1 the Science of Epicurus BIBLIOGRAPHY By

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 the Science of Epicurus BIBLIOGRAPHY By The Science of Epicurus BIBLIOGRAPHY By Melania Cassan & Chiara Rover 1. Epicurus’ Primary Sources (Critical Editions, Collections of Texts, Translations and Commentaries). - Epicurus’ Complete Works. Arrighetti, G. (a cura di) (1973 ). Epicuro: Opere. Torino: Einaudi (New revised and expanded edition; I ed. 1960). Bignone, E. (a cura di) (1920). Epicuro: Opere, frammenti, testimonianze sulla sua vita. Bari: Laterza (reprinted in 1964, Roma: L’Erma di Bretschneider). Diano, C. (ed.) (1946). Epicuri Ethica. Firenze: Sansoni. Indelli, G. (2002). «Addenda agli Epicurea di Usener». SIFC, 20/1-2, 95-103. Inwood, B.; Gerson, L.P. (eds) (1994). The Epicurus Reader: Selected Writings and Testimonia. Introduction by D. S. Hutchinson. Indianapolis: Hackett. Isnardi Parente, M. (a cura di) (1983). Opere di Epicuro. Torino: UTET. Krautz, H.-W. (Hrsg.) (2001). Epikur: Briefe, Sprüche, Werkfragmente, Griechisch/Deutsch. Stuttgart: Reclam. Long, A.A.; Sedley, D.N. (eds) (1987). The Hellenistic philosophers, 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Long, A.A. (1986). Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoic, Epicureans, Sceptics. Berkeley-Los Angeles: University of California Press; Ital. transl. (1997). La filosofia ellenistica: Stoici, epicurei, scettici. Bologna: Il Mulino. [https://www.ucpress.edu/book/9780520058088/hellenistic-philosophy#about-book] [https://www.mulino.it/isbn/9788815061560] Sammartano, R. (a cura di) (1959). Epicuro, Etica. Opere e frammenti. In append. la Vita di Epicuro di Diogene Laerzio. Bologna: Cappelli. Usener, H. (Hrsg.) (1887). Epicurea. Lipsiae: Teubner (reprinted in 1963, Roma: L’Erma di Bretschneider; in 1966, Stutgardiae: Teubner; in 2002, Milano: Bompiani, with Ital. transl.; in 1969, Padova: CEDAM, with Ital. transl., without Greek text). [https://archive.org/stream/HermannUsenerEpicurea1887/Hermann%20Usener%20- %20Epicurea%20%281887%29#page/n11/mode/2up] Usener, H. (1977). Glossarium Epicureum. Edendum curaverunt M. Gigante et W. Schmid. Roma: Olschki. - Epicurus’ On Nature Arrighetti, G. (1956). «Un papiro inedito del Περὶ φύσεως di Epicuro (Papiro Ercolanese 1431)». SCO, 6, 175- 93. 1 [https://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/24172411.pdf] Arrighetti, G. (1957). «Epicuro, περὶ φύσεως β ̓». ASNP Serie II, 26, 26-53. Arrighetti, G. (1957). «Un papiro inedito del Περι φύσεως di Epicuro (PHerc. 1431)». SCO, 6, 175-93. [https://www.jstor.org/stable/24172411?seq=1#metadata_info_tab_contents] Arrighetti, G. (1959). «A proposito di alcuni papiri del Περι φύσεως di Epicuro». Philologus, 103, 39-52. Arrighetti, G. (1971). «L’opera Sulla natura di Epicuro». CErc, 1, 41-56. Arrighetti, G. (1975). «L’opera Sulla natura e le lettere di Epicuro a Erodoto e a Pitocle». CErc, 5, 39-51. Arrighetti, G. (1979). «Un passo dell’opera Sulla natura di Epicuro, Democrito e Colote». CErc, 9, 5-10. Arrighetti, G.; Cantarella, R. (1972). «Il libro Sul tempo (PHerc. 1413) dell’opera di Epicuro Sulla natura». CErc, 2, 5-46. Arrighetti, G.; Gigante, M. (1977). «Frammenti del libro undicesimo Della natura di Epicuro (PHerc. 1042)». CErc, 7, 5-8. Balaudé, J.