Live Unnoticed (ΛΕ ΙΣας) Philosophia Antiqua

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Live Unnoticed (ΛΕ ΙΣας) Philosophia Antiqua Live unnoticed (Λε ισας) Philosophia Antiqua A Series of Studies on Ancient Philosophy Previous Editors J.H. Waszink † W.J. Verdenius† J.C.M. Van Winden Edited by K.A. Algra F.A.J. De Haas J. Mansfeld C.J. Rowe D.T. Runia Ch. Wildberg VOLUME 111 Live unnoticed (Λε ισας) On the Vicissitudes of an Epicurean Doctrine By Geert Roskam LEIDEN • BOSTON 2007 This book is printed on acid-free paper. ISSN: 0079-1678 ISBN: 978 90 04 16171 9 Copyright 2007 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Hotei Publishing, IDC Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in aretrievalsystem,ortransmittedinanyformorbyanymeans,electronic,mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Koninklijke Brill NV provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910, Danvers, MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change. printed in the netherlands To my parents Ipsa enim altitudo attonat summa (Maecenas, ap. Senec., epist. 19,9) … le defir que i’ ay de vivre en repos & de continuer la vie que i’ ay commencée en prenant pour ma deuife: benè vixit, benè qui latuit … (Descartes, Letter to Mersenne,April1634; ed. Adam- Tannery I, 285–286) Epikur hat zu allen Zeiten gelebt und lebt noch, un- bekannt denen, welche sich Epikureer nannten und nennen, und ohne Ruf bei den Philosophen. Auch hat er selber den eigenen Namen vergessen: es war das schwerste Gepäck, welches er je abgeworfen hat. (Nietzsche, Menschliches, Allzumenschliches, 2,227) CONTENTS Acknowledgements .................................................... ix Abbreviations .......................................................... xi ChapterOne.Introduction ........................................... 1 Chapter Two. Epicurus................................................ 29 2.1. Introduction ..................................................... 29 2.2. The maxim λε ισας and Epicurus’ extant writings ....... 33 2.3. The maxim λε ισας insecondarysources................. 41 2.3.1. Themaximitself ........................................ 41 2.3.2. Themaximinitsbroadercontext...................... 44 2.4. The motivations behind λε ισας........................... 63 Chapter Three. The Epicureans of the first generation: Epicurus’ συμ ιλσ ντες...................................................... 67 3.1. A quick glance in the Garden .................................. 67 3.2. Metrodorus ...................................................... 69 3.3. Hermarchus ..................................................... 76 3.4. Colotes........................................................... 80 ChapterFour.Latergenerationsoftheschool ....................... 83 4.1. Lucretius......................................................... 83 4.1.1. Introduction ............................................. 83 4.1.2. Lucretius’ political philosophy in De rerum natura ....... 86 4.1.3. Livingunnoticed?Lucretius’ultimateambitions ...... 99 4.2. Philodemus ...................................................... 101 4.2.1. Introduction ............................................. 101 4.2.2. Theautonomyofpolitics… ........................... 104 4.2.3. … and of philosophy .................................... 108 4.2.4. The interaction of two separate worlds................. 120 4.2.5. Livingunnoticedinthefaceofdeath? ................. 125 4.2.6. Conclusion............................................... 128 4.3. DiogenesofOenoanda.......................................... 129 viii contents ChapterFive.Conclusion............................................. 145 Chapter Six. Appendix: Augustan poetry ............................ 155 6.1. Virgil............................................................. 155 6.2. Horace........................................................... 166 6.3. Ovid.............................................................. 179 Bibliography ........................................................... 189 Indices Indexnominum..................................................... 209 Indexlocorum ...................................................... 213 Indexrerum......................................................... 229 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS According to later traditions, Epicurus claimed to have learned noth- ing from his philosophical predecessors. He even gave his own teacher Nausiphanes the hardly enviable nickname of ‘jelly-fish’. I have abso- lutely no reason to follow his example. I have every reason, in fact, to be grateful to L. Van der Stockt, who was the supervisor of my PhD-dissertation on Plutarch and who since then has continued and still continues to encourage and support me. During the years I have been working with him, he has read more texts of mine than he would probably like to remember. His critical remarks and suggestions have always considerably improved the final result. It has been a great privilege to stay several months at Utrecht Uni- versity, where I had the opportunity to discuss my work with several members of the staff, which has led to thorough correction and revi- sion. I am especially indebted to K. Algra, who went through the whole manuscript and discussed it with me chapter by chapter. I have bene- fited greatly from his acute observations and pertinent criticisms, which often forced me to clarify my argument or give it up. J. Mansfeld like- wise spent many hours carefully reading the whole manuscript and I have been glad to