By reading Plato’s and Xenophon’s works, this dissertation clarifies his thoughts on the trial that must be the basis of his conduct and explains how he achieves his aim. To deal with Socrates’ view of the trial as a whole, this study examines three questions. First, does he believe in his own innocence? I argue that before and even at the trial, Socrates does not intend to prove his innocence effectively. He does not reveal his belief clearly, but at least it is clear that to be acquitted is not his primary purpose. Second, what does Socrates want to achieve at the trial? Socrates’ primary purpose is to demonstrate his virtue in public. His speech that provocatively emphasizes his excellence as a benefactor of the city enables him to be convicted as a wise and noble man rather than as an impious corrupter of the young. Third, why does he refuse to escape from jail? I argue that by introducing the speech that defends the laws of the city, Socrates makes himself appear to be a supremely law-abiding citizen who is executed even when escape is possible. This study maintains that Socrates vindicates his philosophy before the ordinary people of Athens by making a strong impression of his moral excellence and utility to others. His presentation of philosophy makes it possible that being convicted and executed are compatible with appearing virtuous and being respected. Socrates promotes his posthumous reputation as a great philosopher, and thus secures the life of philosophy after his death by mitigating the popular hostility against him and philosophy as such. Socrates’ understanding of his trial leads us to his idea of the nature of philosophy and the city, and of their ideal relationship. This dissertation is therefore an introduction to Socratic political philosophy. Table of Contents Acknowledgments page iii Introduction 1 PART ONE: SOCRATES’ UNDERSTANDING OF THE INDICTMENT Chapter 1: Plato’s Gorgias (521a-522e) 8 Chapter 2: Plato’s Euthyphro (2a-3e) 17 Chapter 3: Plato’s Apology of Socrates (24b-28b) 27 The Altered Indictment (24b-c) 27 The Corruption Charge (24c-26b) 29 The Impiety Charge (26b-28a) 35 Conclusion 44 PART TWO: SOCRATES’ ACHIEVEMENT AT THE TRIAL Chapter 4: Xenophon’s Apology of Socrates to the Jury 46 The Purpose of Xenophon’s Work (1) 46 Conversation with Hermogenes before the Trial (2-9) 51 Socrates’ Conduct at the Trial (10-23) 61 Socrates’ Remarks after the Judgment (24-26) 73 Incidents after the Trial (27-31) 77 Conclusion (32-34) 78 Chapter 5: Plato’s Apology of Socrates 81 The First Speech (17a-28b) 82 Prooemium (17a-18a) 82 Prothesis (18a-19a) 86 Defense against the First Accusers (19a-24b) 91 Defense against the Later Accusers (24b-28b) 109 Digression (28b-34b) 121 Epilogue (34b-35d) 150 The Second Speech (35e-38b) 155 The Third Speech (38c-42a) 167 Conclusion 179 i PART THREE: SOCRATES’ REFUSAL TO ESCAPE Chapter 6: Plato’s Crito 184 Opening Scene (43a-44b) 185 Crito’s Persuasion (44b-46a) 191 Socrates’ Principles (46b-50a) 196 The Speech of the Laws (50a- 54d) 207 Conclusion (54d-e) 224 Conclusion 228 Bibliography 235 ii Acknowledgments I am grateful to the Department of Political Science at Boston College. The faculty provided great courses that broadened my insights on political science in general. Its financial support enabled me to accomplish my graduate study, and the Ernest Fortin Memorial Foundation summer grant gave me an opportunity to develop my Greek at University of California, Berkeley. I wish to thank the four members of the dissertation committee. Robert C. Bartlett generously read my manuscript and gave me thoughtful comments every week. The pleasant conversation with him motivated me to advance my project. Christopher Kelly offered gentle but radical comments based on his profound knowledge that stimulated my thoughts. Robert Faulkner always encouraged me cheerfully and fairly criticized my work. Charles Ahern from the Department of Classics kindly accepted my request that he join the committee and supported my reading of Greek texts. Susan Shell and Nasser Behnegar have supported my study of political philosophy at Boston College. Shozo Iijima, Hiromi Kai, Amy Nendza, Benjamin