The Market As a Legal Concept

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Market As a Legal Concept University of Colorado Law School Colorado Law Scholarly Commons Articles Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship 2012 The Market as a Legal Concept Justin Desautels-Stein University of Colorado Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.law.colorado.edu/articles Part of the Antitrust and Trade Regulation Commons, Constitutional Law Commons, Jurisprudence Commons, and the Law and Economics Commons Citation Information Justin Desautels-Stein, The Market as a Legal Concept, 60 BUFF. L. REV. 387 (2012), available at https://scholar.law.colorado.edu/articles/136. Copyright Statement Copyright protected. Use of materials from this collection beyond the exceptions provided for in the Fair Use and Educational Use clauses of the U.S. Copyright Law may violate federal law. Permission to publish or reproduce is required. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Colorado Law Faculty Scholarship at Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of Colorado Law Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. +(,121/,1( Citation: 60 Buff. L. Rev. 387 2012 Provided by: William A. Wise Law Library Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline Tue Feb 28 10:03:24 2017 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License -- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. -- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your HeinOnline license, please use: Copyright Information ARTICLES The Market as a Legal Concept JUSTIN DESAUTELS-STEINt INTRODUCTION ......................................... 388 I. LIBERAL LEGALISM: THREE STYLES ............... 398 A. The Classic Liberal Style: The Law of Competition. ........................... 398 1. The Passing of English Feudalism.... ..... 401 2. John Locke's "Very Natural Doctrine"...........410 B. The Modern Liberal Style: The Law of Control ............................... 423 1. The Ascent of Trusts and Antitrust...............428 2. "The Ethics of Competition"...............437 C. The Neoliberal Style: The Law of Competition Revisited.. ....................... 444 II. A CRITIQUE OF LIBERAL LEGALISM ............... 459 A. A Critique of the Market/State Distinction.....461 B. A Critique of Propertyand Contract.... .... 465 t Associate Professor, University of Colorado Law School. I received helpful comments from Paulo Barrozo, Hal Bruff, Kristen Carpenter, Amy Cohen, Michael Fahkri, Vic Fleischer, John Haskell, Bernard Harcourt, Peter Huang, Derek Kiernan-Johnson, Steve Medema, Martha McCluskey, Fernanda Nicola, Helen Norton, Jeff Pojanowski, Pierre Schlag, Jack Schlegel, Spencer Weber Waller, Ahmed White, Steve Winter, and participants in faculty colloquia and conferences at American University's Washington College of Law, Boston College Law School, the University of Colorado Law School, and Wayne State School of Law. 387 388 BUFFALO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 60 C. A Critique of Legal Consciousness.... ..... 477 CONCLUSION................................................485 INTRODUCTION Writing thirty-three years ago in the pages of this journal, Duncan Kennedy made the troubling claim that the entire landscape of American Legal Thought was in the shadow of a "fundamental contradiction."' This contradiction was an aspect of the political philosophy associated with thinkers like Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Immanuel Kant, Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, and John Rawls,2 and it involved the basic problem of relating individual freedom to a coercive sovereign.3 Liberalism, as that famous philosophy came to be called, had its origins in an epic battle against an ancient theory of justice and social organization, wherein the new believers asserted a kind of autonomy and subjectivity rooted in an idea about individualism.' The foundational liberal move, however, was to argue that this new individualism, and the freedom and equality that would come with it, could only be realized when men were willing to renounce their natural freedoms in exchange for a regulated and ordered life under a 1. Duncan Kennedy, The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries, 28 BUFF. L. REV. 205, 213 (1979). Five years later, in a piece co-authored with Peter Gabel, Kennedy renounced the fundamental contradiction: "First of all, I renounce the fundamental contradiction. I recant it, and I also recant the whole idea of individualism and altruism, and the idea of legal consciousness . I really see the fundamental contradiction these days as a lifeless slogan .... " Peter Gabel & Duncan Kennedy, Roll Over Beethoven, 36 STAN. L. REV. 1, 15-16 (1984). Almost thirty years later, my own view is that Kennedy has now renounced that renunciation. 