AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN and the LOGIC of RELATIONS the New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN AND THE LOGIC OF RELATIONS The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 38 Series Editor: NORMAN KRETZMANN, Cornell University Associate Editors: DANIEL ELLIOT GARBER, University of Chicago SIMO KNUUTTILA, University of Helsinki RICHARD SORABJI, University of London Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Free University, Amsterdam ROGER ARIEW, Virginia Polytechnic Institute E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University of Waterloo MICHAEL AYERS, Wadham College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. J. HANKINSON, University of Texas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University, Finnish Academy PAUL HOFFMAN, Massachusetts Institute of Technology DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, University of Illinois, Chicago ALAIN DE LIBERA, Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes, Sorbonne DAVID FATE NORTON, McGill University LUCA OBERTELLO, Universita degli Studi di Genova ELEONORE STUMP, Virginia Polytechnic Institute ALLEN WOOD, Cornell University The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. DANIEL D. MERRILL Department of Philosophy, Oberlin College, USA AUGUSTUS DE MORGAN AND THE LOGIC OF RELATIONS KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS DORDRECHT I BOSTON I LONDON Library of Congress Cataloging. in·Publication Data Merrill, Daniel D. (Daniel Davy) Augustus De Morgan and the lOglC of relations / Daniel D. Merril. p. cm. -- <The New synthese historical library; 38) 1. De Morgan, Augustus, 1806-1871--Contributions in logic of relations. 2. Inference. 3. Syllogism. 4. Logic, Symbolic and mathematical--History--19th cenTury. I. Title. II. Series. BC185.M47 1990 160' .92--dc20 90-34935 ISBN·13: 978·94·010·7418·6 e-ISBN -13: 978-94-009-2047-7 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-009-2047-7 Published by Kluwer Academic Publishers, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands. KIuwer Academic Publishers incorporates the publishing programmes of D. Reidel, Martinus Nijhoff, Dr W. Junk and MTP Press. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Academic Publishers, 101 Philip Drive, Norwell, MA 02061, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, The Netherlands. Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved © 1990 Kluwer Academic Publishers Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover I st edition 1990 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE Vll CHAPTER 1. The Traditional Syllogism 1 1. Whately and the Revival of Formal Logic 2 2. Euclid and the Syllogism 10 3. Reid, Hamilton and Mansel on Relational Inferences 15 CHAPTER II. First Thoughts on the Copula 26 1. The Two Copulas 26 2. First Notions of Logic 35 3. Relations and Identity 43 CHAPTER III. Generalizing the Copula 48 1. The Abstract Copula 49 2. The Bicopular Syllogism and the Composition of Relations 60 3. Oblique Inferences and De Morgan's Dictum 79 CHAPTER IV The Problem of Form and Matter 89 1. "Sundry Perversions of the Syllogistic Form" 90 2. The Material Copula 95 3. De Morgan's Response 99 4. The Issues 103 5. Heads and Tails 110 CHAPTER V The Logic of Relations 113 1. Philosophical Preliminaries 114 2. General Logic of Relations 117 3. Properties of Relations 124 4. Singular Relational Syllogisms (Unit Syllogisms) 129 5. Quantified Relational Syllogisms 136 6. The Limited Unit Syllogism 143 7. The Ordinary Syllogism and the Relational Syllogism 145 v vi TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER VI. The Logic of Relations and the Theory of the Syllogism 149 1. The Two Views 150 2. Objective View-The Basic Account 151 3. Objective View-The Relational Form 156 4. The Subjective View 164 CHAPTER VII. Logic and Mathematics 170 1. "A Mathematical Logic" 170 2. Algebraic Techniques and Analogies in Logic 174 3. Logic and Geometrical Proof 176 4. Logic and Algebraic Reasoning 180 5. Form in Algebra and Logic 183 6. Conclusions 193 CHAPTER VIII. A Rigorous Formulation 196 1. Basic Issues 196 2. The System D 200 3. Properties of Inclusion and Identity 202 4. De Morgan's Basic Identities 206 5. Theorem K 208 6. Properties of Relations 212 7. Additional Inclusion Laws 217 8. The Full System of Three-Relation Terms 219 9. De Morgan's Logic with Identity 221 10. More Properties of Relations 223 11. A Surrogate for Quantification Theory 229 12. Postscript-1864 235 13. De Morgan's Conjectures 240 NOTES 245 INDEX 255 PREFACE The middle years of the nineteenth century saw two crucial develop ments in the history of modern logic: George Boole's algebraic treat ment of logic and Augustus De Morgan's formulation of the logic of