Lorch, and Nao Saito read a part of manuscript. Their suggestions and criticism improved my work. Brenna McMahon helped me study Aristotle by reading his Rhetoric with me. Finally, my understanding of classical political philosophy is greatly indebted to the classes of Christopher Bruell and discussion with him. I learned from him what the philosophical spirit is. iii Introduction The central question of this dissertation is this: How does Socrates understand his trial? With this guiding question, this study analyzes Socrates’ conduct based on his view of the trial, and its purpose is to explain his elusive behavior there. The riddle of the trial that our investigation should focus on arises from Socrates’ choice of his conduct. It is a well-known fact that Socrates ends his life as the result of capital punishment. He is accused of corrupting the young and disbelieving in the gods of the city. At the trial he is found guilty, and then in jail he accepts the execution even though he has a chance to escape. This is the way in which he ends his life. Furthermore, it is also a fact that at the trial Socrates does not behave like an ordinary defendant who is supposed to be eager for being acquitted and to proclaim his innocence as persuasively as possible. Indeed, Socrates’ conduct at the trial that leads to the end of his life makes the trial extremely confusing; he seems to fail to prove his innocence, and, moreover, by presenting himself provocatively he even seems to be found guilty intentionally. The trial of Socrates is then not simply an incident in which Socrates is convicted by his fellow citizens, but also a stage on which he intentionally offers a public demonstration of himself in a strange manner. The issue is what Socrates thinks and does. These thoughts and actions cause the result of the trial, conviction and execution. What does he, given his view of the trial, achieve, and what is his true purpose? Answering these questions is the object of our study. This is a study of Socrates’ conduct and understanding as a figure in literature. First, 1 it is a study of the literary Socrates, not of the historical Socrates, since the incidents concerning the trial that we know about are primarily described in the literary works on Socrates written by Plato and Xenophon. As Thomas West says, it is not the historical Socrates, but Socrates in literature who has made history. 1 We then refrain from speculating about what actually happened at the trial as a historical event. Although it is possible that things in Plato and Xenophon actually happened historically, we have no way of confirming it. Second, this is a study of Socrates’ conduct and his reasoning. We then refrain from making our own judgment on whether or not Socrates was rightly executed by the jury in terms of the Athenian laws. For example, we do not vindicate Socrates as an innocent man killed due to the prejudice of the Athenians, nor criticize Socrates as an anti-democrat who deserves the death penalty. For the correctness or incorrectness of the verdict does not explain why Socrates behaves in a certain way. Instead, it is more important that his conduct must be based on his understanding of the incident: his view of the indictment, verdict, the relationship between philosopher and the city, and his duty in the city. One’s conduct is led by thought, and Socrates’ thought can be analyzed by interpreting the writings that have immortalized Socrates. This dissertation, then, focuses on Socrates’ own understanding as the basis of his conduct as described in the works of Plato and Xenophon. This is an appropriate way to approach Socrates at the trial, and to explain his puzzling behavior depicted in selected literature. The final goal of this study is to demonstrate that Socrates does not regard the trial as 1 “I have not entered into the question of what happened at the trial of the ‘historical’ Socrates because that question is unanswerable and, I believe, not very important. What matters for us is Plato’s portrayal of the event, for it is Plato’s Socrates who has truly made history. The Apology of Socrates is above all a philosophic document.