2. For two "modern classics" in the spirit of the "fundamental contradiction" and addressing many of these authors, see MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI, FROM APOLOGY TO UTOPIA: THE STRUCTURE OF INTERNATIONAL LEGAL ARGUMENT 52-54 (1989); ROBERTO MANGABEIRA UNGER, KNOWLEDGE & POLITICS 118 (1975). 3. Kennedy, supra note 1, at 213. 4. See, e.g., PIERRE MANENT, AN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY OF LIBERALISM 115- 16 (Rebecca Balinski trans., Princeton Univ. Press 1994) (1987). 2012] THE MARKET AS A LEGAL CONCEPT 389 collective and coercive power.' Consequently, here was the fundamental contradiction: in order to experience a life of meaningful freedom, we have to give up our "natural" freedom to a supreme authority of law.6 Kennedy claimed that all law in the western tradition was dominated by liberalism, and that every legal problem was in a way a kind of liberal problem.' Referring to the liberal contest between individual freedom and state control, Kennedy stated: [I]t is not only an aspect, but the very essence of every [legal] problem. There simply are no legal issues that do not involve directly the problem of the legitimate content of collective coercion, since there is by definition no legal problem until someone has at least imagined that he might invoke the force of the state.8 That is, in Kennedy's view, all law was liberal, and to suggest that some law could exist outside of this tradition, at least in the developed North Atlantic capitalist states, was to suggest a sort of discourse that we might not even recognize as operating in the language of law. Over the last thirty or forty years, "totalizing" claims about the legal system have come in and out of fashion.' 5. See Kennedy, supra note 1, at 211-12. Classic liberal political theorists have offered varying reasons for how and why freedom would be realized in this way. Hobbes, for example, believed that in the natural condition of mankind, human beings possessed an ultimate right of self-preservation subject to no higher authority. THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN 66 (Dutton 1965) (1651). That is, every individual was free to determine for himself just what was necessary for his own survival, and that such determinations were not moral in any meaningful sense. The problem, as is well known, was that Hobbes saw this all- powerful natural right as the source of social strife, pushing men into a constant state of war and fear. Id. at 67. In order to be truly and actually free, Hobbes argued for a renunciation of that basic natural right of self-preservation in exchange for the order guaranteed by a political sovereign, i.e., the Leviathan. Id. at 89-90. 6. See Kennedy, supra note 1, at 211-12. 7. Id. at 213. 8. Id. 9. Jacques Derrida is representative: Thus it has always been thought that the center [of a totalizing structure], which is by definition unique, constituted that very thing within a structure which while governing the structure, escapes 390 BUFFALO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 60 Critical legal studies bloomed, only to struggle against the onset of rival forms of critical thought,"o and then apparently shrink in the bright lights of a burgeoning law and economics movement," not to mention the ascendance of a new and mighty form of legal consciousness: legal pragmatism. 2 Today, a full generation later, Kennedy's structurality. This is why classical thought concerning structure could say that the center is, paradoxically, within the structure and outside it. The center is at the center of the totality, and yet, since the center does not belong to the totality (is not part of the totality), the totality has its center elsewhere. The center is not the center. JACQUES DERRIDA, Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences, in WRITING AND DIFFERENCE 278, 279 (Alan Bass, trans., Univ. of Chicago Press 1978) (1967). 