Augustus De Morgan

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Augustus De Morgan Travis Deitrich History of Mathematics Minor Paper 2 Augustus De Morgan The beginning of the 19th century was an exciting time in the United States and around the world. The White House was built, Lewis and Clark embarked on and completed their journey across what is now the Western United States, and Napoleon declared himself emperor of France. In 1806, Noah Webster published his first dictionary on the English language, a book that is still being updated and published today under the same name. This was the same year that Augustus De Morgan was born. Augustus was born in 1806 in when his father, a lieutenant, was stationed with the English Army in India. Due to a birth defect, Augustus lost vision in his right eye shortly after birth. His father returned to England with his family before turning a year old. As a child, he struggled in school. This seems to be fairly common among future mathematicians as we have learned this was the case for others, including Newton, at a young age. De Morgan did not fit in with the other young boys at school. He could not join when they were playing sports due to his partial blindness. This resulted in him becoming the target of jokes by other students, which likely lead to his education struggles (O’Connor, Robertson, n.d.). Fortunately, his struggles did not last, and he found pleasure and success in mathematics. It was then at a young age of 16 that he was off to Trinity College Cambridge in 1823 to study math. He was mentored by professors, and future lifetime friends, George Peacock and William Whewell. At the age of 21, after earning his BA, De Morgan applied for the chair of mathematics at a new university, University College London. Despite having never published, he was granted the chair and became the first professor of mathematics at this new college. He would hold his position for a total of 33 years, despite being forced to resign twice. Travis Deitrich History of Mathematics Minor Paper 2 It was during these years that De Morgan began making his impact on the history of mathematics (O’Connor, Robertson, n.d.). I first encountered Augustus De Morgan in the same way that I am sure most other students do. It was early on in my first college probability class that we discussed De Morgan’s Laws. These laws seem very trivial to me now after a few courses in probability that I forget that they weren’t always known and had to be stated and proved. These laws state that (E∪F)` = E`∩F’ and (E∩F)` = E`∪F` (Richards, n.d.). In words, (E∪F)` = E`∩F’, can be explained as the complement of the union of two sets is equal to the intersection of the complement of each set. Also, (E∩F)` = E`∪F` can be explained as the complement of the union of two sets is equal to the union of the complement of each individual set. These laws are perhaps better understood visually at first through the use of Venn Diagrams. If Venn Diagrams had been invented earlier, it is very possible that these laws would have been discovered earlier and would be known by a different mathematician’s name today. Although I knew and understood these laws before researching Augustus De Morgan, I wanted to learn more. I have an interest in probability so I figured he would be a good choice. During my research process, I was shocked to learn that he made an even bigger contribution to mathematics than his laws. De Morgan was the man who recognized the power of, and formalized mathematical induction. I don’t ever remember hearing his name when I took my first course in mathematical proofs. Of course, we learned and used induction, but that was it. We never talked about who formalized it as a key method of proving mathematical statements and theorems. Even in the two semesters so far following this course, I have had numerous Travis Deitrich History of Mathematics Minor Paper 2 classes where mathematical induction was an important tool, and still no mention of De Morgan. Mathematical induction is a method of proving propositions and theorems. There are two types of induction, strong and weak, but they work similarly. Generalizing induction into one category, this is the idea behind how it works. When given a statement, you prove that it is true for some base case. Typically, this is done by allowing n to be a natural number and setting it equal to 1. After you have shown the statement is true for the base case, you assume that the statement is true for n equal to k, where k is any natural number. Finally, you use this assumption to show that the statement is also true for n equal to k + 1. As k is arbitrary, this then shows that the statement holds true for all natural numbers. That is how I was first taught induction, and it is typically how I have used induction since. However, this semester I have experienced it in a slightly different way. I have used induction to prove theorems in graph theory. When using induction in this sense, we are typically removing a vertex or an edge and stating the result. We then continue to remove vertices and edges until we get to the