The Eucharist in Early Franciscan Tradition 307

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Eucharist in Early Franciscan Tradition 307 MarciaL.Colish The Eucharist in Early FranciscanTradition Abstract: This paper considers threequestions on the Eucharist treated by Alexander of Hales in his Quaestiones disputatae antequam esset frater and Glossa on the Sen- tences of Peter Lombard, and then by William of Melitona in his Quaestiones de sac- ramentis and,asthe acknowledgedauthor or complier of Book 4ofthe Summa Ha- lensis,inthat text in its Cologne, 1622 edition: 1. Transubstantiation as the full substantial changeofbread and wine on the altar into the bodyand blood of Christ as opposed to the remanescenceand annihilation theories, the other two orthodox alternatives; 2. How two bodies can occupy the same spaceatthe sametime, al- though one of them, the glorified bodyofthe resurrected Christ,isnot held to be sub- ject to the laws of physics governing natural bodies; and 3. How the accidents of bread and wine can survive in the consecrated elements, since they are no longer subtended by the substance of bread and wine. Along with standard authorities, Alexander and William draw on some distinctive sources. Theseinclude Peter Lom- bard’s Collectanea,not always distinguished from the biblical Glossa ordinaria by Alexander’sand William’seditors;the semantic theory of Prepositinus of Cremona; and Innocent III’streatise on the Mass, which defends the Real Presenceastransub- stantiation in awork otherwise devoted to the liturgy of the Mass. The paper empha- sizes the shifting analyses givenbyAlexander across his twotreatments of these questions, as well as thosealtered by William—moving from semantic to physical to mathematical argumentation—in support of positions on the Eucharist which they shared, but which the Summa Halensis does not adopt. Eucharistic theologyhas receivednolack of attention from historians of scholasti- cism. Accenting philosophicalexplanations of the Real Presencedoctrine after 1250,they tend to devalue earlier accounts as technicallydeficient or as confined to divine miracle. This studyofAlexander of Hales, William of Melitona, and the Summa Halensis proposes arevaluation of earlyFranciscan contributions to two major Eucharistic debates.Theologians in their dayoffered three alternative theories to explain Christ’sReal Presence in the Eucharist.Alexander,William, and the au- thorities on whom they relyall support the transubstantiation theory and reject re- manescenceand annihilation. This position affected their approach to the second issue, accidentswithout asubject in the consecrated species.Sources available to Alexander and William in Latin, and their own ingenuity,informed the usesthey make of the artes and philosophy. This paper will focus on the modes of argument they applytothese twocontroverted doctrines. The characterization of earlyFranciscans as disinclined to applyrational expla- nations to the Eucharist can be found even in studies that valorize learning in that OpenAccess. ©2020 Lydia Schumacher,published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative CommonsAttribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110685008-018 304 Marcia L. Colish order.Bert Roest begins with Bonaventure,¹ as does David Burr.Burr’searlyFrancis- cans join Eucharistic theologians whose view of their job ‘was not to provethe un- provable or explain the unexplainable’.² While noting that,by1330, the Franciscan defenseofaccidents without asubject had become ‘an immovable givenofmetaphy- sics’,³ William Duba givesnosense of its development before Duns Scotus.Marilyn Adams begins her survey with Aquinas, and is likewise uninterested in earlyscho- lastics on the topics she treats.⁴ As is well known, before and after the definition of the Real Presenceastransub- stantiation at Lateran IV in 1215,threetheories wereproposed to describeit. All were regarded as tenable within the western orthodoxconsensus.