10. Two examples would include developments within critical legal studies itself, casting skepticism on the notion of the fundamental contradiction, and later, critical race theory. For a sample of the literature on critical race theory, see DERRICK BELL, FACES AT THE BOTTOM OF THE WELL: THE PERMANENCE OF RACISM (1993); CRITICAL RACE THEORY: THE KEY WRITINGS THAT FORMED THE MOVEMENT (Kimberl6 Crenshaw et al. eds., 1995) (explaining developments, early and late, in critical race theory); Ian F. Haney L6pez, "A Nation of Minorities"-Race, Ethnicity, and Reactionary Colorblindness, 59 STAN. L. REV. 985 (2007) (discussing the role of race in subordination and the history of colorblindness in law); Athena D. Mutua, The Rise, Development, and Future Directions of Critical Race Theory and Related Scholarship, 84 DENV. U. L. REV. 329, 330 (2006) ("[Clritical race theory . rises, in part,
Recommended publications
  • Twelve Fallacies of the “Neo-Antitrust” Movement
    TWELVE FALLACIES OF THE “NEO-ANTITRUST” MOVEMENT Seth B. Sacher John M. Yun Antonin Scalia Law School, George Mason University George Mason University Law & Economics Research Paper Series 19-12 This paper is available on the Social Science Research Network at ssrn.com/abstract=3369013 TWELVE FALLACIES OF THE “NEO-ANTITRUST” MOVEMENT Seth B. Sachera and John M. Yunb Antonin Scalia Law School George Mason University May 1, 2019 Abstract Antitrust enforcement is back in the spotlight with advocates from both the political left and the populist political right demanding fundamental competition policy changes. While there are differences among those calling for such changes, several common beliefs generally unite them. This includes a contention that the writings and interpretations of Robert Bork and the Chicago School of economics have led antitrust astray in a manner fundamentally inconsistent with the original intent of the Sherman Act. Further, they are united by a belief that recent empirical, economic studies indicate the economy is becoming overly concentrated, that market power has been increasing dramatically, that performance in many, if not most, markets has been deficient, and that too much profit is going to too few firms. In this article, we identify and detail twelve fallacies of what we call the “neo-antitrust movement” and their associated claims. At the heart of these fallacies is a fundamental misunderstanding of economics and the consumer welfare standard that has been at the heart of competition policy since at least the 1960s. Additionally, there is a heavy reliance on studies that, upon closer scrutiny, do not support the positions of those who cite them.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Introduction
    1 Introduction The Australian Energy Market Agreement (AEMA) establishes a process for the Australian Energy Market Commission (AEMC or ‘the Commission’) to assess and provide advice to the Ministerial Council on Energy (MCE) on competition in the retail electricity and natural gas markets of jurisdictions for the purpose of phasing out retail price regulation where effective retail competition is demonstrated (clause 14.11).1 1.1 Revisions to Statement of Approach In response to a request for advice by the MCE, this Statement of Approach sets out the proposed methodology and consultation approach the AEMC will adopt in conducting the retail competition reviews. The AEMC has previously prepared and published versions of the Statement of Approach which have been applied to the retail competition reviews undertaken in Victoria in 2007, South Australia in 2008 and the Australian Capital Territory in 2010. Over time, the MCE, in consultation with the AEMC, has periodically approved revisions and updates to the Statement of Approach to reflect developments and reforms in energy markets and revised timings of the AEMC’s remaining jurisdictional reviews. This latest MCE approved version of the Statement of Approach has been prepared for application to the New South Wales retail competition review in 2012-13. 1.2 Scope The scope of the competition reviews is set out in clauses 14.11(a) and (c) of the AEMA (see Appendix A). According to the AEMA, the aim of the competition reviews is to assess the effectiveness of competition in the electricity and gas retail markets for the purpose of the retention, removal or reintroduction of retail energy price controls.
