Daimonion of Socrates: a Search for Definition and an Epistemological Assessment

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Daimonion of Socrates: a Search for Definition and an Epistemological Assessment THE DAIMONION OF SOCRATES: A SEARCH FOR DEFINITION AND AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL ASSESSMENT by ALTON R. POPE B.M.E. , Cornell University, 1951 S.T.B. , Boston University, 1957 A MASTER'S THESIS submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree MASTER OF ARTS Department of Philosophy KANSAS STATE UNIVERSITY Manhattan, Kansas 1969 Approved by: Major Professor TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter Page I. INTRODUCTION 1 PART I. NECESSARY BACKGROUNDS II. THE RELIGIOUS INHERITANCE OF FIFTH CENTURY GREECE 14 Gods and Daimons, and Their Relation to Human Beings Popular Religious Practices Grammatical Considerations III. SOCRATES: THE MAN AND HIS MISSION 27 His Mission Personal Characteristics and Behavior His Beliefs His Trial and Death PART II. THE DAIMONION OF SOCRATES IV. THE DAIMONION IN PLATO 82 The Eight Dialogs The Effect of Plato's Own Views V. THE DAIMONION IN XENOPHON AND OTHER PRIMARY SOURCES 115 The Daimonion in Xenophon Other Contemporary Sources: Aristophanes and Aeschines Noncontemporary Sources: Cicero and Plutarch VI. DEVELOPMENT BY EARLY PHILOSOPHERS AND PLATONISTS 139 Cicero Plutarch Apuleius Proclus Summary ii iii Chapter Page VII. COMMENTARY BY MODERN PHILOSOPHERS 159 Descartes Hegel Nietzsche Kierkegaard Others VIII. INTERPRETATION BY MODERN SOCRATIC SCHOLARS . 184 Naive Interpretations The Voice of Reason The Voice of the Sub-conscious The Voice of God The Daimonion in Psychology IX. THE DEFINITION OF SOCRATES' DAIMONION .... 233 Limitations of Socrates' Own Definition Review and Evaluation of Others' Definitions A Definition of the Daimonion PART III. AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL ASSESSMENT X. SOCRATES' EXPERIENCE OF THE DAIMONION .... 266 Experience of the Daimonion: Parapsy- chological and Religious Similar Experiences of Others Pragmatic Evaluation Theoretical Evaluation XI. THE DAIMONION AS A "VOICE OF TRUTH" 313 The Criterion of Truth: Comprehensive Coherence The Truth-Claims of Religious Experience The Truth-Claims of the Daimonion PART IV. CONCLUSION XII. CONCLUSION 360 APPENDIX 366 BIBLIOGRAPHY 370 " "This Socratic daimonion has always been a crux philologorum , a difficulty that has nevertheless operated more enticingly than forbiddingly, and by its mysterious spell even deceptively. Since time immemorial one finds a strong propensity to say something about this thing, but there the matter usually ends. The curiosity which is tickled by whatever is mysterious is satisfied as soon as the thing is given a name, and profundity accepts satisfaction when one says with a thoughtful air: 'Ah, what is one to say? ' Soren Kierkegaard The Concept of Irony , p. 185. iv CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION For more than 2400 years, the Greek philosopher Socrates has been held in high honor as among the world's foremost heroes of thought and action. Countless are the men who have given him their full measure of respect and admiration, and who have rallied around his conviction that "an unexamined life is not worth living," joining him in the effort to understand the meaning and purpose of human existence. There are two impressive observations concerning Socrates that motivate the present discussion. The first of these is the indisputable claim that Socrates was a man com- mitted to the fullest possible use of his reason. This is apparent from even the most superficial examination of his life and teaching, and is often made explicit in his own words. In one of the dialogs of Plato regarded as among those most faith- ful to the historical Socrates, he tells his friend Crito that he is incapable of obeying anything other than the rule of reason: "I am still what I have always been--a man who will accept no argument but that which on reflection I find to be truest.' Later in the same dialog he expressly calls reason 1 2 Plato Apology 38 a. Plato Crito 46 b. his "guide. m1 That Socrates was without question a man of reason receives further support from a trio of eminent Socratic scholars. One refers to his "obstinate rationality." Another cites his obeying "one law only, the oracle of the higher reason in his breast." A third, calling him "a man who was common-sense personified," reflects further that "Socrates paused at every step to interrupt the flow of thought in order to test its depth and purity. Each fresh conception had to deliver its passport in the course of cross-examination; every slumbering doubt was awakened, every hidden contradiction was exposed." If the commitment to a full use of human reason is one sure fact about Socrates, however, there is another fact--if the evidence from primary sources can be trusted- -which is just as certain. Socrates received unquestionably and un- questioningly the guidance of the daimonion. His reliance on the daimonion was well known; he spoke of it often, and in no less than eight dialogs attributed to Plato and three writings X 48 c. 2 A. E. Taylor, Socrates (Garden City, N. Y. : Doubleday Co. , Inc. , 1953), p. 46. 