Recommended publications
  • PA 4-H Horse Cloverbud Activity Book B
    PA 4-H Horse Cloverbud Activity Book B Name: Club Name: County: Thank you for helping with the PA 4-H Horse Cloverbud Program! Here are some notes to help you lead this project: The PA 4-H Horse Cloverbud Policy & Safety Guidelines must be followed at all times when using this activity book. Please see your Extension Office or http://extension.psu.edu/4-h/projects/ horses/cloverbud-program/cloverbud-policy-and-guidelines for a copy of the policy and guidelines. Many sections include a variety of activities. At least one activity per section must be completed. There will be three PA 4-H Horse Cloverbud Activity Books. All Cloverbud members in one club or group should complete the same book in the course of one year, regardless of their ages or the length of time they have been members. Ex: This year, all Cloverbud Horse Club members complete Book B. Next year, all members will complete Book C, etc. Currently, this curriculum is available as an electronic publication. Please contact your local Extension Office for printed copies. For additional Cloverbud activities, please refer to our Leader & Educator Resource page located at http://extension.psu.edu/4-h/projects/horses/cloverbud-program/leader-resources. PA 4-H Horse Cloverbud Mission This educational program provides safe, fun, hands-on, developmentally appropriate learning opportunities for 4-H youth ages 5 to 7 years (as of January 1st). Using horses, this program will focus on participation as well as cooperative learning in informal settings. Summary of Differences Between
    [Show full text]
  • Clitophon's Challenge and the Aporia of Socratic Protreptic* Teruo Mishima
    Clitophon’s Challenge and the Aporia of Socratic Protreptic* Teruo Mishima Before I discuss the text in detail, I would like to briefly sketch the main line of arguments in the Clitophon which I am going to take up, just for the sake of anamnēsis of the readers : In the opening scene Socrates speaks to Clitophon in the third person and tells him that he heard from somebody else that Clitophon, in his conversation with Lysias, has criticised Socratic diatribai (pursuits), whereas he has lavishly praised his synousia (association) with Thrasymachus. Taking Socrates’ words as a sort of disguised criticism or complaint, Clitophon answers that the story was only half true, because although he did on the one hand criticise Socrates, he also on the other hand highly praised him. Then, he explains to Socrates why he must take such an ambiguous attitude towards him. In the first half of his speech he focuses on the aspect of Socratic teaching which he admires unreservedly, namely Socrates’ protreptic speech towards virtues. Here he refers to a lot of Socratic dicta which remind us of well known passages in the early dialogues of Plato. By contrast, in the latter half Clitophon explains where his deep frustration with Socrates lies. He says that, being already converted by Socratic protreptic and resolved to pursue virtues, what he expects now from Socrates is “what comes next”, that is a detailed account of the essence of virtues to be acquired and a piece of concrete advice on how to acquire them. But to these - Clitophon complains - neither Socrates’ company nor Socrates himself gives any convincing answer.
    [Show full text]
  • CRATYLUS by Plato Translated by Benjamin Jowett the Project Gutenberg Ebook of Cratylus, by Plato
    CRATYLUS By Plato Translated by Benjamin Jowett The Project Gutenberg EBook of Cratylus, by Plato INTRODUCTION. The Cratylus has always been a source of perplexity to the student of Plato. While in fancy and humour, and perfection of style and metaphysical originality, this dialogue may be ranked with the best of the Platonic writings, there has been an uncertainty about the motive of the piece, which interpreters have hitherto not succeeded in dispelling. We need not suppose that Plato used words in order to conceal his thoughts, or that he would have been unintelligible to an educated contemporary. In the Phaedrus and Euthydemus we also find a difficulty in determining the precise aim of the author. Plato wrote satires in the form of dialogues, and his meaning, like that of other satirical writers, has often slept in the ear of posterity. Two causes may be assigned for this obscurity: 1st, the subtlety and allusiveness of this species of composition; 2nd, the difficulty of reproducing a state of life and literature which has passed away. A satire is unmeaning unless we can place ourselves back among the persons and thoughts of the age in which it was written. Had the treatise of Antisthenes upon words, or the speculations of Cratylus, or some other Heracleitean of the fourth century B.C., on the nature of language been preserved to us; or if we had lived at the time, and been 'rich enough to attend the fifty-drachma course of Prodicus,' we should have understood Plato better, and many points which are now attributed to the extravagance of Socrates' humour would have been found, like the allusions of Aristophanes in the Clouds, to have gone home to the sophists and grammarians of the day.