-F. (éd.) (1994). Épicure : Lettres, maximes, sentences. Paris: Librairie Générale Française. Barigazzi, A. (1949). «La μονή della terra nei frammenti ercolanesi del libro XI del Περι φύσεως di Epicuro». SIFC, 24, 3-19. Cantarella, R. (1955). «Dal Papiro Ercolanese 1413». Acme, 8/2-3, 57-8. Cantarella, R. (1957). «Dal Papiro Ercolanese 1413». Krókowski, G.; Steffen, V.; Strzelecki, L. (eds). Symbolae R. Taubenschlag dedicatae III. Wroclaw: Ossolineum, 77-81. Cantarella, R. (1966). «Il Papiro Ercolanese 1413». Atti dell’XI Congresso Internazionale di Papirologia, Milano 2-8 settembre 1965. Milano: Istituto Lombardo di Scienze e Lettere, 595. Damiani, V. (2015). Rev. to Leone, G. (2012). Epicuro, Sulla natura, libro II. Edizione, traduzione e commento. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Eikasmos, 26, 436-43. Danella, P. (2001). «I segni in alcuni papiri Della natura di Epicuro». Andorlini, I. (a cura di). Atti del XXII congresso internazionale di papirologia, Firenze, 23-29 agosto 1998. Firenze: Istituto Papirologico G. Vitelli, 301-20. D’Angelo, A. (2001). «Epicuro, Περὶ χρόνου (PHerc. 1413): nuove letture». Andorlini, I. (a cura di). Atti del XXII congresso internazionale di papirologia, Firenze, 23-29 agosto 1998. Firenze: Istituto Papirologico G. Vitelli, 321-9. Del Mastro, G. (2011). «PHerc. 1416, cr. 5: tre pezzi del papiro Sul tempo (PHerc. 1413)». CErc 41, 27-32. Del Mastro, G. (2013). «A proposito del ΠΕΡΙ ΦΥΣΕΩΣ di Epicuro: il XXI libro e un nuovo papiro (PHerc. 362 e 560)». Lexicon Philosophicum, 1, 179-91. [http://lexicon.cnr.it/index.php/LP/article/view/103/120] Dorandi, T. (2015). «Libri dell’opera Sulla natura in più esemplari». Masi, F.G.; Maso, S. (eds). Epicurus on Eidola. Peri Phuseos Book II. Update, Proposals, and Discussions. Amsterdam: Hakkert, 17-34. Dorandi, T. (2015). «Modi e modelli di trasmissione dell’opera Sulla natura di Epicuro». De Sanctis, D; Spinelli, E.; Tulli, M.; Verde, F. (a cura di). Questioni epicuree. Sankt Augustin: Akademia Verlag, 15-52. 2 Giannantoni, G. (1983). «La polemica antimegarica nel XXVIII libro Della natura di Epicuro». CErc, 13, 15- 9. Isnardi Parente, M. (1976). «Χρόνος ἐπινοούμενος e χρόνος οὐ νοούμενος in Epicuro, PHerc. 1413». PP, 31, 168-75. Laks, A. (1981). « Une légèreté de Démocrite (Epicurus, De natura liber incertus 34.30, 7-15 Arrighetti2) ». CErc, 11, 19-23. Laursen, S. (1987). “Epicurus, On Nature Book XXV”. CErc, 17, 77-8. Laursen, S. (1988). “Epicurus, On Nature XXV (Long-Sedley 20,B,C, and j)”. CErc, 18, 7-18. Laursen, S. (1992). “The Summary of Epicurus On Nature Book 25”. Capasso, M. (a cura di). Papiri letterari greci e latini. Galatina: Congedo, 141-54. Laursen, S. (1995). “The Early Parts of Epicurus, On Nature, 25th Book”. CErc, 25, 5-109. Laursen, S. (1997). “The Later Parts of Epicurus, On Nature, 25th Book”. CErc, 27, 5-82. Leone, G. (1984). «Epicuro, Della natura, libro XIV». CErc, 14, 17-107. Leone, G. (1987). «La chiusa del XIV libro Della natura di Epicuro». CErc, 17, 49-76. Leone, G. (1988). «Achille Vogliano editore di Epicuro». CErc, 18, 149-91. Leone, G. (1988). «Il II libro Della natura di Epicuro (PHerc. 1149/993 e 1010). Problemi testuali ed esegetici». Mandilaras, V.G. (ed.). Proceedings of the XVIIIth International Congress of Papyrology, Athens 25-31 May 1986. Athens: Greek Papyrological Society. Leone, G. (1993). «Strutture concettuali del II libro Della natura di Epicuro (PHerc. 1149/993 e 1010)». Franchi dell’Orto, L. (a cura di). Ercolano 1738-1988: 250 anni di ricerca archeologica. Atti del Convegno Internazionale, Ravello-Ercolano-Napoli-Pompei, 30 ottobre-5 novembre 1988. Roma: L’Erma di Bretschneider, 307-12. Leone, G. (2000). «Epicuro fondatore del Giardino e l’opera sua conservata nei papiri». CErc, 30, 21-33. Leone, G. (2002). «Epicuro, Della natura, libro XXXIV (PHerc. 