desired conclusion, hence proving the original theorem or statement true. While we don’t use induction over the natural numbers, the same ideology and principles still hold true. De Morgan first defined and used the term mathematical induction in an article titled Induction (Mathematics) (O’Connor, Robertson, n.d.). This article was one of 712 articles he would eventually write for the Penny Cyclopedia. He defined successive induction as “a collection of general truth from a demonstration which implies the examination of every particular case” (O’Connor, Robertson, n.d.). He then went on to show how this method in Travis Deitrich History of Mathematics Minor Paper 2 action by proving that the sum of any number of successive odd numbers beginning with 1 is a square number (Kolpas, n.d.). Another field that De Morgan studied was complex numbers. He published Trigonometry and Double Algebra in 1849. In this book he gave a geometric interpretation of complex numbers. This work led him to understand that there were other forms of algebra outside of ordinary algebra. He realized that algebra had a purely symbolic nature which is why he worked with Charles Babbage and Lady Lovelace. Lovelace of course is said to have wrote the first computer program for Babbage. They all worked well together because of their understanding that algebra was symbolic and had other forms (O’Connor, Robertson, n.d.). One question that De Morgan posed that I found particularly interesting is the four color problem. Essentially, De Morgan claimed that given any map that shows the borders of any number of countries, you can color them without two countries bordering each other being the same color using just four colors. He made this proposition in 1852 and despite being fairly obvious just by drawing and coloring any map, it wasn’t proved to be true until 1976 (Richards, n.d.). Before I began the research process, I only knew Augustus De Morgan in the context of probability. Because of this, I assumed that De Morgan was primarily interested in probability and statistics. However, I have now learned that is not true. De Morgan was primarily a logician, it just so happens that his laws are used in probability. These laws also apply to set theory, which is more along the lines of their original use by De Morgan. He also used his interest in logic to formalize mathematical induction, which in my opinion is where we should really learn his name as induction is far more important to a math student then De Morgan’s laws. I will Travis Deitrich History of Mathematics Minor Paper 2 leave you with this “fun fact” as De Morgan, much like myself, was always interested in random numerical facts. In the year 1849 De Morgan turned age 43, which as he himself wrote, gave him the distinction of being x years old in the year 푥2. Travis Deitrich History of Mathematics Minor Paper 2 References: Kolpas, S. (n.d.). Mathematical Treasure: Augustus De Morgan and Mathematical Induction. Retrieved October 17, 2019, from https://www.maa.org/press/periodicals/convergence/mathematical-treasure-augustus-de- morgan-and-mathematical-induction. O'Connor, J., & Robertson, E. (n.d.). Augustus De Morgan. Retrieved October 17, 2019, from https://www-history.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/Biographies/De_Morgan.html. Richards, Joan L. “‘This Compendious Language’: Mathematics in the World of Augustus De Morgan.” Retrieved October 17, 2019, from www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/661624. .
Recommended publications
  • Explanations
    © Copyright, Princeton University Press. No part of this book may be distributed, posted, or reproduced in any form by digital or mechanical means without prior written permission of the publisher. CHAPTER 1 Explanations 1.1 SALLIES Language is an instrument of Logic, but not an indispensable instrument. Boole 1847a, 118 We know that mathematicians care no more for logic than logicians for mathematics. The two eyes of exact science are mathematics and logic; the mathematical sect puts out the logical eye, the logical sect puts out the mathematical eye; each believing that it sees better with one eye than with two. De Morgan 1868a,71 That which is provable, ought not to be believed in science without proof. Dedekind 1888a, preface If I compare arithmetic with a tree that unfolds upwards in a multitude of techniques and theorems whilst the root drives into the depthswx . Frege 1893a, xiii Arithmetic must be discovered in just the same sense in which Columbus discovered the West Indies, and we no more create numbers than he created the Indians. Russell 1903a, 451 1.2 SCOPE AND LIMITS OF THE BOOK 1.2.1 An outline history. The story told here from §3 onwards is re- garded as well known. It begins with the emergence of set theory in the 1870s under the inspiration of Georg Cantor, and the contemporary development of mathematical logic by Gottlob Frege andŽ. especially Giuseppe Peano. A cumulation of these and some related movements was achieved in the 1900s with the philosophy of mathematics proposed by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell.