    [Show full text]
  • ANA MILENA RIBERO 238 Moreland Hall 2550 SW Jefferson Way Corvallis, OR 97331 (541) 737-3613
    ANA MILENA RIBERO 238 Moreland Hall 2550 SW Jefferson Way Corvallis, OR 97331 (541) 737-3613 EDUCATION PhD, Rhetoric, Composition, and the Teaching of English – University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ; May 2016 Dissertation: Citizenship and Undocumented Youth: An Analysis of the Rhetorics of Migrant- rights Activism in Neoliberal Contexts. Committee: Drs. Adela C. Licona (chair), Damián Baca, Maritza Cárdenas, and Victor Villanueva MA, Writing, Rhetoric and Discourse, with distinction – DePaul University, Chicago, IL Concentration in Teaching Writing and Language; June 2009 BS, Journalism – University of Florida, Gainesville, FL Emphasis in magazine journalism; December 2002 RESEARCH & TEACHING INTERESTS Im/migrant rhetorics, border rhetorics, the rhetorics of social movements, the rhetorics of race, Latinx rhetorics, Women of Color feminisms, literacy studies. ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS 2017-2018 Resident Research Fellow, The Center for the Humanities, Oregon State University, Corvallis, OR 2016-current Assistant Professor of Rhetoric and Composition, School of Writing, Literature, and Film, Oregon State University, Corvallis, OR 2016-17 Engaged Scholar in Residence, Center for Latino/a Studies and Engagement, Oregon State University, Corvallis, OR 2013-16 Research Assistant, Writing Program, University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ 2011-16 Graduate Teaching Associate, Department of English, University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ 2010-11 Coordinator, The Collaborative for Multilingual Writing and Research, DePaul University, Chicago, IL 2009-11 Instructor, Department of Writing, Rhetoric and Discourse, DePaul University, Chicago, IL Ribero 2019 1 PUBLICATIONS Journal Articles 2019 And Sonia Arellano. “Advocating Comadrismo: A Feminist Mentoring Approach for Latinas in Rhetoric and Composition.” Peitho: Journal of the Coalition of Feminist Scholars in the History of Rhetoric & Composition.
    [Show full text]
  • A Moderately Ironic Reading of Xenophon's Oeconomicus
    David M. JOHNSON Ischomachus the Model Husband? A Moderately Ironic Reading of Xenophon's Oeconomicus Xenophon's Oeconomicus is usually considered a treatise on household management masquerading as a Socratic dialogue (Pomeroy). But for others the reverse is true (Strauss and the Straussians; see also Mackenzie and Nails in EMC 1985, Too's review of Pomeroy in CR 1995, and the less orthodox Straussian Stevens). How one comes down on this issue will obviously affect one's evaluation of Ischomachus' relationship with his wife, and of Xenophon as a Socratic writer. I argue that the Oeconomicus is both Socratic and economic, both didactic and ironic. Xenophon chose Ischomachus because both his virtues and his vices have much to teach Critobulus, Socrates' immediate interlocutor, and Xenophon's readers. Our Ischomachus is probably the man whose wife went on to become the Chrysilla who would marry and bear a son to her son-in-law Callias, driving her daughter to attempt suicide (Andocides 1.124-127). There may be evidence for this in Oeconomicus itself. Callias would fall for Chrysilla again when she was "an old battleaxe" (Andocides 1.127); Ischomachus promises his wife that she can maintain her status even in old age (Oec. 7.20). The scandals which would beset Chrysilla and her children may shed light on Ischomachus' otherwise odd failure to say much about children to the wife he had married in large part for the sake of children. There are other ironies. Ischomachus hardly shares Socrates' understanding of property as that one knows how to use. Critobulus, in fact, is evidently already rich enough in conventional terms: he needs another sort of help.
    [Show full text]
  • Oikos and Economy: the Greek Legacy in Economic Thought
    Oikos and Economy: The Greek Legacy in Economic Thought GREGORY CAMERON In the study of the history of economic thought, there has been a tendency to take the meaning of the term “economics” for granted. As a consequence, when considering economic thought in ancient Greece, we turn to what the Greeks said about wealth, about money or about interest. This seems relatively straightforward. Problems emerge when we consider that the term “economics” had a different meaning in ancient Greece than it does today. As a rule, we project back onto history what we mean by “economics” and more or less ignore what it meant during the period in question. On one level, there is nothing wrong with this way of proceeding; after all we have no choice, ultimately, but to study the past with the concepts that are at our disposal. But the procedure can have certain drawbacks. The tendency of positive investigations is that they risk overlooking the kinds of transformations that give rise to our own concerns and even what is essential to our own thought and assumptions. The term “economics” has a long and varied history; the following is a brief attempt to turn things on their head and consider the history of economics not from the perspective of the modern notion of economics, but from the perspective of its ancient Greek ancestor and to begin to indicate the non-obvious ways in which the Greek legacy continues to inform even our most recent economies. As such, while brief mention is made of some modern economic historians, the primary focus is on the meaning of PhaenEx 3, no.