adopt many of his helpful suggestions. I am sure both will recognise their positive influence throughout the book and they will perhaps remain wisely sceptical about those points where my stubbornness has not been overcome by their arguments. I am much indebted to A. Casanova, W. Evenepoel, P.H. Schrijvers, and T. van Houdt, who read substantial parts of an earlier draft of this book and especially to M. Erler who read the whole of it. They all saved me from many embarrassing errors and made extremely valuable, often challenging, suggestions. I also owe many thanks to C. Steel, who drew my attention to several interesting passages which I would otherwise have overlooked and who indirectly contributed more to this book than he probably realises himself. I am also much indebted to M. Funk Deckard and to the referee of the series for many useful suggestions and corrections. x acknowledgements It is a pleasure to extend thanks to my colleagues at the Department of Classical Studies at the Catholic University of Leuven and to the members of the De Wulf—Mansion Centre at the Leuven Institute of Philosophy. I also gratefully acknowledge the financial support of the Fund for Scientific Research—Flanders (Belgium). Epicurus was extremely grateful to his own circle of family and friends. I have many reasons to follow his example. So I should like to express my thanks to my parents to whom this book is dedicated as a token of grateful pietas, to my children, who day after day show me in the most various ways that I was right not to follow Epicurus’ advice of μ τεκνπισειν, and to my wife Kristin, who shared in all the πνι and γρυπναι of my scientific research to such an extent that this book—except for its shortcomings—is no less the fruit of her work than it is of mine. ABBREVIATIONS References to Latin authors follow the forms established by the TLL. Abbreviations of Greek authors and works are usually as listed in LSJ. Where they differ (esp. in the case of Philodemus and of Plutarch’s Moralia), they are more complete. Abbreviations of journals are as listed in L’Année Philologique. ANRW Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt,Berlin–NewYork,1972–. CPG E.L. a Leutsch – F.G. Schneidewin (eds.), Corpus Paroemiographorum Graecorum, Göttingen, 1839–1851. DK H. Diels – W. Kranz (eds.), Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker,Dublin– Zurich, 1966–1967. KG R. Kühner – B. Gerth, Ausführliche Grammatik der griechischen Sprache, Zweiter Teil: Satzlehre, Hannover–Leipzig, 1898–1904. LCL Loeb Classical Library LSJ H.G. Liddell – R. Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon, 9th edn., rev. H. Stu- art Jones, with a revised supplement, Oxford, 1996. OCT Scriptorum Classicorum Bibliotheca Oxoniensis OLD P.G.W. Glare (ed.), Oxford Latin Dictionary, 2nd edn., Oxford, 2000. PHerc. Herculaneum Papyri; cf. M. Gigante, Catalogo dei Papiri Ercolanesi, Napoli, 1979. RE G. Wissowa (and others) (ed.), Paulys Realencyclopädie der classischen Alter- tumswissenschaft, München–Stuttgart, 1893–1980. RS Ratae Sententiae (= Κριαι δαι) SV Sententiae Vaticanae SVF J. von Arnim (ed.), Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta [indices by M. Adler], Leipzig, 1903–1924. TAM E. Kalinka (and others) (ed.), Tituli Asiae Minoris, Vindobonae, 1901– 1989. TLL Thesaurus Linguae Latinae (Index: Leipzig, 1990). TrGF B. Snell – R. Kannicht – S. Radt (eds.), Tragicorum Graecorum Frag- menta, Göttingen, 1977–2004. chapter one INTRODUCTION σν δ μηδ να ναι πλν ατ γεγν ναι κα τν μαητν (Plutarch, Non posse 1100A) 1.1. This is a book on two words, which were offensive, scandalous, outrageous, and provocative. No doubt they were equally attractive, seductive, enticing, and fascinating. They were merely two common words, which were not even technical or abstruse ones, but they stood for a whole way of life, ridiculed and despised by many, praised and applauded by others. These two words were λε ισας: ‘live unno-
Recommended publications
  • The Epicurean School
    IX Hellenistic Philosophy: The Epicurean School 1. THE PHILOSOPHERS Were we not upset by the worries that celestial phenomena and death might matter to us, and also by failure to appreciate the limits of pains and desires, we would have no need for natural philosophy. There is no way to dispel the fear about matters of supreme importance for someone who does not know what the nature of the universe is, but retains some of the fears based on mythology. Hence without natural philosophy there is no way of securing the purity of our pleasures. Epicurus, Principal Doctrines 11–12. Empty are the words of that philosopher who offers therapy for no human suffering. For just as there is no use in medical expertise if it does not give therapy for bodily diseases, so too there is no use in philosophy if it does not expel the sufferings of the soul. Epicurus, as quoted in Porphyry, To Marcella 31.1 Epicurus (342/1–270 BCE), the founder of the Epicurean school, was born in Samos, of Athenian parents, seven years after the death of Plato.2 His father, Neocles, a school master, had settled there in 352 with two thousand other Athenian cleruchs, colonists retaining a diminished form of Athenian citizenship. Economic adversity probably made emigration attractive to Neocles, for in leaving Athens he gave up a number of rights, including his vote in the Assembly, and the colonists would not have been popular with the Samians. Moreover, his profession enjoyed little status, and a number of later authors referred to Epicurus contemptuously as the son of a school teacher.