⁵ Historians have flagged the shift from alargely anti-heretical defense of the Real Presencetoits reframing in Aristotelian terms. Indeed, it was the controversy launched by Berengarius of Tours in the 11th century thatnormalized the languageofmatterand form, substance and accident,inthis context,⁶ Aristotelian terminology accessed by wayofBoethius. A standard author in the Latin school curriculum, Boethius remained amajor source for the philosophical arguments of Alexander and William as well, along with Bert Roest, ‘“Franciscan Augustinianism”:Musings about Labels and LateMedieval School Forma- tion,’ in Bert Roest, Franciscan Learning, Preaching and Mission, c. 1226–1650: Cum scientia sit donum Dei, armaturaaddefendendamsanctam fidem catholicam…,The Medieval Franciscans,10(Leiden: Brill, 2016), 111–3, and this despiteRoest’svigorousdefense of the acceptability of learningfrom Francis of Assisi onwardinBertRoest, ‘Francis of Assisi and the Pursuit of Learning,’ in Franciscan Learning,Preaching and Mission,1–18;BertRoest, ‘The Franciscan School System:Re-assessing the EarlyEvidence,’ in Franciscan Learning, Preaching and Mission,19–50;and Bert Roest, ‘Religious Life in the Franciscan School Network (13th Century),’ in Franciscan Learning,Preaching and Mission, 51– 82. The anthology De causalitate sacramentorum iuxta scholam franciscanum,ed. Willibrord Lampen (Bonn: PetrusHanstein, 1931) is not of use in this paper; whilethe editor’sselections begin with the Summa Halensis (ascribingits authorship to Alexander)they do not treat the Euchar- istic topics herediscussed. David Burr, Eucharistic Presence and Conversion in Late Thirteenth-CenturyFranciscan Thought, Transactionsofthe American Philosophical Society,74/3(Philadelphia: American Philosophical So- ciety,1984), 6–7. William O. Duba, TheForge of Doctrine: TheAcademicYear 1330–31 and the Rise of Scotism at the University of Paris,Studia Sententiarum,2(Turnhout: Brepols,2017), 150 –3; quotationat153. Marilyn McCordAdams, Some Later Medieval Theories of the Eucharist:Thomas Aquinas,Giles of Rome, Duns Scotus,and William of Ockham (Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press,2010). Hans Jorissen, Die Entfaltung der Transsubstantiationslehrebis zumBeginn der Hochscholastik, Münsterische Beiträgezur Theologie, 28/1 (Münster: Aschendorff, 1965), 11–154,156;Gary Macy, TheTheologies of the Eucharist in the Early Scholastic Period: AStudy of the Salvific Function of the Sacrament according to the Theologians,c.1080-c. 1220 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), 3–5; Gary Macy, ‘Berengar’sLegacyasaHeresiarch,’ in Treasuresfrom the Storeroom: Medieval Religion and the Eucharist (Collegeville, MN:Liturgical Press, 1999), 59–80,Gary Macy, ‘The “Dogma of Transub- stantiation” in the Middle Ages,’ in Treasures from the Storeroom,82–120; Paul J.J.M. Bakker, La rai- son et le miracle: Les doctrines eucharistiques (c. 1250-c. 1400): Contribution àl’étude des rapports entre philosophie et théologie,2vols. (Nijmegen: KatholiekeUniversiteit Nijmegen, 1999), 1:156–66; Bakkerbegins his account with William of Auxerre. Jorissen, Die Entfaltung,25–44,156. The EucharistinEarly Franciscan Tradition 305 more recent Latin sources and translations. Before continuing, let us note thatthe investigation in this paper will be limited to printedsources, including, perforce, the uncritical earlymodern edition of Book 4ofthe Summa Halensis. Another limi- tation is that we will not draw systematicallyonbiblical exegesis as asource, al- though the scholastics did so. And, despite the terms preferred by some modern scholars,⁷ we will follow our medieval authorsinnaming the three Real Presence theories: remanescence, annihilation, and transubstantiation. Proponents of remanescenceheld that the substance of bread and wine remains in the consecratedspecies, at least in part,inorder to provide asubstrate in which the accidents of bread and wine can inhere. Proponents of annihilation held that the bread and wine are totallyannihilated by the consecration; God then replaces them with newlycreated species that contain both Christ’sbodyand blood and the acci- dents of bread and wine. Both annihilationists and proponents of the completesub- stantial changeofbread and wine into the bodyand blood of Christ,called transub- stantiation since the earlytwelfth century,had to account for the inherenceofthe accidents of bread and wine in species that no longer contain the substance of bread and wine. They agreed that such was the case; what they debated was if, and how,itcould be explained,beyond the reiteration of biblical and patristic asser- tions and the appeal to miracle. Alexander of Hales is rightlyhailed for making the commentary on Peter Lom- bard’s Sentences arequirement for incipient university theologians.