    [Show full text]
  • Shattering and Moving Beyond the Gutenberg Paradigm: the Dawn of the Electronic Will
    University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform Volume 42 2008 Shattering and Moving Beyond the Gutenberg Paradigm: The Dawn of the Electronic Will Joseph Karl Grant Capital University Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjlr Part of the Estates and Trusts Commons, and the Science and Technology Law Commons Recommended Citation Joseph K. Grant, Shattering and Moving Beyond the Gutenberg Paradigm: The Dawn of the Electronic Will, 42 U. MICH. J. L. REFORM 105 (2008). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mjlr/vol42/iss1/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. SHATTERING AND MOVING BEYOND THE GUTENBERG PARADIGM: THE DAWN OF THE ELECTRONIC WILL Joseph Karl Grant* INTRODUCTION Picture yourself watching a movie. In the film, a group of four siblings are dressed in dark suits and dresses. The siblings, Bill Jones, Robert Jones, Margaret Jones and Sally Johnson, have just returned from their elderly mother's funeral. They sit quietly in their mother's attorney's office intently watching and listening to a videotape their mother, Ms. Vivian Jones, made before her death. On the videotape, Ms. Jones expresses her last will and testament. Ms. Jones clearly states that she would like her sizable real estate holdings to be divided equally among her four children and her valuable blue-chip stock investments to be used to pay for her grandchildren's education.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparative Market Structures in Developing Countries
    380. 141 LI7" M671 No. 75 i"J- _ , Comparative Market Structures In Developing Countries by Marvin Miracle The University of Wisconsin LAND TENURE CENTER Madison, Wisconsin 53706 Comparative Market Structures in Developing Countries. 380.14i Wisconsir Uniro Lard Tenure Center. NTIS M671 Comparative Market Structures in Devel­ j)b oping'hp. Cou;triesoMarvh-7 P. Miracle. 19'0° I-,r /0L6 Bibliographic footnotes. C LTC Repriit -,o, 75. i. Markets. 2. Capital markets. 3. Marketing - Agricultural commodities, I. Miracle, Marvin P. IT. Title. Reprinted from Nebraska Journal of Economics and Business, Vol. 9, No. 4, Autumn 1970. Copyright by the University of Nebraska, 1970 COMPARATIVE MARKET STRUCTURES IN DEVELOPING COUNTRIES* Marvin Miracle Associate Professor,Departmentof AgriculturalEconomics and Chairman,African Studies Program Universityof Wisconsin Market structures in developing countries arc of interest for a number of reasons. Apart from the possibility that market structure may have an important impact on the rate of economic growth-a possibility that will not be explored here-market structure is of interest because it clearly affects the distribution of income, a subject that is increasingly of interest among those working on the problems of developing countries. It is also of interest because economic theory has its widest applications when per­ fect competition can be assumed. In fact, in absence of evidence to the contrary, something close to perfect competition is nearly always assumed by planners in developing countries. The literature on market structures in developing countries-which are here defined to exclude Communist-bloc countries-is relatively thin, un­ usually widely scattered, and so far has resulted in few insights as to the impact of market structure on the pace and character of economic devel­ opment.
    [Show full text]
  • Entrepreneurship in Regulated Markets: Burden Or Boon?
    Entrepreneurship in regulated markets: Burden or boon? Chair: Vickie Gibbs, Executive Director, Entrepreneurship Center, UNC Kenan-Flagler Business School Panelists: Susan Cates, Partner, Leeds Equity Partners, LLC Chris Elmore, Community Evangelist, AvidXchange Eric Ghysels, Faculty Director, Rethinc. Labs; Edward Bernstein Distinguished Professor of Economics, UNC-Chapel Hill; Professor of Finance, UNC Kenan-Flagler Business School Bill Starling, CEO, Synecor Regulatory barriers to entry can distort markets and limit innovation, but also result in breakthrough business models facing less competition. Examples include fintech, medtech and edtech. This session examined the challenges specific to entrepreneurship and innovation in regulated industries. Bill Starling started the session by describing the regulatory complexities of the medtech market. Food and Drug Administration (FDA) approval for medical device products can sometimes take more than a decade. For example, approval for the TAVR heart valve replacement device took 17 years and $2 billion in funding. One strategy for ventures is to minimize the number of approvals required to bring a product to market. For example, iRhythm focused on the unmet customer need for an affordable way to detect heart conditions. The company created a simple, bandage-like device that collected data about the heart, which allowed them to avoid regulatory scrutiny. Even so, the product required $100 million to complete the clinical trials. Starling closed by noting that regulated markets are difficult to enter, but once a venture successfully enters the market, it can do very well and find protected positions. Susan Cates provided perspective as both a business operator and as an investor within education. Cates believes that success in regulated markets often requires “nontraditional thinking inside traditional institutions.” Cates described the “stroke of the pen” risks and tailwinds that can occur when policymakers pass new laws or provide regulatory guidance.