3 Paul Shorey, What Plato Said (Abridged ed. , Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1965), p. 14. 4 Theodor Gomperz, The Greek Thinkers , trans. Laurie Magnus (2 vols. , London: John Murray, iyb4) , II, 89. 5 Ibid. , I, 385. " of Xenophon are there specific references to it. When these two observations are brought together, the resulting picture is of a man dedicated to using his reason and at the same time obeying without question the counsel of his daimonion. "This man, who more than any other proposed to clarify by the power of his intellect what was unclear and ambiguous, recognized mysterious forces which he obeyed without •i examining their claim. What was the daimonion of Socrates? How did it func- tion? What is its significance? And why did the one who was always pressing for understanding and definition, who was forever asking --whether of piety or beauty or friendship or justice- -"What does it mean?", follow unhesitatingly the guidance of the daimonion? Surely it appears inconsistent for the man of reason to be so uncritical of something as nonrational as the sudden warning of the daimonion. If the daimonion constitutes a problem for the student of Socrates, there arises a further problem for the student of philosophy, respecting the epistemological status of Soc- rates' experience of the daimonion and the value and correct- ness of its counsel. Specifically, did the daimonion in its monitions and silences present serious claims to truth; and were those claims in fact true? In the two areas of Socratic studies and epistemology, Paul Friedlander, Plato , trans. Hans Meyerhoff (2 vols., Vol. I, New York: Harper & Row, 1964; Vol. II, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1964), I, 32. 4 the daimonion poses important and enticing questions: (1) What was the daimonion of Socrates, and how did he reconcile his reliance on it with his firm commitment to reason? and (2) What is the verdict of epistemology upon this kind of experience and its claims? The thesis that is here presented answers these questions, in the light of certain important assumptions in the two general areas of Socratic studies and epistemology. On these assumptions the discussion builds, and the conclu- sions reached depend heavily upon them. Within the area of Socratic studies, the first and crucial assumption which is here granted is that Socrates actually experienced a form of inner communication or assurance which was not totally a subjective phenomenon; i.e., there was an objective source for the guidance he received. It may of course be doubted that Socrates really had his daimonion. Plato and Xenophon, the major primary sources, do not establish the fact that Socrates had a daimonion, but only the fact that he spoke as if he did. The only possible evidence for it is the unsupported testimony of Socrates himself, and he may have completely misunderstood-- in the light of his religious inheritance- -what was simply a subjective process within his sub-conscious mind, or even a psychotic manifestation. Clearly, some position must be taken concerning what only Socrates himself experienced, and 5 what even he might not have been able accurately to conceive. The assumption here is that Socrates did experience a real, not an imagined or purely subjective, form of communication. A second assumption in the area of Socratic studies relates both to the veracity of Socrates' statements about the daimonion, and to his honesty in reporting it. It is here granted that Socrates was not wholly mistaken about the daimonion; and further that when he spoke of it, he did so without any intent to dissemble. This last point, which has occasionally been challenged in the Socratic literature, appears reasonable in the light of the "whole" Socrates. It is clear that he was a man of intellectual and moral integrity. For him to pretend to be guided by a daimonion when he was not would be a brand of dishonesty wholly in- consistent with all that is known of him. On occasion, to be sure, he adopted the counterfeit methods of the sophists, but it was for the purpose of showing up the pretensions of men who were trying to pass off cleverness for true wisdom. In general, his life presents the testimony of a man whose word can be trusted, and should be trusted. Neither Ryle nor Winspear, the two contemporary scholars who most severely challenge the accepted Platonic portrait of Socrates, sug- gests that for Socrates to speak of his daimonion was a deliberate falsification or pretense. There is a very serious problem concerning the 6 historical Socrates, and therefore the first major task of this thesis will be to assess the historical data available especially in the dialogs of Plato, with special reference to the daimonion. Subsequent chapters will consider the degree to which the portraits of Socrates by Plato and Xenophon may misrepresent the historical Socrates, but will establish too a consensus on the fact of the daimonion in his experience, and on the broad nature of its effects.