1431)». CErc, 32, 7-135. Leone, G. (2002). «Nuove conferme dall’opera Della natura di Epicuro alla valenza tecnica del gruppo semantico ἕτοιμος/ἑτοίμως nella dottrina epicurea dei pori». SIFC, 20/1-2, 104-18. Leone, G. (2003). «Rileggendo il XXVIII libro Della natura di Epicuro: riflessioni e proposte». CErc, 33, 159-64. Leone, G. (2004). «Una risposta da un papiro dell’opera Della natura di Epicuro (PHerc. 1149) a una vexata quaestio sulla struttura dell’Epistola ad Erodoto». Indelli, G.; Leone, G.; Longo Auricchio, F. (a cura di). Mathesis e mneme: studi in memoria di Marcello Gigante, 2 voll. Napoli: Università degli Studi di Napoli Federico II, vol. II, 45-57. Leone, G. (2005). «Per la ricostruzione dei PHerc. 1149/993 e 1010 (Epicuro, Della natura, libro II)». CErc, 35, 15-25. Leone, G. (2006). «Momenti del percorso ecdotico del II libro Sulla natura di Epicuro». CErc, 36, 145-87. 3 Leone, G. (2007). «Per la ricostruzione del PHerc. 1149/993 (Epicuro, Della natura, libro II)». Frosen, J.; Purola, T.; Salmenkivi, E. (eds). Proceedings of the 24th International Congress of Papyrology, vol. II. Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica Publisher, 549-58. Leone, G. (2010). «Il PHerc. 1010 (Epicuro, Sulla natura, libro II): anatomia del rotolo». Gagos, T. (ed.). Proceedings of the 25th International Congress of Papyrology. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Library, 409-26. [https://quod.lib.umich.edu/i/icp/7523866.0025.151/--il-pherc-1010-epicuro-sulla-natura-libro-ii-anatomia- del?rgn=main;view=fulltext] Leone, G. (2010). «Il secondo libro Sulla natura di Epicuro tra disegni e incisioni». CErc, 40, 155-72. Leone, G. (2012). Epicuro, Sulla natura, libro II. Edizione, traduzione e commento. Napoli: Bibliopolis. [https://bibliopolis.it/shop/sulla-natura-libro-ii/] Leone, G. (2012). «Il PHerc. 1149/993 (Epicuro, Sulla natura, libro II): una nuova ipotesi di ricostruzione». Schubert, P. (éd.). Actes du 26e Congrès International de Papyrologie. Ginevra: Librarie Droz, 429-35. Leone, G. (2012). “Reconstructing PHerc. 1783/1691/1010 and PHerc. 1149/993 (Epicurus, On nature, Book II)”. Erler, M.; Rother, W. (Hrsgg). Philosophie der Lust. Studien zum Hedonismus. Basel: Schwabe Verlag, 105-12. Leone, G. (2014). «Osservazioni sui papiri ercolanesi di Epicuro». SEP, 11, 83-109. [https://www.torrossa.com/en/resources/an/3001812] Leone. G. (2015). «Appendice». Masi, F.G.; Maso, S. (eds). Epicurus on Eidola. Peri Phuseos Book II. Update, Proposals, and Discussions. Amsterdam: Hakkert, 191-209. Leone, G. (2016). «I papiri del Περὶ φύϲεωϲ di Epicuro nella storia dell’Officina dei Papiri Ercolanesi». Casanova, A.; Messeri, G.; Pintaudi, R. (a cura di). “E sì d’amici pieno”. Omaggio di studiosi italiani a Guido Bastianini per il suo settantesimo compleanno. Firenze: Edizioni Gonnelli, 233-50. Leone, G. (2018). «Gli Epicurei e il buon raccolto dell’anima». Davoli, P.; Pelle, N. (a cura di). Πολυμάθεια: studi classici offerti a Mario Capasso. Lecce: Pensa Multimedia, 265-86. [https://issuu.com/pensamultimedia/docs/75_indice_961] Leone, G. (2018). «Il PHerc. 1811/335: Epicuro, Sulla natura, libro III?». CErc, 48, 5-24. [http://www.cispe.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/11/Abstract-Cronache-48.pdf] Leone, G; Carrelli, S. (2019). «Per l’edizione di Epicuro, Sulla natura, libro incerto (PHerc.