⁸ Yet, it is remark- able how little attention has been paid to the Lombard’sown teachingsonthe Eu- charist as asourcefor Alexander’s. In Peter’s Collectanea (first redaction 1139/41, second redaction 1157/58), his commentary on 1Cor.11:23–24 defends the transub- stantiation theory and formulates aposition on accidents without asubject that res- onates later. He invokes the Aristotelian languageofsubstance and accidents. ‘It is believed’,heobserves, that[the bread and wine] ‘changeinto the substance of [Christ’s] bodyand blood’ (credatur transire in substantiam corporis et sanguinis). Re- garding the consecrated species,hemaintains thattheir ‘color,taste, shape, and weight,which wereaccidents of their substance before, ( … )may exist without a subject, even as they do in asubject’ (color,sapor,forma, pondus, quae prioris sub- Macy, ‘Dogma of Transubstantiation,’ 83 and passim substitutes ‘coexistence’, ‘substitution’,and
Recommended publications
  • Medieval Western Philosophy: the European Emergence
    Cultural Heritage and Contemporary Change Series I, Culture and Values, Volume 9 History of Western Philosophy by George F. McLean and Patrick J. Aspell Medieval Western Philosophy: The European Emergence By Patrick J. Aspell The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy 1 Copyright © 1999 by The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy Gibbons Hall B-20 620 Michigan Avenue, NE Washington, D.C. 20064 All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Aspell, Patrick, J. Medieval western philosophy: the European emergence / Patrick J. Aspell. p.cm. — (Cultural heritage and contemporary change. Series I. Culture and values ; vol. 9) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Philosophy, Medieval. I. Title. III. Series. B721.A87 1997 97-20069 320.9171’7’090495—dc21 CIP ISBN 1-56518-094-1 (pbk.) 2 Table of Contents Chronology of Events and Persons Significant in and beyond the History of Medieval Europe Preface xiii Part One: The Origins of Medieval Philosophy 1 Chapter I. Augustine: The Lover of Truth 5 Chapter II. Universals According to Boethius, Peter Abelard, and Other Dialecticians 57 Chapter III. Christian Neoplatoists: John Scotus Erigena and Anselm of Canterbury 73 Part Two: The Maturity of Medieval Philosophy Chronology 97 Chapter IV. Bonaventure: Philosopher of the Exemplar 101 Chapter V. Thomas Aquinas: Philosopher of the Existential Act 155 Part Three: Critical Reflection And Reconstruction 237 Chapter VI. John Duns Scotus: Metaphysician of Essence 243 Chapter
    [Show full text]
  • Alexander of Hales'stheology in His Authentic Texts (Commentary On
    chapter 13 Alexander of Hales’s Theology in His Authentic Texts (Commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, Various Disputed Questions) Hubert Philipp Weber As the first teacher at the University of Paris to become a Franciscan friar, Alexander of Hales has an honoured place in the history of the order. The greater part of his theological work was already completed while he was a secular master. It is therefore more correct to call him an important theolo- gian who influenced Franciscan theology. However, it is not easy to distinguish what makes him a ‘Franciscan theologian’. I will begin by offering some his- torical remarks on his life and his authentic writings, most of which were discovered in the twentieth century. Then I will continue by giving an impres- sion of his thought with a few examples from his writings. The final sec- tion contains a very short outline of the Summa Universae Theologiae (also known as the Summa fratris Alexandri or Summa Halensis) connected with his name. 1 Historical Remarks: Alexander’s Life and Work We do not know very much about Alexander’s early life.1 His surname indicates his origin, Hales in Shropshire, England, where he was born around 1185. He stayed in contact with England all his life. In the first years of the thirteenth century he arrived at the University of Paris, where he studied and taught artes liberales. From about 1220 he lectured at the theological faculty. During the conflict between the university and the bishop of Paris in 1229/31 he went into exile.