Recommended publications
  • Biology and Philosophy. VII. Sokrates, the Demigod
    https://doi.org/10.31871/WJRR.9.1.9 World Journal of Research and Review (WJRR) ISSN:2455-3956, Volume-9, Issue-1, July 2019 Pages 26-30 Biology and Philosophy. VII. Sokrates, the Demigod Juan S. Gómez-Jeria His diverse pupils, though proclaiming themselves similarly Abstract—I use the cylinder-ladder model presented in the faithful, presented opposing images of him. And in each of previous paper of this series to present and defend the thesis them, legend and history are probably mixed. Some that Sokrates was placed in a step much higher than those that well-known biographic details follow. There is a certain were occupied by almost all mortals regarding the degree of perception of reality and that he could perfectly be situated in possibility that some facts are not exactly as they are told, the category of ‘demigod’ as defined in this paper. Plato´s even that some are just gossip, but that is not important in this Apology is considered the most probable and unique context. Sokratic-like text. Furthermore, I claim that Sokrates knew that he was (relatively) wiser than those around him due to its higher position on the cylinder-ladder. This last statement opens new questions about the response of the Pythia. Sokrates was clear that his discourse would be understood by his listeners accordingly to the place they occupied in the cylinder-ladder model. This is the reason because, after Sokrates death, so many different Socratic schools appeared. Finally, I firmly hold the idea that one day we will discover that our knowledge of Sokrates has not grown one iota since his death.
    [Show full text]
  • The Trial and Death of Socrates : Being the Euthyphron, Apology, Crito, and Phaedo of Plato
    LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SAN DIEGO /?. (Boffcen THE TRIAL & DEATH OF SOCRATES *O 5' dve^Tcurroj /3toj ov /Siwrds cu>0p(j!nrip ' An unexamined life is not worth living.' (PLATO, Apol. 38 A. ) THE TRIAL AND DEATH OF SOCRATES BEING THE EUTHYPHRON, APOLOGY, CRITO, AND PH^EDO OF PLATO TRANSLATED INTO ENGLISH BY F. J. CHURCH, M.A. LONDON MACMILLAN AND CO. AND NEW YORK 1895 [ All rights reserved.] First Edition printed 1880 Second Edition, Golden Treasury Series, 1886 Reprinted 1887, 1888, 1890, 1891, 1892, March and September 1895 PREFACE. THIS book, which is intended principally for the large and increasing class of readers who wish to learn something of the masterpieces of Greek literature, and who cannot easily read them in Greek, was originally published by Messrs. Macmillan in a different form. Since its first appearance it has been revised and corrected throughout, and largely re- written. The chief part of the Introduction is new. It is not intended to be a general essay on Socrates, but only an attempt to explain and illustrate such points in his life and teaching as are referred to in these dialogues, which, taken by themselves, con- tain Plato's description of his great master's life, and work, and death. The books which were most useful to me in writing it are Professor Zeller's Socrates and the Socratic Schools, and the edition of the VI PREFACE. Apology by the late Rev. James Riddell, published after his death by the delegates of the Clarendon Press. His account of Socrates is singularly striking.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Symposium. a Critical Guide
    CJ-Online, 2018.10.03 BOOK REVIEW Plato’s Symposium. A Critical Guide. By PIERRE DESTRÉE and ZINA GIANNOPOU- LOU, eds. Cambridge, UK and New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 2017. Pp. ix + 268. Hardback, $99.99. ISBN 978-1-107-11005-2. estrée and Giannopoulou have provided scholars with thirteen exegeti- cally rich and philosophically sophisticated chapters on Plato’s Sympo- sium, written for the most part by scholars with numerous publications D(in several cases, numerous books) on Plato, classical Greek moral psychology, and ancient Greek philosophy. Many of the chapters warrant discussion at least to the length that I am allotted for my review of the entire volume, which alas I cannot provide here. In lieu of that: First, an overview: Since the editors’ introduction ably summarizes the main insights and methodological approaches of each individual chapter, I will refrain from duplicating such effort and instead offer an overview of the volume’s organ- ization. Running through the volume is a commitment to understanding Plato’s Symposium through the interrelations of the dialogue’s various encomia of Erôs and their anticipations of Diotima’s account. The first two chapters consider the “place-settings,” as it were, to the encomia of Erôs in the Symposium: Zina Gian- nopoulou examines how the dialogue’s outer frame and prologue anticipate as- pects of temporality raised by Diotima’s speech, while Jeremy Reid looks at inter- textual connections between the positive depictions of Erôs in the first three speeches of the Symposium and the account of potential guardians in the Republic.