Recommended publications
  • The Epicurean School
    IX Hellenistic Philosophy: The Epicurean School 1. THE PHILOSOPHERS Were we not upset by the worries that celestial phenomena and death might matter to us, and also by failure to appreciate the limits of pains and desires, we would have no need for natural philosophy. There is no way to dispel the fear about matters of supreme importance for someone who does not know what the nature of the universe is, but retains some of the fears based on mythology. Hence without natural philosophy there is no way of securing the purity of our pleasures. Epicurus, Principal Doctrines 11–12. Empty are the words of that philosopher who offers therapy for no human suffering. For just as there is no use in medical expertise if it does not give therapy for bodily diseases, so too there is no use in philosophy if it does not expel the sufferings of the soul. Epicurus, as quoted in Porphyry, To Marcella 31.1 Epicurus (342/1–270 BCE), the founder of the Epicurean school, was born in Samos, of Athenian parents, seven years after the death of Plato.2 His father, Neocles, a school master, had settled there in 352 with two thousand other Athenian cleruchs, colonists retaining a diminished form of Athenian citizenship. Economic adversity probably made emigration attractive to Neocles, for in leaving Athens he gave up a number of rights, including his vote in the Assembly, and the colonists would not have been popular with the Samians. Moreover, his profession enjoyed little status, and a number of later authors referred to Epicurus contemptuously as the son of a school teacher.
    [Show full text]
  • Marketing Fragment 6 X 10.5.T65
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-84801-5 - The Cambridge Companion to Lucretius Edited by Stuart Gillespie and Philip Hardie Index More information GENERAL INDEX Abad, Diego Jose,´ 4, 201 atoms Aemilius Macer, 96 combinations of, 48, 63, 90–1 Aeschylus, 67 Lucretian terms for, 22, 95–6 ‘aesthetics of the gap’, 176 Augustus, 151 Akenside, Mark, 267 Avancius, Hieronymus, 211 Alamanni, Luigi, 223–4 Aldus Manutius, 211 Bacon, Francis, 134–5, 148, 152, 153, 155–8, Alexander, William, 248 244, 251–2 Anaxagoras, 25, 27, 28, 90 eulogised by Cowley, 13, 252 ‘Anaxagorean’ mechanism (Robert Boyle), Baıf,¨ Jean-Antoine de, 229 140 Bailey, Cyril, 318 Anti-Jacobin, The, 290–1 Baker, Henry, 266 ‘anti-Lucretius’, 6, 7, 113, 189–90, Barozzi, Pietro, 210 196 Basso, Sebastian, 134 Antipater of Sidon, 68 Bayle, Pierre, 278 Antipater of Thessalonica, 71 Beattie, James, 259 apotheosis, 114–15 Beeckman, Isaac, 136 Ara Pacis, 125 Beer, Gillian, 5 Aratus, 95, 174 Behn, Aphra, 15 Aristotelianism, 131, 133, 134, 138, 251 Belleau, Remy, 229 Arnobius, 118 Benlowes, Edward, 248 Arnold, Matthew, 299–301 Berault,´ Nicolas, 228 ataraxia (freedom from disturbance), 21, 43, Bergerac, Cyrano de, 133, 238–9, 240 73, 74, 82, 239 Bergson, Henri, 184, 308–9, 320–1 Athens, 20, 38, 79, 83 Berkeley, George, 142 atomism, 3, 8–9, 22, 28, 131, 145–8 Berni, Francesco, 223–4 ancient vs. modern, 8 Bignone, E., 206 Bacon on, 134–5, 251–2 Bischoff, B., 206 Descartes on, 136 Blackmore, Sir Richard, 267–8 in Leibniz, 142 Blake, William, 295 in Newton, 141–2 Blumenberg, H., 282–3 and
    [Show full text]
  • The Polemical Practice in Ancient Epicureanism* M