    [Show full text]
  • The Passions of the Will and the Passion of Christ in Franciscantheologyfromthe Summa Halensis to Duns Scotus
    Andrew V. Rosato The Passions of the Will and the Passion of Christ in FranciscanTheologyfromthe Summa Halensis to Duns Scotus Abstract: This chapter examines how the Summa Halensis’ analysis of Christ’ssorrow was adopted and modified by later Franciscan theologians.Accordingtothe teach- ing of Jerome, which Peter Lombardmade available to medieval theologians,Christ’s sorrow arose from an involuntary reaction to his physical suffering. In order to ex- pand upon Jerome’saccount,the Summa Halensis develops an elaborate map of Christ’ssoul by drawing on psychological principles found in Augustine and John Damascene. 13th century theologians debated whether Christ could experience sor- row over his ownsuffering not justasanatural and instinctual reaction, but also as the result of freelywillingthat he not suffer.Anobstacle to asserting this would be anyimplication that Christ did not will by his human willwhat God willed him to will. Richard of Middleton, Matthew of Aquasparta, and Duns Scotus do af- firm that Christ in some wayfreelynilled his own suffering, and experiencedsorrow over it because of that.Indifferent ways they employ the account of Christ’ssoul out- lined in the Summa Halensis to avoid anyimplication that Christ fell into sin by freely nilling his ownsuffering. The GospelofMatthew reports that Jesus experienced sorrow in the Garden of Geth- semane (26:37–38): ‘he began to be sorrowful [coepit contristari]and troubled. Then he said to them, “My soul is sorrowful [tristis]tothe point of death.”’ Jerome offered an influential interpretation of this passagewhen he statedthatChrist experienced the propassion of sorrow rather than afull-fledgedform of thatpassion. One differ- ence between apropassion and afull-fledgedpassion is that apropassion does not overwhelm one’sability to use reason.
    [Show full text]
  • Divine Providence from Alexander of Hales to Thomas Aquinas
    chapter 2 Divine Providence from Alexander of Hales to Thomas Aquinas 1 Accidental Causality, Free Choice and Evil Divine causality was discussed by the medieval theologians under the rub- ric of several independent doctrines. All the authors studied in this work held that providence worked through an order of secondary natural causes. This sets the theology of providence apart from the theology of salvation, for example. The salvation or damnation of any given individual was based solely on divine causality.The realization of the providential order, on the other hand, was founded on the co-operation between divine and created causality. While this order was certainly based on divine disposition, its practical implementa- tion was carried out by the total order of causes (connexio causarum). In this sense, divine providence was conceptualized in a natural philosophical frame- work. One of the foundational themes of Aristotelian natural philosophy, the notion of causality was crucial to the medieval discussions concerning divine providence. According to Aristotle, causes come in four distinct types: mater- ial, formal, efficient and final.1 From the perspective of this study, efficient and final causality are of greater importance than material and formal caus- ality. As shown in the previous chapter, Boethius’s Consolatio philosophiae was of crucial importance for the medieval theories of divine providence. Boethius’s understanding of providence contained elements of both efficient and final causality.2 Meanwhile in Averroes’s influential interpretation of Aris- totle, divine providence was seen exclusively as a final cause, whereas the effi- cient causality of God was not considered to be of direct relevance for the topic.
    [Show full text]
  • Blander Diss Commented Normore Blander Replies V3
    UCLA UCLA Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Dependence, Separability, and Theories of Identity and Distinction in Late Medieval Philosophy: Case Studies from Scotus and Ockham Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/6wh8q15d Author Blander, Joshua Publication Date 2014 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Dependence, Separability, and Theories of Identity and Distinction in Late Medieval Philosophy: Case Studies from Scotus and Ockham A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Joshua Blander 2014 © Copyright by Joshua Blander 2014 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Dependence, Separability, and Theories of Identity and Distinction in Late Medieval Philosophy: Case Studies from Scotus and Ockham by Joshua Blander Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy University of California, Los Angeles, 2014 Professor Calvin Normore, Chair Theories of distinctions surface some of the most fundamental elements of metaphysical and logical inquiry. For many medieval philosophers, theories of distinctions provided some semblance of rational order and unity to metaphysical, logical and theological questions. The two philosophers on which I focus, John Duns Scotus and William Ockham, discuss distinctions and metaphysical adjuncts in a variety of philosophical and theological contexts. When discussing Scotus, I emphasize his development of a robust theory of identity and distinction. I give special attention to his accounts of what he calls qualified non-identity or qualified distinction, which he surprisingly says is compatible with real identity. When I turn my attention to Ockham, I focus on his use of the real distinction in the context of the common fourteenth century disputes about universals.