    [Show full text]
  • AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN and the LOGIC of RELATIONS the New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy
    AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN AND THE LOGIC OF RELATIONS The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 38 Series Editor: NORMAN KRETZMANN, Cornell University Associate Editors: DANIEL ELLIOT GARBER, University of Chicago SIMO KNUUTTILA, University of Helsinki RICHARD SORABJI, University of London Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Free University, Amsterdam ROGER ARIEW, Virginia Polytechnic Institute E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University of Waterloo MICHAEL AYERS, Wadham College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. J. HANKINSON, University of Texas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University, Finnish Academy PAUL HOFFMAN, Massachusetts Institute of Technology DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, University of Illinois, Chicago ALAIN DE LIBERA, Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes, Sorbonne DAVID FATE NORTON, McGill University LUCA OBERTELLO, Universita degli Studi di Genova ELEONORE STUMP, Virginia Polytechnic Institute ALLEN WOOD, Cornell University The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. DANIEL D. MERRILL Department of Philosophy, Oberlin College, USA AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN AND THE LOGIC OF RELATIONS KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS DORDRECHT I BOSTON I LONDON Library of Congress Cataloging. in·Publication Data Merrill, Daniel D. (Daniel Davy) Augustus De Morgan and the lOglC of relations / Daniel D. Merril. p. cm. -- <The New synthese historical library; 38) 1. De Morgan, Augustus, 1806-1871--Contributions in logic of relations. 2. Inference. 3. Syllogism. 4. Logic, Symbolic and mathematical--History--19th cenTury. I. Title. II. Series. BC185.M47 1990 160' .92--dc20 90-34935 ISBN·13: 978·94·010·7418·6 e-ISBN -13: 978-94-009-2047-7 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-009-2047-7 Published by Kluwer Academic Publishers, P.O.
    [Show full text]
  • How Peircean Was the “'Fregean' Revolution” in Logic?
    HOW PEIRCEAN WAS THE “‘FREGEAN’ REVOLUTION” IN LOGIC? Irving H. Anellis Peirce Edition, Institute for American Thought Indiana University – Purdue University at Indianapolis Indianapolis, IN, USA [email protected] Abstract. The historiography of logic conceives of a Fregean revolution in which modern mathematical logic (also called symbolic logic) has replaced Aristotelian logic. The preeminent expositors of this conception are Jean van Heijenoort (1912–1986) and Don- ald Angus Gillies. The innovations and characteristics that comprise mathematical logic and distinguish it from Aristotelian logic, according to this conception, created ex nihlo by Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) in his Begriffsschrift of 1879, and with Bertrand Rus- sell (1872–1970) as its chief This position likewise understands the algebraic logic of Augustus De Morgan (1806–1871), George Boole (1815–1864), Charles Sanders Peirce (1838–1914), and Ernst Schröder (1841–1902) as belonging to the Aristotelian tradi- tion. The “Booleans” are understood, from this vantage point, to merely have rewritten Aristotelian syllogistic in algebraic guise. The most detailed listing and elaboration of Frege’s innovations, and the characteristics that distinguish mathematical logic from Aristotelian logic, were set forth by van Heijenoort. I consider each of the elements of van Heijenoort’s list and note the extent to which Peirce had also developed each of these aspects of logic. I also consider the extent to which Peirce and Frege were aware of, and may have influenced, one another’s logical writings. AMS (MOS) 2010 subject classifications: Primary: 03-03, 03A05, 03C05, 03C10, 03G27, 01A55; secondary: 03B05, 03B10, 03E30, 08A20; Key words and phrases: Peirce, abstract algebraic logic; propositional logic; first-order logic; quantifier elimina- tion, equational classes, relational systems §0.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Language and Mathematical Progress by Eberhard Knobloch
    Mathematical language and mathematical progress By Eberhard Knobloch In 1972 the space probe Pioneer 10 was launched, carrying a plaque which contains the first message of mankind to leave our solar system1: The space probe is represented by a circular segment and a rectangle designed on the same scale as that of the man and the woman. This is not true of the solar system: sun and planets are represented by small circles and points. We do not know whether there are other intelligent beings living on stars in the universe, or whether they will even understand the message. But the non-verbal, the symbolical language of geometry seemed to be more appropriate than any other language. The grammar of any ordinary language is so complicated that still every computer breaks down with regards to it. 1 Karl Märker, "Sind wir allein im Weltall? Kosmos und Leben", in: Astronomie im Deutschen Museum, Planeten - Sterne - Welteninseln, hrsg. von Gerhard Hartl, Karl Märker, Jürgen Teichmann, Gudrun Wolfschmidt (München: Deutsches Museum, 1993), p. 217. [We reproduce the image of the plaque from: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pioneer_plaque ; Karine Chemla] 1 The famous Nicholas Bourbaki wrote in 19482: "It is the external form which the mathematician gives to his thought, the vehicle which makes it accessible to others, in short, the language suited to mathematics; this is all, no further significance should be attached to it". Bourbaki added: "To lay down the rules of this language, to set up its vocabulary and to clarify its syntax, all that is indeed extremely useful." But it was only the least interesting aspect of the axiomatic method for him.