    UDK 101.1;141.5 Вестник СПбГУ. Философия и конфликтология. 2019. Т. 35. Вып. 3 The polemical practice in ancient Epicureanism* M. M. Shakhnovich St. Petersburg State University, 7–9, Universitetskaya nab., St. Petersburg, 199034, Russian Federation For citation: Shakhnovich M. M. The polemical practice in ancient Epicureanism. Vestnik of Saint Petersburg University. Philosophy and Conflict Studies, 2019, vol. 35, issue 3, pp. 461–471. https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu17.2019.306 The article explores the presentation methods of a philosophical doctrine in Greek and Ro- man Epicureanism; it is shown that for the ancient, middle, and Roman Epicureans a con- troversy with representatives of other philosophical schools was a typical way of present- ing their own views. The polemical practice, in which the basic principles of Epicureanism were expounded through the criticism of other philosophical systems, first of all, Academics and Stoics, was considered not only as the preferred way of presenting the own doctrine, but also as the most convenient rhetorical device, which had, among other things, didac- tic significance. The founder of the school, Epicurus, often included in his texts the terms used in other philosophical schools, giving them a different, often opposite, content. While presenting his teaching in the treatise “On Nature” or in letters to his followers, Epicurus pushed off the opinions of Democritus, Plato, and the Stoics, but resorted mainly to implicit criticism of his opponents, often without naming them by name. His closest students and later followers — Metrodorus, Hermarchus, Colotes, Philodemus, Lucretius, Diogenes of Oenoanda — continuing the controversy with the Academics and the Stoics, more frank- ly expressed their indignation about the “falsely understood Epicureanism” or erroneous opinions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Epicurean Criteria of Truth and Its Transmission Through the Word)
    LOS CRITERIOS DE LA VERDAD EPICÚREOS Y SU TRANSMISIÓN POR MEDIO DE LA 1 PALABRA (The epicurean criteria of truth and its transmission through the word) Víctor Daniel Albornoz (Universidad de Los Andes. Venezuela) ([email protected] / [email protected]) 3 1 / 1 Resumen - z Este artículo expone en primer lugar la importancia que le atribuyó Epicuro a los criterios o n r de la verdad: las sensaciones, las emociones y las prolepsis. Luego analiza el rol o b l A fundamental que estos criterios juegan en la transmisión del conocimiento por parte de dos l e i de los principales divulgadores de la doctrina en la Antigüedad: Lucrecio y Diógenes de n a D Enoanda. Los resultados de la investigación revelarán que en los textos epicúreos subyace r o t una estrategia discursiva que se vale de las emociones, las sensaciones y las prolepsis c í V como modo de revelar y transmitir el conocimiento. En el caso particular de las prolepsis - los textos se valen de ellas para presentar de manera gradual los tópicos de la doctrina que abordan, pues cuando los temas se presentan someramente existe una primera relación de conocimiento previo para con ellos y así se está presto a dar el siguiente paso de comprobación cognoscitiva. Palabras clave: Epicureísmo, sensaciones, afecciones, prolepsis, Lucrecio, Diógenes de Enoanda. Abstract This article refers, firstly, to the importance given by Epicurus to the criteria of truth: feelings, emotions, and prolepsis. Afterwards, it analyzes the main role that these criteria play in the transmission of knowledge by two of the main divulgers of the dogma in the Antiquity: Lucretius and Diogenes of Oenoanda.