    [Show full text]
  • The Friendships of St. Thomas
    THE FRIENDSHIPS OF ST. THOMAS BRO. CYRIL DORE, 0 . P. T . Thomas Aquinas is a perfect type of that harmonious un­ ion of sanctity and learning which characterizes the great Doctors of the Church. A tender affection and a sympathetic understanding, which unites hearts entirely devoted to God, can be observed in all his friendships. While bearing himself affably towards all, the Angelic Doctor had but few intimate friends and these were persons of singular learning and holiness. From a consideration of these few, we can see the great influence for good which he exerted, the wide extent of his knowledge, and the deep penetration of his in­ tellectual prowess. They not only give us an insight into the reaction of personality on personality and the interplay of mind on mind, but in a very special manner, they exhibit the practical aspect of his writ­ ings. From the investigations of his biographers, the friendships of St. Thomas can be considered under four headings; namely, within his own Order, in the religious world, in the academic world, and in the political world. Amongst the members of the Dominican Order, the first friend mentioned is John of St. Julian. He is referred to as the old adviser and dear familiar friend of St. Thomas.1 This celebrated preacher directed the footsteps of the young Aquinas during the three years previous to his entrance into the Dominican Order. As a student at the University of Naples, the mind and imagination of Aquinas were captivated by the sanctity, the learning and the marvellous activ­ ity of the Dominicans.
    [Show full text]
  • Christian History & Biography
    Issue 73: Thomas Aquinas: Greatest Medieval Theologian Thomas Aquinas: Did You Know? Interesting and unusual fact about Thomas Aquinas editors Trounced In a detail from Andrea di Bonaiuto's fourteenth-century fresco The Triumph of Saint Thomas Aquinas, heretics Averroes and Arius crouch beneath the enthroned Aquinas. Averroes (also called Ibn Rushd; 1126-1198) was a Muslim philosopher who, according to Aquinas, made a hash of Aristotle and led many medieval Christians astray. Arius (c. 250-c. 336) denied Christ's full divinity by positing that "there was [a time] when the son was not." Aquinas participated in no physical crusades against heresy, but he did believe that heretics "deserve not only to be separated from the Church by excommunication, but also to be severed from the world by death." Fancy meeting you here Aquinas and several of his enemies make appearances in James Joyce's daunting 1922 novel Ulysses. In chapter one, a character is asked for his views on Hamlet but replies, "I'm not equal to Thomas Aquinas and the fiftyfive reasons he has made to prop it up. Wait till I have a few pints in me first." Arius, Sabellius (the third heretic at Aquinas's feet in The Triumph), Averroes, and Moses Maimonides (see page 37) pop up as well. Heeding the call Franciscans in Assisi will soon enjoy a new feature in their habits: cell phone pockets. Some critics consider the innovation inappropriate, but Elisabetta Biancheri, who designed the habits, said, "It is simply a functional item of clothing. Even monks make phone calls." Biancheri is right about the phones, but she shouldn't call Franciscans "monks"—they're friars, and, as Thomas well knew, there is a difference (see page 23).