    [Show full text]
  • George Boole. Selected Manuscripts on Logic and Its Philosophy (Science Networks
    George Boole. Selected Manuscripts on Logic and its Philosophy (Science Networks. Historical Studies, vol. 20). Ivor Grattan-Guinness/G´erard Bor- net, eds. Birkh¨auser Verlag: Basel/Boston/Berlin, 1997, e 37.30, ISBN 0- 8176-5456-9, lxiv + 236 pp. Reviewed by Volker Peckhaus Universit¨at Paderborn Kulturwissenschaftliche Fakult¨at Warburger Str. 100, D – 33098 Paderborn E-mail: [email protected] George Boole, the founder of the algebra of logic, did not stop working on logic after having published his seminal An Investigation of the Laws of Thought (1854 ). Among his aims was to write a philosophical comple- ment to his writings in the algebra of logic, but he died before he was able to finish it. All this was known already to his contemporaries and although leading authorities like Augustus De Morgan, Bertrand Russell, Philip E. B. Jourdain and Louis Couturat were involved in attempts to publish Boole’s posthumous logical papers, only bits and pieces from his logical manuscripts have been published up to now. This insufficient situation comes now to an end with this scholarly edition by Ivor Grattan-Guinness and G´erard Bornet. The editors have compiled a selection of about 40 % of Boole’s unpublished manuscripts on logic “from a scattered and chronologically unclear textual universe” (p. xxv). The bad condition of the manuscripts is due to Boole’s working style. He usually started each time from scratch producing not really substantial texts but notes and further work-plans. This is explained by Boole himself when he reported his plans to Augustus De Morgan in March 1859 (quoted p.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Symbolic Logic
    An Introduction to Symbolic Logic Guram Bezhanishvili and Wesley Fussner∗ 1 Introduction This project is dedicated to the study of the basics of propositional and pred- icate logic. We will study it based on Russell and Whitehead's epoch making treatise Principia Mathematica [9]. Published in three volumes between 1910 and 1913, Principia was a culmination of work that had been done in the preceding century on the foundations of mathematics. Since the middle of the nineteenth century, such thinkers as George Boole (1815{1864), Augustus De Morgan (1806{1871), Charles Sanders Peirce (1839{1914), Ernst Schr¨oder (1841-1902), Gottlob Frege (1848{1925), and Giuseppe Peano (1858{1932) had been developing axiomatic bases for logic and the foundations of math- ematics. This research program found its culmination in Principia, which had a tremendous influence on the development of logic and the foundations of mathematics in the twentieth century. Logic is a branch of science that studies correct forms of reasoning. It plays a fundamental role in such disciplines as philosophy, mathematics, and computer science. Like philosophy and mathematics, logic has ancient roots. The earliest treatises on the nature of correct reasoning were written over 2000 years ago. Some of the most prominent philosophers of ancient Greece wrote of the nature of deduction more than 2300 years ago, and thinkers in ancient China wrote of logical paradoxes around the same time. However, though its roots may be in the distant past, logic continues to be a vibrant field of study to this day. Modern logic originated in the work of the great Greek philosopher Aris- totle (384{322 bce), the most famous student of Plato (c.427{c.347 bce) and ∗Department of Mathematical Sciences; New Mexico State University; Las Cruces, NM 88003, USA; [email protected]; [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • 2016 Clifton Henry.Pdf
    The Foundations of Mathematics History, Concepts, and Applications in Higher Level Mathematics by Clifton Henry A CAPSTONE PROJECT submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the acknowledgement Honors Distinction Mathematics School of Engineering, Mathematics, and Science TYLER JUNIOR COLLEGE Tyler, Texas 2016 When people hear the word mathematics, some think numbers and others think solving for x and y. In all truth, the field of mathematics is more than numbers and equations. Mathematics was founded based off the principle of counting in 50,000 B.C.E. Mathematical contributions and ideas increased from the Babylonian Empire in 2000 BC to the 18th century, where mathematicians and philosophers developed ideas in algebra, geometry and calculus. It can be argued that mathematical contributions in the 19th century shaped the field of mathematics