    [Show full text]
  • Morgan Horse Bulrush Youth Workbook
    AMHAY Horsemastership Achievement Program Bulrush Level Level 1 Youth Workbook American Morgan Horse Association, Inc. Youth Program 4066 Shelburne Road, Suite 5, Shelburne, VT 05482 (802) 985-4944 www.morganhorse.com Revised 1/16 Purpose The purpose of the AMHAY Horsemastership Program is to instill in young people pride in, enjoyment of, and knowledge about the Morgan horse with the ultimate objective of educating future owners and breeders dedicated to preserving, improving, promoting, and cherishing the Morgan breed. These objectives – incorporating the ideals and skills of horsemastership and management, sportsmanship, responsibility in citizenship, discipline, and competence in leadership – will be pursued through this program. Rules 1. This program is open to AMHAY members, 21 years and under, who are interested in learning more about Morgans and safe horsemanship. 2. The five levels of achievement are: 1) Bulrush, 2) Woodbury, 3) Sherman, 4) Black Hawk, 5) Justin Morgan. 3. Members may work on the badge levels as individuals or in a youth group. The first two levels may be completed with any horse, but third level and above completed with a Morgan horse. Level requirements do not need to be completed at the same time, although you must complete one level before progressing to the next. 4. AMHAY will provide awards to members who pass the Bulrush, Woodbury, Sherman, and Black Hawk levels. Bulrush through Sherman will receive a certificate, pin and a gift certificate for the AMHA Gift Catalog. Members who complete the Black Hawk and Justin Morgan levels will receive a certificate, pin and U.S. Savings Bond. 5.
    [Show full text]
  • Emily Wilson's the Death of Socrates
    Wilson, Emily. The Death of Socrates. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2007. Socrates would be an important figure in the history of philosophy even if all we knew about him was what Aristotle tells us: “[H]e occupied himself with ethics even though he said nothing about the universe, but in the course of his activities he searched for the general (to katholou) and was the first to understand about the concept of boundaries (horismn)” (Metaphysics 987b.1-4). Poets and thinkers before him had thought about ethics. But what made Socrates different is that he was able to devise a process for discovering it that caused him to move away from particulars to general definitions. Without that significant step forward in thought, Plato could never have devised his theory of forms, and Aristotle could not have written his treatises on ethics. But it is not because of his thinking that Socrates has been remembered, as Emily Wilson demonstrates in her lively and entertaining book. Rather, Socrates has remained an inspiration to politicians, thinkers, and artists for more than two millennia because of his death. If he had not died as he did, we would be talking about pre-Platonic rather than pre-Socratic philosophers. But as Plato describes him in the Apology and the Crito, Socrates did nothing to stop himself from being executed. He did not try to flatter and appease the jury. When given an opportunity to propose an alternative punishment, he offered only the trivial sum of one mina. His friend Crito devised a plan that would have allowed him to escape from prison and live the rest of his life in exile, but Socrates again refused to cooperate.
    [Show full text]
  • The Minotaur in Phaedo's Labyrinth: Philosophy's Necessary Myth
    Trinity College Trinity College Digital Repository Trinity Publications (Newspapers, Yearbooks, The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) Catalogs, etc.) 2016 The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth Gregory Convertito Trinity College, Hartford Connecticut Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Convertito, Gregory, "The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth". The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) (2016). Trinity College Digital Repository, Hartford, CT. https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers/43 The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth Gregory Convertito Plato’s Phaedo is a confusing dialogue. It takes place after the Apology and the Crito, on Socrates’s last night before his execution; Socrates has been waiting in prison for a long time due to an Athenian law barring executions during the annual ritual to celebrate Theseus’s mythical victory over the Minotaur. This story of the death of Socrates is embedded in a narration by Phaedo himself, who is relating the story to Echecrates. Socrates, after discussing the soul, the self, immortality, and death with Simmias and Cebes, Pythagorean acquaintances who have come to visit him, drinks the φαρμακον and dies. The myth of the Minotaur—a monster which has the body of a man and the head of a bull—is explicitly invoked in the text, which structurally mirrors this myth. Each has a monster, fourteen characters, and a thread which leads out of a labyrinth. In the myth, Theseus and the others are taken into the labyrinth wherein the Minotaur resides as tribute, as dictated by the Delphic Oracle, and the princess Ariadne gives Theseus a ball of thread to attach to the entrance, so he may find his way out again.