    [Show full text]
  • EUTHYPHRO and the LOGIC of MIASMA Maureen ECKERT
    EUTHYPHRO AND THE LOGIC OF MIASMA Maureen ECKERT ABSTRACT: Euthyphro is a Socratic interlocutor claiming enormous religious expertise, while his portrayal in the eponymous dialogue raises questions the reliability of his beliefs. This paper closely examines how Euthyphro justifies his case against his father, identifying an argument that relies on the concept of miasma (pollution). In so far as miasma is considered in isolation, Euthyphro has a good argument. Unfortunately, there is more than miasma at stake when considering why one could prosecute one’s own parent. Introducing the other relevant concepts, honor and shame, we find his case reflects a dilemma at the source of ancient Greek religious thought. It would not be possible for Euthyphro or anyone else to know what to do in his case. KEYWORDS: Plato, Euthyphro, Dilemma, Miasma, Pollution This is why even now I go around in accordance with the God, seeking out and investigating both citizens and foreigners, any whom I suppose are wise, and when someone doesn’t seem so to me, I make it clear they are not wise, assisting the god. (Appology 23b)1 Euthyphro is a classic Socratic interlocutor, one who claims expertise in religion and is then shown that he does not know what he claims to know. Plato’s vivid characterization of Euthyphro’s variety of quirks, his claims of superiority, his lack of self-awareness, his susceptibility to Socrates’ mocking flattery, the outrageousness of his case, make it easy to lose sight of any philosophically significant elements contained in his claims. While he exemplifies the type of epistemic hubris Socrates is out to cure, it would be a mistake to write him off ad hominem.
    [Show full text]
  • The Poverty of Socratic Questioning: Asking and Answering in the Meno
    University of Cincinnati University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications Faculty Articles and Other Publications College of Law Faculty Scholarship 1994 The oP verty of Socratic Questioning: Asking and Answering In The eM no Thomas D. Eisele University of Cincinnati College of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.uc.edu/fac_pubs Part of the Legal Education Commons Recommended Citation Eisele, Thomas D., "The oP verty of Socratic Questioning: Asking and Answering In The eM no" (1994). Faculty Articles and Other Publications. Paper 36. http://scholarship.law.uc.edu/fac_pubs/36 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Law Faculty Scholarship at University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Articles and Other Publications by an authorized administrator of University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE POVERTY OF SOCRATIC QUESTIONING: ASKING AND ANSWERING IN THE MEND Thomas D. Eisele* I understand [philosophy 1 as a willingness to think not about some­ thing other than what ordinary human beings think about, but rather to learn to think undistractedly about things that ordinary human beings cannot help thinking about, or anyway cannot help having occur to them, sometimes in fantasy, sometimes asa flash across a landscape; such things, for example, as whether we can know the world as it is in itself, or whether others really know the nature of one's own experiences, or whether good and bad are relative, or whether we might not now be dreaming that we are awake, or whether modern tyrannies and weapons and spaces and speeds and art are continuous with the past of the human race or discontinuous, and hence whether the learning of the human race is not irrelevant to the problems it has brought before itself.