and set in place the true foundations of mathematics. In the 19th century, mathematical logic was founded, followed by the development of set theory, and then came the concept of mathematical function. Logic, set theory, and function are some of the foundations of mathematics, and the three revolutionized the field of mathematics as a whole. Mathematical fields, such as topology, abstract algebra, and probability rely heavily on the three foundations. Instead of being seen as numbers and equations, mathematics is the field of logic and proof that is based off the mathematical foundations of logic, set theory, and function. It is important to know how the ideas were developed and put to use in order for mathematics to have its meaning and significance. After understanding how the foundations were developed, it is important to understand how they apply in advanced mathematical fields such as topology, abstract algebra, and probability.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustus De Morgan (1806–1871)
    AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN (1806–1871) AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN was born in the month of June at Madura in the presid- ency of Madras, India; and the year of his birth may be found by solving a conundrum ¢ ¡ proposed by himself, “I was ¡ years of age in the year .” The problem is indeterm- inate, but it is made strictly determinate by the century of its utterance and the limit to a man’s life. His father was Col. De Morgan, who held various appointments in the service of the East India Company. His mother was descended from James Dodson, who computed a table of anti-logarithms, that is, the numbers corresponding to exact logarithms. It was the time of the Sepoy rebellion in India, and Col. De Morgan re- moved his family to England when Augustus was seven months old. As his father and grandfather had both been born in India, De Morgan used to say that he was neither English, nor Scottish, nor Irish, but a Briton “unattached,” using the technical term ap- plied to an undergraduate of Oxford or Cambridge who is not a member of any one of the Colleges. When De Morgan was ten years old, his father died. Mrs. De Morgan resided at various places in the southwest of England, and her son received his elementary edu- cation at various schools of no great account. His mathematical talents were unnoticed till he had reached the age of fourteen. A friend of the family accidentally discovered him making an elaborate drawing of a figure in Euclid with ruler and compasses, and explained to him the aim of Euclid, and gave him an initiation into demonstration.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646 – 1716)
    Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646 – 1716) From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gottfried_Leibniz Leibniz occupies a prominent place in the history of mathematics and the history of philosophy. He developed the infinitesimal calculus independently of Isaac Newton, and Leibniz's mathematical notation has been widely used ever since it was published. He became one of the most prolific inventors in the field of mechanical calculators. While working on adding automatic multiplication and division to Pascal's calculator, he was the first to describe a pinwheel calculator in 1685 and invented the Leibniz wheel, used in the arithmometer, the first mass-produced mechanical calculator. He also refined the binary number system, which is at the foundation of virtually all digital computers. In philosophy, Leibniz is mostly noted for his optimism, e.g., his conclusion that our Universe is, in a restricted sense, the best possible one that God could have created. Leibniz, along with René Descartes and Baruch Spinoza, was one of the three great 17th century advocates of rationalism. The work of Leibniz anticipated modern logic and analytic philosophy, but his philosophy also looks back to the scholastic tradition, in which conclusions are produced by applying reason to first principles or prior definitions rather than to empirical evidence. Leibniz made major contributions to physics and technology, and anticipated notions that surfaced much later in biology, medicine, geology, probability theory, psychology, linguistics, and information science. He wrote works on politics, law, ethics, theology, history, philosophy, and philology. Leibniz's contributions to this vast array of subjects were scattered in various learned journals, in tens of thousands of letters, and in unpublished manuscripts.