    [Show full text]
  • Sean Hannan 7-352H | Department of Humanities | Macewan University | City Centre Campus 10700 – 104 Ave
    Sean Hannan 7-352H | Department of Humanities | MacEwan University | City Centre Campus 10700 – 104 Ave. | Edmonton AB T5J 4S2 | Canada [email protected] | (780) 292-1150 EMPLOYMENT Assistant Professor in the Humanities, MacEwan University (Edmonton), July 2016 - EDUCATION Ph.D. University of Chicago (Chicago, IL), 2016 Awarded with Distinction Discipline: Divinity (History of Christianity) Dissertation: “Belatedness: Augustine on Transformation in Time and History” Committee: Willemien Otten (Advisor); Jean-Luc Marion and David Nirenberg (Readers) Qualifying Exams (2012): Ancient Christianity (Margaret Mitchell); Medieval Christianity (Willemien Otten); Early Modern Christianity (Susan Schreiner); Philosophy of Religion – Kant through Heidegger (Jean-Luc Marion) M.A. University of Chicago (Chicago, IL), 2008 Discipline: Social Sciences (History) Thesis: “The Essence of Relation: Eternity and Trinity in Augustine’s De Trinitate” B.A. University of Alberta (Edmonton, AB, Canada), History (with Honors), 2007 Awarded with Honours Discipline: History Thesis: “The Specter of Theology in Husserl’s Phenomenology of Time-Consciousness” MONOGRAPH Reading Augustine: on Time, Change, History, and Conversion. Part of the Reading Augustine Series, edited by Miles Hollingworth. London: Bloomsbury, forthcoming. CO-EDITED VOLUMES Political Theology: Promise and Prospects. Edited by Willemien Otten, Andrea White, and Sean Hannan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming. Augustine and Time. Edited by John Doody, Kim Paffenroth, and Sean Hannan. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, forthcoming. ARTICLES & CHAPTERS “Individuating Time: the Indivisible Moment in Augustine and Ancient Atomism.” The Unique, the Singular, and the Individual: the Debate about the Non-Comparable. Eds. Ingolf U. Dalferth and Trevor W. Kimball. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2020. Forthcoming. Hannan – CV June 2019 – 1 “Nineveh Overturned: Augustine and Chrysostom on the Threat of Jonah.” Journal of Early Christian Studies (2020).
    [Show full text]
  • Salvation in Christ.Qxp 4/29/2005 4:09 PM Page 365
    Salvation in Christ.qxp 4/29/2005 4:09 PM Page 365 Index Aaronic Priesthood. See priesthood Amos, 240, 316 Abelard, Peter, 109, 212 Anglicanism, 53–66 Abraham, 30, 137–38, 148, 316 Anglican Understanding of the Acts of the Apostles, 38–40 Church, The, 54 Adam, 13, 110, 130, 137–39, 151, Anselm of Canterbury, 75, 107–9, 162, 215 112–20, 212, 347 Adam and Eve, 256 Aquinas, Thomas, 109, 113–15, and rebirth, 8 118, 121, 320 call upon God, 148 Aristotle, 224 cast from Garden of Eden, Arminianism, 161, 183–202 143, 145 Arminius, Jacob, 183, 189–91, descendants of, 205 193, 310 Greek understanding of, Articles and Covenants, 276 248, 259 “Articles of Religion,” 57–58 Fall of (see Fall of Adam Ashton, Marvin J., 89 and Eve) Association of Evangelicals, 189 first sin, 338 Atonement. See Jesus Christ, Adorno, Theodor, 225 Atonement of Adversus Haereses, 111 Athanasian Creed, 339 agency, 12, 147, 162–63, 200, 249 Athanasius the Great, 173, 175, agnosticism, 301 255, 313 Aimilianos, Father, 250–251 Augustine, 113, 173, 175, 305, 308, Albert the Great, 310 314–15 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 224 Aulén, Gustaf, 111–12, 118, 212 Alexander of Hales, 309 Avis, Paul, 54 Alliance of Confessing Evangeli- cals, 186 Baker, Simon, 278 Althaus, Paul, 117 Bangs, Carl, 190 365 Salvation in Christ.qxp 4/29/2005 4:09 PM Page 366 Salvation in Christ baptism, 13–14, 90, 131, 214 Callister, Tad R., 169 by immersion, 16 Calvin, John, 327–28 for dead (see redemption of on Arminianism, 191, 196 the dead) on Crucifixion, 74 Barclay, Robert, 318 on election, 341 Barth, Karl,
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and the Condemnations of 1277