    [Show full text]
  • A Moderately Ironic Reading of Xenophon's Oeconomicus
    David M. JOHNSON Ischomachus the Model Husband? A Moderately Ironic Reading of Xenophon's Oeconomicus Xenophon's Oeconomicus is usually considered a treatise on household management masquerading as a Socratic dialogue (Pomeroy). But for others the reverse is true (Strauss and the Straussians; see also Mackenzie and Nails in EMC 1985, Too's review of Pomeroy in CR 1995, and the less orthodox Straussian Stevens). How one comes down on this issue will obviously affect one's evaluation of Ischomachus' relationship with his wife, and of Xenophon as a Socratic writer. I argue that the Oeconomicus is both Socratic and economic, both didactic and ironic. Xenophon chose Ischomachus because both his virtues and his vices have much to teach Critobulus, Socrates' immediate interlocutor, and Xenophon's readers. Our Ischomachus is probably the man whose wife went on to become the Chrysilla who would marry and bear a son to her son-in-law Callias, driving her daughter to attempt suicide (Andocides 1.124-127). There may be evidence for this in Oeconomicus itself. Callias would fall for Chrysilla again when she was "an old battleaxe" (Andocides 1.127); Ischomachus promises his wife that she can maintain her status even in old age (Oec. 7.20). The scandals which would beset Chrysilla and her children may shed light on Ischomachus' otherwise odd failure to say much about children to the wife he had married in large part for the sake of children. There are other ironies. Ischomachus hardly shares Socrates' understanding of property as that one knows how to use. Critobulus, in fact, is evidently already rich enough in conventional terms: he needs another sort of help.
    [Show full text]
  • Oikos and Economy: the Greek Legacy in Economic Thought
    Oikos and Economy: The Greek Legacy in Economic Thought GREGORY CAMERON In the study of the history of economic thought, there has been a tendency to take the meaning of the term “economics” for granted. As a consequence, when considering economic thought in ancient Greece, we turn to what the Greeks said about wealth, about money or about interest. This seems relatively straightforward. Problems emerge when we consider that the term “economics” had a different meaning in ancient Greece than it does today. As a rule, we project back onto history what we mean by “economics” and more or less ignore what it meant during the period in question. On one level, there is nothing wrong with this way of proceeding; after all we have no choice, ultimately, but to study the past with the concepts that are at our disposal. But the procedure can have certain drawbacks. The tendency of positive investigations is that they risk overlooking the kinds of transformations that give rise to our own concerns and even what is essential to our own thought and assumptions. The term “economics” has a long and varied history; the following is a brief attempt to turn things on their head and consider the history of economics not from the perspective of the modern notion of economics, but from the perspective of its ancient Greek ancestor and to begin to indicate the non-obvious ways in which the Greek legacy continues to inform even our most recent economies. As such, while brief mention is made of some modern economic historians, the primary focus is on the meaning of PhaenEx 3, no.
    [Show full text]
  • Daimonic Imagination
    Daimonic Imagination Daimonic Imagination: Uncanny Intelligence Edited by Angela Voss and William Rowlandson Daimonic Imagination: Uncanny Intelligence, Edited by Angela Voss and William Rowlandson This book first published 2013 Cambridge Scholars Publishing 12 Back Chapman Street, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2XX, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2013 by Angela Voss and William Rowlandson and contributors All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-4438-4726-7, ISBN (13): 978-1-4438-4726-1 TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface and Acknowledgments .................................................................. ix Introduction ................................................................................................. 1 Part I: Daimonic History Chapter One ................................................................................................. 8 When Spirit Possession is Sexual Encounter: The Case for a Cult of Divine Birth in Ancient Greece Marguerite Rigoglioso Chapter Two .............................................................................................. 23 Encounters at the Tomb: Visualizing the Invisible in Attic Vase Painting Diana Rodríguez Pérez Chapter Three ...........................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • From Hades to the Stars: Empedocles on the Cosmic Habitats of Soul', Classical Antiquity, Vol
    Edinburgh Research Explorer From Hades to the stars Citation for published version: Trepanier, S 2017, 'From Hades to the stars: Empedocles on the cosmic habitats of soul', Classical Antiquity, vol. 36, no. 1, pp. 130-182. https://doi.org/10.1525/ca.2017.36.1.130 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1525/ca.2017.36.1.130 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Classical Antiquity Publisher Rights Statement: Published as Trépanier, S. 2017. From Hades to the Stars: Empedocles on the Cosmic Habitats of Soul, Classical Antiquity, Vol. 36 No. 1, April 2017; (pp. 130-182) DOI: 10.1525/ca.2017.36.1.130. © 2017 by the Regents of the University of California. Authorization to copy this content beyond fair use (as specified in Sections 107 and 108 of the U. S. Copyright Law) for internal or personal use, or the internal or personal use of specific clients, is granted by the Regents of the University of California for libraries and other users, provided that they are registered with and pay the specified fee via Rightslink® or directly with the Copyright Clearance Center. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation.