    [Show full text]
  • De Morgan's Logic
    DE MORGAN'S LOGIC Michael E. Hobart and Joan L. Richards 1 INTRODUCTION: THE SYMBOLIC TURN IN LOGIC Looking back on a more than a decade of work in logic, Augustus De Morgan (1806-1871) remembered that from the beginning "in my own mind I was facing Kant's assertion that logic neither has improved since the time of Aristotle, nor of its own nature can improve, except in perspicuity, accuracy of expressions and the like" .1 For Immanuel Kant, writing at the very end of the eighteenth century, the longevity of Aristotle's logic showed that the Greek had essentially gotten it right; for De Morgan it was evidence of stagnation. From his position in the progressive nineteenth century, De Morgan set out in the 1840s to move the study of logic forward by building on the foundation Aristotle had laid. In so doing, De Morgan brought a very specific view of progress to his logical enterprise. "Every science that has thriven has thriven upon its own symbols: logic, the only science which is admitted to have made no improvements in century after century, is the only one which has grown no new symbols. ''2 De Morgan's logical program, then, entailed creating a set of symbols that would show him the way to move logic beyond its Aristotelian base into an ever-expanding future. For many, De Morgan's determination to create an operational set of logical symbols has marked him as a pioneer of the symbolic logic of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, and he is routinely credited with the laws that bear his name and with the logic of relations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Project Gutenberg Ebook #39088: on the Study and Difficulties of Mathematics
    The Project Gutenberg EBook of On the Study and Difficulties of Mathematics, by Augustus De Morgan This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org Title: On the Study and Difficulties of Mathematics Author: Augustus De Morgan Release Date: February 17, 2013 [EBook #39088] Language: English Character set encoding: ISO-8859-1 *** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK STUDY AND DIFFICULTIES OF MATHEMATICS *** Produced by Andrew D. Hwang. (This ebook was produced using OCR text generously provided by the University of California, Berkeley, through the Internet Archive.) transcriber's note The camera-quality files for this public-domain ebook may be downloaded gratis at www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/39088. This ebook was produced using scanned images and OCR text generously provided by the University of California at Berkeley through the Internet Archive. Punctuation in displayed equations has been regularized, and clear typographical errors have been corrected. Aside from this, every effort has been made to preserve the spelling, punctuation, and phrasing of the original. This PDF file is optimized for screen viewing, but may be recompiled for printing. Please consult the preamble of the LATEX source file for instructions and other particulars. ON THE STUDY AND DIFFICULTIES OF MATHEMATICS BY AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN THIRD REPRINT EDITION CHICAGO THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY LONDON Kegan Paul. Trench, Trubner¨ & Co., Ltd. 1910 EDITOR'S NOTE.
    [Show full text]
  • B,S Hm SOC:IE'i'\' Ffi I50 YEARS the BSHM-LMS 150Th Anniversilry De Morgan Day Saturday 9 May 201 5
    LONDON ( ^\ ['\T]{ ti \,t.\"f I I A [. b,s hm SOC:IE'I'\' ffi I50 YEARS The BSHM-LMS 150th Anniversilry De Morgan Day Saturday 9 May 201 5 Programme 10.00 Coffee and Registration 10.30 Opening of the Society Meeting l0:30 .,]clriAn [t ic:c, An Introduction to the Life and Work of Augustus De Morgan 1 1.30 ('hr'Ls t Iolii!_rgj, "A batch of observations & enquiries": the correspondence of Ada Lovelace and Augustus De Morgan 12.00 Skran l)cspcaux, Augustus De Morgan's 'Budget of Paradoxes' 1.00 Lunch Exhibition 2.00 .loltn Hcard, Augustus De Morgan and the Early History o.f the London Mathematical Society 3.00 Ian St*rart, Augustus De Morgan and George Boole 4.00 T.1 4.30 \\'illiicl I Iudgcs, The Influence o-f Augustus De Morgan 5.30 Close of meeting 5.30 Wine Reception 7.00 Society Dinner This meeting is organised in collaboration with the ll,':!i:'ir_S,,,e rci-r itir tirc liisr,rlr .'l \liilhcnl.riic: { I'rSi i \l :. I,ONDON I [,\-['H E, \, L{[I( ],\ L b,s hm S0C:I L,'I'\' # I50 YEARS Abstracts Adrian Rice An Introduction to the Life and Work of Augustus De Morgan Augustus De Morgan is remembered primarily for the pair of algebraic laws that bear his name, as well as for his formative association with the London Mathematical Society. But his career spanned a far greater array of interests and venues than his limited fame of today would suggest. In the last few decades, historical research has shed light on forgotten aspects of De Morgan's life and work to give us a more complete picture of the range and diversity of his mathematical activities, some of which will be discussed in more detail in subsequent talks.
    [Show full text]