    [Show full text]
  • Effective Competition and Corporate Disclosure A
    EFFECTIVE COMPETITION AND CORPORATE DISCLOSURE A CRITICAL STUDY by RAZAHUSSEIN M, DEVJI B. Sc. (Econ)», University of London, 1961 Barrister-at-Law, Honourable Society of Middle Temple, London, 1962 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF BUSINESS ADMINISTRATION In the Faculty of Graduate Studies We accept this thesis as conforming to the required staricTardT THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA September, 1968 In presenting this thesis in partial ful• filment of the requirements for an advanced degree at the University of British Columbia, I agree that the Library shall make it freely available for reference and study* I further agree that permission for ex• tensive copying of this thesis for scholarly purposes may be granted by the Head of my Department or by his representatives. It is understood that copying or publication of this thesis for financial gain shall not be allowed without my written permission. Faculty of Commerce and Business Administration, The University of British Columbia, Vancouver 8, B. C. Canada. ABSTRACT Economic activity in the United States and Canada is predominantly performed by corporations. They are by far the largest private employers of workers, the biggest investors and the predominant instrument of production. They are rapidly growing in size, are generating sufficient funds internally to carry out most of their expansion programs, and are diversifying into unrelated activities. Their affairs are increasingly managed by professional executives who have little, if any, stake In the risk capital. The shareholders, who are legally pre• sumed to exercise control over the powers and actions of corporate executives, are normally too numerous and scattered so as not to be in a position to have a significant influence on the policies of the corporations.
    [Show full text]
  • American Political Thought: Readings and Materials Keith E. Whittington
    American Political Thought: Readings and Materials Keith E. Whittington Index of Materials for Companion Website 2. The Colonial Era, Before 1776 II. Democracy and Liberty John Adams, Letter to James Sullivan (1776) John Cotton, The Bloudy Tenent Washed and Made White (1647) John Cotton, Letter to Lord Say and Seal (1636) Jacob Duche, The Duty of Standing Fast in Our Spiritual and Temporal Liberties (1775) Massachusetts Body of Liberties (1641) James Otis, Rights of the British Colony Asserted and Proved (1764) Elisha Williams, The Essential Rights and Liberties of Protestants (1744) Roger Williams, The Bloudy Tenent Yet More Bloudy (1652) John Winthrop, Arbitrary Government Described (1644) John Winthrop, A Defense of an Order of Court (1637) John Winthrop, Defense of the Negative Vote (1643) III. Citizenship and Community Agreement among the Settlers of Exeter, New Hampshire (1639) Combination of the Inhabitants of the Piscataqua River for Government (1641) Robert Cushman, The Sin and Danger of Self-Love (1621) Fundamental Agreement, or Original Constitution of the Colony of New Haven (1639) Fundamental Orders of Connecticut (1639) Patrick Henry, Give Me Liberty Speech (1775) William Livingston, “The Vanity of Birth and Titles” (1753) Oath of a Freeman in Massachusetts Bay (1632) Thomas Tryon, The Planter’s Speech to His Neighbors and Countrymen (1684) IV. Equality and Status Address of the Mechanics of New York City (1776) Jonathan Boucher, Sermon on the Peace (1763) Charles Inglis, The True Interest of America (1776) William Knox, Three Tracts Respecting the Conversion (1768) William Byrd, Letter to Lord Egmont (1736) Samuel Sewall, The Selling of Joseph (1700) John Saffin, A Brief and Candid Answer (1701) John Woolman Some Considerations on Keeping Negroes (1762) V.