    [Show full text]
  • Diogenes of Oinoanda: Epicureanism and Philosophical Debates / Diogène D’Œnoanda: Épicurisme Et Controverses
    Jürgen Hammerstaedt, Pierre-Marie Morel, Refk Güremen (eds.), Diogenes of Oinoanda: Epicureanism and Philosophical Debates / Diogène d’Œnoanda: Épicurisme et controverses by Frederik bakker On the publisher’s website this book is commended as the «first col- lection of essays entirely devoted to the inscription of Diogenes of Oinoanda». Indeed, this book can be said to represent a new stage in the research into this very important document. The inscription, which was set up in the early second century AD in Oinoanda in Southern Turkey, provides an elaborate exposition of the philosophy of Epicurus (341-270 BC). It was discovered in 1884, and so far 299 fragments have been brought to light, in various states of preservation and readability. For the last half century the study of Diogenes’ inscription has been dominated by the towering figure of Martin Ferguson Smith (Durham University), whose editions with translations and commentary – both philological and philosophical – still provide the best if not the only ways of access to the fragments. Most of the results of his research have been brought together in two volumes: M. F. Smith, Diogenes of Oinoanda. The Epicurean Inscription, Bibliopolis, Naples 1993; and M. F. Smith, Supplement to Diogenes of Oinoanda. The Epicurean Inscription, Bibliopolis, Naples 2003. From 2007 onwards Smith has been work- ing together with Jürgen Hammerstaedt (University of Cologne). The results of their investigations have been conveniently collected in J. Hammerstaedt-M. F. Smith, The Epicurean Inscription of Diogenes of Oinoanda. Ten Years of New Discoveries and Research, Rudolf Habelt Verlag, Bonn 2014. Besides these two scholars, over the years many others have involved reCensioni Syzetesis V/1 (2018) 113-122 ISSN 1974-5044 - http://www.syzetesis.it 113 Frederik Bakker themselves with the inscription or portions of it, offering new interpre- tations of its philosophical content, and sometimes proposing alterna- tive readings.
    [Show full text]
  • EPISTOLARY EPICUREANS Pamela Gordon Sayings, Rejoinders
    EPISTOLARY EPICUREANS Pamela Gordon Send me a little pot of cheese, so that— when I wish—I may have a feast.1 Sayings, rejoinders, and retorts are the salient media for the construction of the biographies and teachings of most of the philosophers who appear in Diogenes Laertius’ Lives and Opinions of the Eminent Philosophers (third cen- tury ad). The great Greek philosophers tend to speak in one-liners that Dio- genes presents alongside or within anecdotes about their lives. Occasionally Diogenes embeds a letter to, from, or about a philosopher, but these letters appear only sporadically. When letters do appear, each is presented either in full or as an extended quotation.2 The exception emerges in Diogenes’ last and tenth book, whose subject is Epicurus and the Epicureans. In the biog- raphy of Epicurus, the prominent vehicles are the fragmentary letter and the allusion to letters. Why letters, when creative biographers could have continued the pattern set by the use of anecdote, aphorism or clever repar- tee in the accounts of Solon, Socrates, Diogenes the Cynic, and the other philosophers?3 And why fragments of letters, when the letters of the other 1 From a letter of Epicurus as recorded by Diogenes Laertius (10. 11): πέµψον µοι τυροῦ […] κυθριδίου, ἵν’ ὅταν βούλωµαι πολυτελεύσασθαι δύνωµαι. All texts of Diogenes Laertius quoted here are from Long 1964. For texts of Epicurus, I depart from convention by citing the text of Diogenes Laertius (the only source for Epicurus’ three extant epistles). Throughout this essay, all translations are my own unless otherwise stated.
    [Show full text]
  • “Then Truly the Life of the Gods Will Pass to Men”: Contemplating Diogenes of Oenoanda’S Golden Age Wim Nijs
    “then truly the life of the gods will pass to men”: Contemplating Diogenes of Oenoanda’s Golden Age Wim Nijs PICUREANS are well known for their preoccupation with the present and their avoidance of the anxieties that may E be caused by fretting over the uncontrollable future. Since one can only exert direct influence over the present, the only viable strategy to enhance ataraxia and increase one’s hap- piness is to enjoy the present moment to the fullest by living it in accordance with the principles of Epicurean doctrine. 1. Thinking about the present, but keeping one eye on the future? When Diogenes of Oenoanda in Lycia, a wealthy citizen as well as an Epicurean philosopher, decided that, before he died,1 he wanted to share the benefits of Epicurean doctrine with present and future citizens and visitors of Oenoanda, he had stonemasons cover a stoa’s wall with a monumental inscription containing treatises on ethics, physics, and old age. Although this wall is no longer standing and the stone blocks of the inscription have been re-used elsewhere in the city, many fragments of the text have been recovered and reassembled, gradually enabling us to gain some insight in Diogenes’ philosophical legacy. One of these recovered fragments, NF 184, shows that Dioge- nes was no exception with regard to the typically Epicurean orientation towards the present, rather than to the uncertain 1 As far as Diogenes’ life and death are concerned, we know only that he probably lived during the first half of the second century A.D.