    [Show full text]
  • Emily Wilson's the Death of Socrates
    Wilson, Emily. The Death of Socrates. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2007. Socrates would be an important figure in the history of philosophy even if all we knew about him was what Aristotle tells us: “[H]e occupied himself with ethics even though he said nothing about the universe, but in the course of his activities he searched for the general (to katholou) and was the first to understand about the concept of boundaries (horismn)” (Metaphysics 987b.1-4). Poets and thinkers before him had thought about ethics. But what made Socrates different is that he was able to devise a process for discovering it that caused him to move away from particulars to general definitions. Without that significant step forward in thought, Plato could never have devised his theory of forms, and Aristotle could not have written his treatises on ethics. But it is not because of his thinking that Socrates has been remembered, as Emily Wilson demonstrates in her lively and entertaining book. Rather, Socrates has remained an inspiration to politicians, thinkers, and artists for more than two millennia because of his death. If he had not died as he did, we would be talking about pre-Platonic rather than pre-Socratic philosophers. But as Plato describes him in the Apology and the Crito, Socrates did nothing to stop himself from being executed. He did not try to flatter and appease the jury. When given an opportunity to propose an alternative punishment, he offered only the trivial sum of one mina. His friend Crito devised a plan that would have allowed him to escape from prison and live the rest of his life in exile, but Socrates again refused to cooperate.
    [Show full text]
  • The Minotaur in Phaedo's Labyrinth: Philosophy's Necessary Myth
    Trinity College Trinity College Digital Repository Trinity Publications (Newspapers, Yearbooks, The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) Catalogs, etc.) 2016 The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth Gregory Convertito Trinity College, Hartford Connecticut Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Convertito, Gregory, "The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth". The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) (2016). Trinity College Digital Repository, Hartford, CT. https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers/43 The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth Gregory Convertito Plato’s Phaedo is a confusing dialogue. It takes place after the Apology and the Crito, on Socrates’s last night before his execution; Socrates has been waiting in prison for a long time due to an Athenian law barring executions during the annual ritual to celebrate Theseus’s mythical victory over the Minotaur. This story of the death of Socrates is embedded in a narration by Phaedo himself, who is relating the story to Echecrates. Socrates, after discussing the soul, the self, immortality, and death with Simmias and Cebes, Pythagorean acquaintances who have come to visit him, drinks the φαρμακον and dies. The myth of the Minotaur—a monster which has the body of a man and the head of a bull—is explicitly invoked in the text, which structurally mirrors this myth. Each has a monster, fourteen characters, and a thread which leads out of a labyrinth. In the myth, Theseus and the others are taken into the labyrinth wherein the Minotaur resides as tribute, as dictated by the Delphic Oracle, and the princess Ariadne gives Theseus a ball of thread to attach to the entrance, so he may find his way out again.
    [Show full text]
  • Agorapicbk-17.Pdf
    Excavations of the Athenian Agora Picture Book No. 17 Prepared by Mabel L. Lang Dedicated to Eugene Vanderpool o American School of Classical Studies at Athens ISBN 87661-617-1 Produced by the Meriden Gravure Company Meriden, Connecticut COVER: Bone figure of Socrates TITLE PAGE: Hemlock SOCRATES IN THE AGORA AMERICAN SCHOOL OF CLASSICAL STUDIES AT ATHENS PRINCETON, NEW JERSEY 1978 ‘Everything combines to make our knowledge of Socrates himself a subject of Socratic irony. The only thing we know definitely about him is that we know nothing.’ -L. Brunschvicg As FAR AS we know Socrates himselfwrote nothing, yet not only were his life and words given dramatic attention in his own time in the Clouds of Ar- istophanes, but they have also become the subject of many others’ writing in the centuries since his death. Fourth-century B.C. writers who had first-hand knowledge of him composed either dialogues in which he was the dominant figure (Plato and Aeschines) or memories of his teaching and activities (Xe- nophon). Later authors down even to the present day have written numerous biographies based on these early sources and considering this most protean of philosophers from every possible point of view except perhaps the topograph- ical one which is attempted here. Instead of putting Socrates in the context of 5th-century B.C. philosophy, politics, ethics or rhetoric, we shall look to find him in the material world and physical surroundings of his favorite stamping- grounds, the Athenian Agora. Just as ‘agora’ in its original sense meant ‘gathering place’ but came in time to mean ‘market place’, so the agora itself was originally a gathering place I.
    [Show full text]