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by CiteSeerX Logic and the condemnations of 1277 Sara L. Uckelman† †Institute for Logic, Language, and Computation Plantage Muidergracht 24 1018TV Amsterdam, The Netherlands +31 20 525 5361 (phone) +31 20 525 5206 (fax) [email protected] November 13, 2008 Abstract The struggle to delineate the relationship between theology and logic flourished in the thirteenth century and culminated in two condemnations in early 1277, one in Paris and the other in Oxford. To see how much and what kind of affect ecclessiastical actions such as condemnations and prohibitions to teach had on the development of logic in the Middle Ages, we investigate the events leading up to the 1277 actions, the condemned propositions, and the parts of these condemnations connected to modal and temporal logic specifically. We show that because of the specific mo- tivations late 13th-century and 14th-century logicians had when working in modal and temporal logic, the effect of the 1277 condemnations on the development of those branches was much smaller than might have been supposed. Keywords: modal logic, temporal logic, Oxford condemnation, Paris condemnation, Robert Kilwardby, Stephen Tempier 1 Preliminary remarks A 21st-century logician who is interested in the societal factors which affect the development of various branches of logic cannot help but notice that one of the biggest differences between logic as it is currently practiced and logic as it was practiced in the Middle Ages is the role of the Church. Problems in theology have very little influence on modern logic, whereas medieval logicians were often trained theologians and those who were not were still connected to the Church via the Church’s role in everyday life and its connections to the university and academic life.
    [Show full text]
  • Book Reviews
    BOOK REVIEWS THE NEW TESTAMENT OF OUR LORD AND SAVIOR JESUS CHRIST: RE­ VISED STANDARD VERSION—CATHOLIC EDITION. Prepared by the Catholic Biblical Association of Great Britain. Collegeville, Minn.: St. John's Abbey, 1965. Pp. 250. $3.50. With the publication of the NT in the Catholic edition of the Protestant Revised Standard Version (RSV), and the preparation of the OT in the same edition, English-speaking Catholics throughout the world will finally have a whole Bible translated from the original languages. Most of them will not realize at first what this means and it will take them some time to get used to it. But the boon that this publication represents is beyond estimate. The RSV is justly famed as the latest revision of the English translation of the Bible first published in England in 1611. That "Authorized Version" (AV), commonly called in this country the King James Version (KJV), was first modernized in the "Revised Version" (RV) of 1881 (the NT) and 1885 (the OT). This revision strove to introduce as few alterations as possible into the text of the KJV, and sought to be faithful to the original and con­ sistent with current English usage. Yet, the revisers did introduce the prin­ ciple of using, as far as possible, the same English word or phrase for the same Greek or Hebrew. The RV was widely criticized for years, despite the care with which it was produced. Then in 1901 some American scholars who had co-operated in the RV brought out an amended edition called the "American Standard Version" (ASV).
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of Intellectualism: Will, Intellect, and Control in Late Thirteenth-Century Philosophy
    A Defense of Intellectualism: Will, Intellect, and Control in Late Thirteenth-century Philosophy by Michael Szlachta A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Michael Szlachta 2019 A Defense of Intellectualism: Will, Intellect, and Control in Late Thirteenth-century Philosophy Michael Szlachta Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2019 Abstract The question of whether our volitions are caused by the activity of our cognitive powers was the subject of tremendous controversy for medieval philosophers. By answering in the affirmative, Thomas Aquinas, Thomas of Sutton and Godfrey of Fontaines, the so-called intellectualists, face what I call the Problem of Control. If my wanting some object is caused by my apprehending it as good through some cognitive act, then it seems that I am not able to will otherwise than I do. For to will otherwise than I do, it would be necessary that I apprehend some other object as good. If, however, I am not able to will otherwise than I do, then I do not seem to have control over my actions. But if I do not have control over my actions, then I do not act freely, since having control over one’s actions is necessary for acting freely. My dissertation addresses the Problem of Control. I first argue that Thomas Aquinas’s notion of “perfect cognition of the end” gives the intellectualists the resources to explain how a human being has control over her actions. Second, I argue that Aquinas does not adequately explain a central feature of his intellectualism, namely, how the will “moves itself” to the exercise of its act, and discuss how the “self-motion” of the will is addressed by Thomas of Sutton and Godfrey of Fontaines.
    [Show full text]