    [Show full text]
  • Live Unnoticed (ΛΕ ΙΣας) Philosophia Antiqua
    Live unnoticed (Λε ισας) Philosophia Antiqua A Series of Studies on Ancient Philosophy Previous Editors J.H. Waszink † W.J. Verdenius† J.C.M. Van Winden Edited by K.A. Algra F.A.J. De Haas J. Mansfeld C.J. Rowe D.T. Runia Ch. Wildberg VOLUME 111 Live unnoticed (Λε ισας) On the Vicissitudes of an Epicurean Doctrine By Geert Roskam LEIDEN • BOSTON 2007 This book is printed on acid-free paper. ISSN: 0079-1678 ISBN: 978 90 04 16171 9 Copyright 2007 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Hotei Publishing, IDC Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in aretrievalsystem,ortransmittedinanyformorbyanymeans,electronic,mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Koninklijke Brill NV provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910, Danvers, MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change. printed in the netherlands To my parents Ipsa enim altitudo attonat summa (Maecenas, ap. Senec., epist. 19,9) … le defir que i’ ay de vivre en repos & de continuer la vie que i’ ay commencée en prenant pour ma deuife: benè vixit, benè qui latuit … (Descartes, Letter to Mersenne,April1634; ed. Adam- Tannery I, 285–286) Epikur hat zu allen Zeiten gelebt und lebt noch, un- bekannt denen, welche sich Epikureer nannten und nennen, und ohne Ruf bei den Philosophen. Auch hat er selber den eigenen Namen vergessen: es war das schwerste Gepäck, welches er je abgeworfen hat.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucretius' Arguments on the Swerve and Free Action
    Lucretius’ arguments on the swerve and free-action Abstract: In his version of atomism, Lucretius made explicit reference to the concept of an intrinsic declination of the atom, the atomic swerve (clinamen in Latin), stressing that the time and space of the infinitesimal atomic vibration is uncertain. The topic of this article is the Epicurean and Lucretian arguments in favour of the swerve. Our exposition of the Lucretian model of the atomic clinamen will present and elucidate the respective considerations on the alleged role of the swerve in the generation of free-action. 1. Fall and clinamen The Greek alchemists distinguished two models of material analysis: either the traditional method of the research for the four basic elements, respectively earth, water, fire and air; or the competing model that suggested that all material substances consist of atoms. The advantage of the atomist model was that it explained the phenomena that we classify under the general term of secondary qualities, for instance, color, taste, smell and sound, which were still not measurable as the primary qualities, namely, solidity, extension, motion, number and figure. Color, according to Democritus, was the effect of the turning and inclination of the shapes of the atoms. This declination of the atomic shape obtained more significance with Epicurus and Lucretius. Philodemus, Cicero, Lucretius, Plutarch, Aetius, Diogenes of Oenoanda, Galen, Plotinus and Augustine, conveyed that Epicurus introduced the model of the atomic clinamen (παρέγκλισις), as an impulsive indeterminacy in the motion of the undividable atom. This atomic swerve should be regarded as an internalization of the universal atomic motion in every single solid and indestructible atom, causing collisions and joining compounds and bodies.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction Aux Sources Documentaires Sur Épicure Konstantinos Alevizos
    Introduction aux sources documentaires sur Épicure Konstantinos Alevizos To cite this version: Konstantinos Alevizos. Introduction aux sources documentaires sur Épicure. 2020, 978-2-9574800-0-5. hal-03161654 HAL Id: hal-03161654 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-03161654 Submitted on 16 Mar 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Introduction aux sources documentaires sur Épicure. Konstantinos Alevizos Aix Marseille Univ, CNRS, PRISM, Marseille, France Introduction. Il est surprenant de penser qu’après plus de 2 300 ans, la philosophie d’Épicure reste si actuelle, au point de pouvoir se vanter de nouveaux adhérents encore aujourd’hui, même si une école formelle épicurienne, non autoproclamée comme telle, n’existe pas. L’épicuréisme aujourd’hui signifie d’une part l’étude historique, philologique et philosophique de sa doctrine, c’est-à-dire l’examen philosophique de son système afin de comprendre son fonctionnement, ce qu’il propose, ses failles, ses limites, son actualisation éventuelle et en général son évaluation dans ces parties et de manière globale. Celui-ci, si l’on accepte que son système détient une sorte de véridicité naturelle atemporelle (dans ses parties ou globalement) qui est applicable aussi en dehors d’un contexte historique et social précis.