    [Show full text]
  • Marketing Fragment 6 X 10.5.T65
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-84801-5 - The Cambridge Companion to Lucretius Edited by Stuart Gillespie and Philip Hardie Index More information GENERAL INDEX Abad, Diego Jose,´ 4, 201 atoms Aemilius Macer, 96 combinations of, 48, 63, 90–1 Aeschylus, 67 Lucretian terms for, 22, 95–6 ‘aesthetics of the gap’, 176 Augustus, 151 Akenside, Mark, 267 Avancius, Hieronymus, 211 Alamanni, Luigi, 223–4 Aldus Manutius, 211 Bacon, Francis, 134–5, 148, 152, 153, 155–8, Alexander, William, 248 244, 251–2 Anaxagoras, 25, 27, 28, 90 eulogised by Cowley, 13, 252 ‘Anaxagorean’ mechanism (Robert Boyle), Baıf,¨ Jean-Antoine de, 229 140 Bailey, Cyril, 318 Anti-Jacobin, The, 290–1 Baker, Henry, 266 ‘anti-Lucretius’, 6, 7, 113, 189–90, Barozzi, Pietro, 210 196 Basso, Sebastian, 134 Antipater of Sidon, 68 Bayle, Pierre, 278 Antipater of Thessalonica, 71 Beattie, James, 259 apotheosis, 114–15 Beeckman, Isaac, 136 Ara Pacis, 125 Beer, Gillian, 5 Aratus, 95, 174 Behn, Aphra, 15 Aristotelianism, 131, 133, 134, 138, 251 Belleau, Remy, 229 Arnobius, 118 Benlowes, Edward, 248 Arnold, Matthew, 299–301 Berault,´ Nicolas, 228 ataraxia (freedom from disturbance), 21, 43, Bergerac, Cyrano de, 133, 238–9, 240 73, 74, 82, 239 Bergson, Henri, 184, 308–9, 320–1 Athens, 20, 38, 79, 83 Berkeley, George, 142 atomism, 3, 8–9, 22, 28, 131, 145–8 Berni, Francesco, 223–4 ancient vs. modern, 8 Bignone, E., 206 Bacon on, 134–5, 251–2 Bischoff, B., 206 Descartes on, 136 Blackmore, Sir Richard, 267–8 in Leibniz, 142 Blake, William, 295 in Newton, 141–2 Blumenberg, H., 282–3 and
    [Show full text]
  • The Polemical Practice in Ancient Epicureanism* M
    UDK 101.1;141.5 Вестник СПбГУ. Философия и конфликтология. 2019. Т. 35. Вып. 3 The polemical practice in ancient Epicureanism* M. M. Shakhnovich St. Petersburg State University, 7–9, Universitetskaya nab., St. Petersburg, 199034, Russian Federation For citation: Shakhnovich M. M. The polemical practice in ancient Epicureanism. Vestnik of Saint Petersburg University. Philosophy and Conflict Studies, 2019, vol. 35, issue 3, pp. 461–471. https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu17.2019.306 The article explores the presentation methods of a philosophical doctrine in Greek and Ro- man Epicureanism; it is shown that for the ancient, middle, and Roman Epicureans a con- troversy with representatives of other philosophical schools was a typical way of present- ing their own views. The polemical practice, in which the basic principles of Epicureanism were expounded through the criticism of other philosophical systems, first of all, Academics and Stoics, was considered not only as the preferred way of presenting the own doctrine, but also as the most convenient rhetorical device, which had, among other things, didac- tic significance. The founder of the school, Epicurus, often included in his texts the terms used in other philosophical schools, giving them a different, often opposite, content. While presenting his teaching in the treatise “On Nature” or in letters to his followers, Epicurus pushed off the opinions of Democritus, Plato, and the Stoics, but resorted mainly to implicit criticism of his opponents, often without naming them by name. His closest students and later followers — Metrodorus, Hermarchus, Colotes, Philodemus, Lucretius, Diogenes of Oenoanda — continuing the controversy with the Academics and the Stoics, more frank- ly expressed their indignation about the “falsely understood Epicureanism” or erroneous opinions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Epicurean Criteria of Truth and Its Transmission Through the Word)