    [Show full text]
  • Markets Not Capitalism Explores the Gap Between Radically Freed Markets and the Capitalist-Controlled Markets That Prevail Today
    individualist anarchism against bosses, inequality, corporate power, and structural poverty Edited by Gary Chartier & Charles W. Johnson Individualist anarchists believe in mutual exchange, not economic privilege. They believe in freed markets, not capitalism. They defend a distinctive response to the challenges of ending global capitalism and achieving social justice: eliminate the political privileges that prop up capitalists. Massive concentrations of wealth, rigid economic hierarchies, and unsustainable modes of production are not the results of the market form, but of markets deformed and rigged by a network of state-secured controls and privileges to the business class. Markets Not Capitalism explores the gap between radically freed markets and the capitalist-controlled markets that prevail today. It explains how liberating market exchange from state capitalist privilege can abolish structural poverty, help working people take control over the conditions of their labor, and redistribute wealth and social power. Featuring discussions of socialism, capitalism, markets, ownership, labor struggle, grassroots privatization, intellectual property, health care, racism, sexism, and environmental issues, this unique collection brings together classic essays by Cleyre, and such contemporary innovators as Kevin Carson and Roderick Long. It introduces an eye-opening approach to radical social thought, rooted equally in libertarian socialism and market anarchism. “We on the left need a good shake to get us thinking, and these arguments for market anarchism do the job in lively and thoughtful fashion.” – Alexander Cockburn, editor and publisher, Counterpunch “Anarchy is not chaos; nor is it violence. This rich and provocative gathering of essays by anarchists past and present imagines society unburdened by state, markets un-warped by capitalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Indiana Magazine of History
    INDIANA MAGAZINE OF HISTORY ’Volume XLV SEPTEMBER,1949 Number 3 The Heroic Age of the Social Sciences Robert S. Fletcher* History, political theory, and economics were not wholly neglected even in the colonial colleges. But history was chiefly treated as the handmaiden of theology and the Greek and Latin classics, while economic and political matters were dealt with in the courses in moral philosophy and ethics. The American Revolution and the experience of constitu- tion-making gave a great impetus to the study of politics. In 1779, Thomas Jefferson was instrumental in bringing about a notable revision of the curriculum of William and Mary College whereby more emphasis was placed upon political studies; by 1792 a knowIedge of “NationaI Law, Law of Nations, and the general principles of politics” was required for graduation. Other colleges followed this example. In the two succeeding generations the Federalist was listed as a text in many catalogs, and Locke, Rousseau, Montesquieu, and the Declaration of Independence were often included in required reading. New books on moral philosophy appeared with an ex- panded political emphasis. In 1795 a professor at Columbia published a Systematic Treatise on Moral Philosophy: Com- prehending the Law of Nature-Ethics-Natural Jurispru- dence-General Economy-Politics-and the Lnw of Nations which he optimistically hoped would “inflame the American youth with a true love for their country.”’ The first rumblings of the industrial revolution produced a greater emphasis on economics (or political economy, as it wag called). Adam Smith’s famous but wordy and difficult *Robert S. Fletcher is .a member of the history department at Oberlin College, Oberlin Oho.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Consciousness Studies According to Susan Silbey: Dissonance Between Empirical Data and Theoretical Resources?