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophical Polemics in Lucretius : a Study in the History of Epicurean Criticism
    The philosophical polemics in Lucretius : a study in the history of Epicurean criticism Autor(en): Kleve, Knut Objekttyp: Article Zeitschrift: Entretiens sur l'Antiquité classique Band (Jahr): 24 (1978) PDF erstellt am: 10.10.2021 Persistenter Link: http://doi.org/10.5169/seals-660664 Nutzungsbedingungen Die ETH-Bibliothek ist Anbieterin der digitalisierten Zeitschriften. Sie besitzt keine Urheberrechte an den Inhalten der Zeitschriften. Die Rechte liegen in der Regel bei den Herausgebern. Die auf der Plattform e-periodica veröffentlichten Dokumente stehen für nicht-kommerzielle Zwecke in Lehre und Forschung sowie für die private Nutzung frei zur Verfügung. Einzelne Dateien oder Ausdrucke aus diesem Angebot können zusammen mit diesen Nutzungsbedingungen und den korrekten Herkunftsbezeichnungen weitergegeben werden. Das Veröffentlichen von Bildern in Print- und Online-Publikationen ist nur mit vorheriger Genehmigung der Rechteinhaber erlaubt. Die systematische Speicherung von Teilen des elektronischen Angebots auf anderen Servern bedarf ebenfalls des schriftlichen Einverständnisses der Rechteinhaber. Haftungsausschluss Alle Angaben erfolgen ohne Gewähr für Vollständigkeit oder Richtigkeit. Es wird keine Haftung übernommen für Schäden durch die Verwendung von Informationen aus diesem Online-Angebot oder durch das Fehlen von Informationen. Dies gilt auch für Inhalte Dritter, die über dieses Angebot zugänglich sind. Ein Dienst der ETH-Bibliothek ETH Zürich, Rämistrasse 101, 8092 Zürich, Schweiz, www.library.ethz.ch http://www.e-periodica.ch II Knut Kleve THE PHILOSOPHICAL POLEMICS IN LUCRETIUS A Study in the History of Epicurean Criticism I. THE PROBLEM The main problem in Lucretius' polemics has been who were his opponents. He names four of them, Heraclitus, Empedocles, Anaxagoras and Democritus, the others remain anonymous. For at least a hundred years the commentators have collected sources referring to thinkers who conceivably could have been attacked by him, and, at least since C.
    [Show full text]
  • Epicurus in Lycia P
    The Classical Review http://journals.cambridge.org/CAR Additional services for The Classical Review: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Epicurus in Lycia P. Gordon: Epicurus in Lycia: the Second­century World of Diogenes of Oenoanda. Pp. 140. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1996. £29.95/$37.50. ISBN: 0­472­10461­6. R. W. Sharples The Classical Review / Volume 48 / Issue 01 / April 1998, pp 89 ­ 90 DOI: 10.1017/S0009840X00330530, Published online: 09 March 2010 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/ abstract_S0009840X00330530 How to cite this article: R. W. Sharples (1998). The Classical Review,48, pp 89­90 doi:10.1017/ S0009840X00330530 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/CAR, IP address: 144.82.107.43 on 10 Sep 2012 THE CLASSICAL REVIEW 89 EPICURUS IN LYCIA P. GORDON: Epicurus in Lycia: the Second-century World of Diogenes of Oenoanda. Pp. 140. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1996. £29.95/$37.50. ISBN: 0-472-10461-6. Diogenes of Oenoanda's Epicurean inscription has usually been discussed as evidence for the doctrines of the founder of the school. G.'s aim is rather to place it in its second-century A.D. context, relating it to the archaizing culture characteristic of the 'second Sophistic', while insisting that Diogenes does not share all the values of that culture and is adapting a distinctively Epicurean message to the circumstances and the modes of discourse of his own time. For example, G. argues (p.
    [Show full text]