    [Show full text]
  • Agorapicbk-17.Pdf
    Excavations of the Athenian Agora Picture Book No. 17 Prepared by Mabel L. Lang Dedicated to Eugene Vanderpool o American School of Classical Studies at Athens ISBN 87661-617-1 Produced by the Meriden Gravure Company Meriden, Connecticut COVER: Bone figure of Socrates TITLE PAGE: Hemlock SOCRATES IN THE AGORA AMERICAN SCHOOL OF CLASSICAL STUDIES AT ATHENS PRINCETON, NEW JERSEY 1978 ‘Everything combines to make our knowledge of Socrates himself a subject of Socratic irony. The only thing we know definitely about him is that we know nothing.’ -L. Brunschvicg As FAR AS we know Socrates himselfwrote nothing, yet not only were his life and words given dramatic attention in his own time in the Clouds of Ar- istophanes, but they have also become the subject of many others’ writing in the centuries since his death. Fourth-century B.C. writers who had first-hand knowledge of him composed either dialogues in which he was the dominant figure (Plato and Aeschines) or memories of his teaching and activities (Xe- nophon). Later authors down even to the present day have written numerous biographies based on these early sources and considering this most protean of philosophers from every possible point of view except perhaps the topograph- ical one which is attempted here. Instead of putting Socrates in the context of 5th-century B.C. philosophy, politics, ethics or rhetoric, we shall look to find him in the material world and physical surroundings of his favorite stamping- grounds, the Athenian Agora. Just as ‘agora’ in its original sense meant ‘gathering place’ but came in time to mean ‘market place’, so the agora itself was originally a gathering place I.
    [Show full text]
  • A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion
    ABSTRACT Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A., M.A. Mentor: T. Michael Parrish, Ph.D. The trouble with “definitions” is they leave no room for evolution. When a word is concretely defined, it is done so in a particular time and place. Contextual interpretations permit a better understanding of certain heavy words; Atheism as a prime example. In the post-modern world Atheism has become more accepted and popular, especially as a reaction to global terrorism. However, the current definition of Atheism is terribly inaccurate. It cannot be stated properly that pagan Atheism is the same as New Atheism. By interpreting the Atheisms from four stages in the term‟s history a clearer picture of its meaning will come out, hopefully alleviating the stereotypical biases weighed upon it. In the interpretation of the Atheisms from Pagan Antiquity, the Enlightenment, the New Atheist Movement, and the American Judicial and Civil Religious system, a defense of the theory of elastic contextual interpretations, rather than concrete definitions, shall be made. Rejecting the Definitive: A Contextual Examination of Three Historical Stages of Atheism and the Legality of an American Freedom from Religion by Ethan Gjerset Quillen, B.A., M.A. A Thesis Approved by the J.M. Dawson Institute of Church-State Studies ___________________________________ Robyn L. Driskell, Ph.D., Interim Chairperson Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Baylor University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Approved by the Thesis Committee ___________________________________ T.
    [Show full text]
  • The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1946 The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates David J. Bowman Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Bowman, David J., "The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates" (1946). Master's Theses. 61. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/61 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1946 David J. Bowman !HE HISTORICITY OP PLATO'S APOLOGY OF SOCRATES BY DA.VID J. BOWJWf~ S.J• .l. !BESIS SUBMITTED Ilf PARTIAL FULFILIJIE.NT OF THB: R}gQUIRE'IIENTS POR THE DEGREE OF IIA.STER OF ARTS Ill LOYOLA UlfiVERSITY JULY 1946 -VI'fA. David J. Bowman; S.J•• was born in Oak Park, Ill1no1a, on Ma7 20, 1919. Atter b!a eleaentar7 education at Ascension School# in Oak Park, he attended LoJola AcademJ ot Chicago, graduat1DS .from. there in June, 1937. On September 1, 1937# he entered the Sacred Heart Novitiate ot the SocietJ ot Jesus at Milford~ Ohio. Por the tour Jear• he spent there, he was aoademicallJ connected with Xavier Univeraitr, Cincinnati, Ohio. In August ot 1941 he tranaterred to West Baden College o.f Lorol& Universit7, Obicago, and received the degree ot Bachelor o.f Arts with a major in Greek in Deo.aber, 1941.
    [Show full text]