relations. The former episode has been studied extensively; the latter, hardly at all. This is a pity, for the most central feature of modern logic may well be its ability to handle relational inferences. De Morgan was the first person to work out an extensive logic of relations, and the purpose of this book is to study this attempt in detail. Augustus De Morgan (1806-1871) was a British mathematician and logician who was Professor of Mathematics at the University of London (now, University College) from 1828 to 1866. A prolific but not highly original mathematician, De Morgan devoted much of his energies to the rather different field of logic. In his Formal Logic (1847) and a series of papers "On the Syllogism" (1846-1862), he attempted with great ingenuity to reformulate and extend the tradi tional syllogism and to systematize modes of reasoning that lie outside its boundaries. Chief among these is the logic of relations. De Mor gan's interest in relations culminated in his important memoir, "On the Syllogism: IV and on the Logic of Relations," read in 1860. De Morgan made important contributions to the study of the categorical syllogism, and he invented many novel notations and rules for this purpose. The sheer variety of his approaches to the syllogism give his work an almost chaotic quality, despite the systematic motiva tions behind it. In the course of these investigations, he introduced into logic the concept of the universe of discourse and rediscovered what have come to be called De Morgan's laws-e.g., that the comple ment of the intersection of two classes is the union of the complements of the two classes. De Morgan's greatest achievement in logic was undoubtedly his discovery of the logic of relations. Some earlier logicians, including Aristotle, had noted the existence of relational arguments, such as, "Every circle is a figure; therefore, anyone who draws a circle draws a figure." It appears, though, that De Morgan was the first logician to sense the pervasiveness of relational arguments and to see their systematic importance for logic. This belief in the importance of relational arguments led De Morgan to create much of the logic of relations as we know it today. He made vii viii PREFACE the fundamental discovery that relations could be compounded so that, for instance, one can compound the relations brother and parent to get their relative product, brother of a parent-i.e., uncle. Once this and other forms of relational composition are introduced, a vast array of inferences comes into view. Among them is the inference which De Morgan called Theorem K, which states that if the product of a relation L with a relation M is included in a relation N, then the product of the complement of N with the converse of M is included in the complement of L. This means that the statement "Every brother of a parent of a person is an uncle of that person," implies "Every non-uncle of a child of a person is a non-brother of that person." De Morgan was also the first person to study the properties of relations, such as transitivity and symmetry (which he called con vertibility). Once again, complex logical inferences abound. De Mor gan notes, for instance, that the transitivity of the ancestor relation implies that "Among non-descendents are contained all ancestors of non-descendents. " Such inferences are hardly trivial, and De Morgan's memoir on the logic of relations is filled with similar examples. We must admire not only his ingenuity in constructing the logic of relations but also his ear for valid inferences. The logic of relations has long since been incorporated into quantifi cation theory, but it remains of interest in its own right. For De Morgan, it was as if he had discovered a new logical world. After developing this new logic, he proclaimed, "And thus in logic, as in mathematics, the horizon opens with the height gained: generalization suggests detail, which again suggests generalization, and so on ad injinitum"(S4,235). While realizing the great importance of the logic of relations for later developments in logic, it is important to place De Morgan's pioneering work in the context of his own thought. This is one of the main objectives of this book. We will see how De Morgan's logic of relations grew out of two idiosyncratic features of his thought: an analysis of propositions which turned all categorical propositions into relational propositions; and the resulting attempt to work out syllogis tic logic within the framework of the logic of relations. This framework both motivated and limited De Morgan's logic of relations. Chapter One sets the stage. I first consider some central features of Archbishop Whately'S Elements of Logic (1826), which is often cre- PREFACE ix dited with restoring the study of formal logic in Great Britain.