    Legal Consciousness Studies according to Susan Silbey: Dissonance between Empirical Data and Theoretical Resources? Jacques Commaille Institut des Sciences sociales du Politique (ISP/ ENS Paris-Saclay – Université Paris Nanterre), Bâtiment Laplace, 61 avenue du Président Wilson, F-94235 Cachan cedex. <[email protected]> * Translated by Benn Williams Résumé Les Legal Consciousness Studies selon Susan Silbey : une dissonance entre données empiriques et ressources théoriques ? À la lecture des observations de Susan Silbey tirées des entretiens réalisés, laissant notamment entrevoir des capacités de résistance de la part des citoyens ordinaires, la question est posée dans le présent article de la perti- nence de la formulation d’un constat général qui reste celui d’une « legal hegemony » s’imposant massivement. Un tel positionnement conduit alors Susan Silbey à solliciter des théories européennes valorisant exclusivement cette idée d’hégémonie, de systèmes de domination et de « fausse cons- cience ». La conséquence est que ne sont pas véritablement prises en compte d’autres théories fondées précisément sur la thèse selon laquelle les acteurs sociaux, y compris les plus dominés, sont susceptibles de s’opposer et, pour cela, de s’approprier le droit comme instrument de résistance. Contradiction entre empirie et théorie – Domination versus résistance – Legal hegemony – Théories européennes. Summary Reading Susan Silbey’s observations pulled from completed interviews, notably allowing glimpses into the capacity for resistance
    [Show full text]
  • Annotated Presentation of Regulated Markets and National Provisions
    15.7.2011 EN Official Journal of the European Union C 209/21 Annotated presentation of regulated markets and national provisions implementing relevant requirements of MiFID (Directive 2004/39/EC of the European Parliament and of the Council) (2011/C 209/13) Article 47 of the Markets in Financial Instruments Directive (Directive 2004/39/EC, OJ L 145, 30.4.2004) authorises each Member State to confer the status of ‘regulated market’ on those markets constituted on its territory and which comply with its regulations. Article 4, paragraph 1, point 14 of Directive 2004/39/EC defines a ‘regulated market’ as a multilateral system operated and/or managed by a market operator, which brings together or facilitates the bringing together of multiple third-party buying and selling interests in financial instruments — in the system and in accordance with its non-discretionary rules — in a way that results in a contract, in respect of the financial instruments admitted to trading under its rules and/or systems, and which is authorised and functions regularly and in accordance with the provisions of Title III of Directive 2004/39/EC. Article 47 of Directive 2004/39/EC requires that each Member State maintains an updated list of regulated markets authorised by it. This information should be communicated to other Member States and the European Commission. Under the same article (Article 47 of Directive 2004/39/EC), the Commission is required to publish a list of regulated markets, notified to it, on a yearly basis in the Official Journal of the European Union. The present list has been compiled pursuant to this requirement.
    [Show full text]
  • Abstention and the Constitutional Limits of the Judicial Power of the United States Calvin R
    University of California, Hastings College of the Law UC Hastings Scholarship Repository Faculty Scholarship 1991 Abstention and the Constitutional Limits of the Judicial Power of the United States Calvin R. Massey UC Hastings College of the Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.uchastings.edu/faculty_scholarship Recommended Citation Calvin R. Massey, Abstention and the Constitutional Limits of the Judicial Power of the United States, 1991 Brigham Young University Law Review 811 (1991). Available at: http://repository.uchastings.edu/faculty_scholarship/1128 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Abstention and the Constitutional Limits of the Judicial Power of the United States Calvin R. Massey* I. INTRODUCTION The federal courts have by now firmly established a variety of doctrines by which they decline to exercise jurisdiction vested in them by Congress. The constitutional validity of these "ab- stention" doctrines has been challenged in recent years by Pro- fessor Martin Redish, who contends that "[j]udge-made absten- tion constitutes judicial lawmaking of the most sweeping nature."1 He characterizes the abstention doctrines "as a judicial usurpation of legislative authority, in violation of the principle of separation of powers."'2 To Professor Redish, judicial con- struction of "a jurisdictional statute that somehow vests a power in the federal courts to adjudicate the relevant claims without a corresponding duty to do so is unacceptable." 3 Redish's intellec- tual cohort, Professor Donald Doernberg, establishes the same point by invoking more directly the familiar admonition of Chief Justice Marshall in Cohens v.
    [Show full text]