    LOS CRITERIOS DE LA VERDAD EPICÚREOS Y SU TRANSMISIÓN POR MEDIO DE LA 1 PALABRA (The epicurean criteria of truth and its transmission through the word) Víctor Daniel Albornoz (Universidad de Los Andes. Venezuela) ([email protected] / [email protected]) 3 1 / 1 Resumen - z Este artículo expone en primer lugar la importancia que le atribuyó Epicuro a los criterios o n r de la verdad: las sensaciones, las emociones y las prolepsis. Luego analiza el rol o b l A fundamental que estos criterios juegan en la transmisión del conocimiento por parte de dos l e i de los principales divulgadores de la doctrina en la Antigüedad: Lucrecio y Diógenes de n a D Enoanda. Los resultados de la investigación revelarán que en los textos epicúreos subyace r o t una estrategia discursiva que se vale de las emociones, las sensaciones y las prolepsis c í V como modo de revelar y transmitir el conocimiento. En el caso particular de las prolepsis - los textos se valen de ellas para presentar de manera gradual los tópicos de la doctrina que abordan, pues cuando los temas se presentan someramente existe una primera relación de conocimiento previo para con ellos y así se está presto a dar el siguiente paso de comprobación cognoscitiva. Palabras clave: Epicureísmo, sensaciones, afecciones, prolepsis, Lucrecio, Diógenes de Enoanda. Abstract This article refers, firstly, to the importance given by Epicurus to the criteria of truth: feelings, emotions, and prolepsis. Afterwards, it analyzes the main role that these criteria play in the transmission of knowledge by two of the main divulgers of the dogma in the Antiquity: Lucretius and Diogenes of Oenoanda.
    [Show full text]
  • Diogenes of Oinoanda: Epicureanism and Philosophical Debates / Diogène D’Œnoanda: Épicurisme Et Controverses
    Jürgen Hammerstaedt, Pierre-Marie Morel, Refk Güremen (eds.), Diogenes of Oinoanda: Epicureanism and Philosophical Debates / Diogène d’Œnoanda: Épicurisme et controverses by Frederik bakker On the publisher’s website this book is commended as the «first col- lection of essays entirely devoted to the inscription of Diogenes of Oinoanda». Indeed, this book can be said to represent a new stage in the research into this very important document. The inscription, which was set up in the early second century AD in Oinoanda in Southern Turkey, provides an elaborate exposition of the philosophy of Epicurus (341-270 BC). It was discovered in 1884, and so far 299 fragments have been brought to light, in various states of preservation and readability. For the last half century the study of Diogenes’ inscription has been dominated by the towering figure of Martin Ferguson Smith (Durham University), whose editions with translations and commentary – both philological and philosophical – still provide the best if not the only ways of access to the fragments. Most of the results of his research have been brought together in two volumes: M. F. Smith, Diogenes of Oinoanda. The Epicurean Inscription, Bibliopolis, Naples 1993; and M. F. Smith, Supplement to Diogenes of Oinoanda. The Epicurean Inscription, Bibliopolis, Naples 2003. From 2007 onwards Smith has been work- ing together with Jürgen Hammerstaedt (University of Cologne). The results of their investigations have been conveniently collected in J. Hammerstaedt-M. F. Smith, The Epicurean Inscription of Diogenes of Oinoanda. Ten Years of New Discoveries and Research, Rudolf Habelt Verlag, Bonn 2014. Besides these two scholars, over the years many others have involved reCensioni Syzetesis V/1 (2018) 113-122 ISSN 1974-5044 - http://www.syzetesis.it 113 Frederik Bakker themselves with the inscription or portions of it, offering new interpre- tations of its philosophical content, and sometimes proposing alterna- tive readings.
    [Show full text]
  • EPISTOLARY EPICUREANS Pamela Gordon Sayings, Rejoinders
    EPISTOLARY EPICUREANS Pamela Gordon Send me a little pot of cheese, so that— when I wish—I may have a feast.1 Sayings, rejoinders, and retorts are the salient media for the construction of the biographies and teachings of most of the philosophers who appear in Diogenes Laertius’ Lives and Opinions of the Eminent Philosophers (third cen- tury ad). The great Greek philosophers tend to speak in one-liners that Dio- genes presents alongside or within anecdotes about their lives. Occasionally Diogenes embeds a letter to, from, or about a philosopher, but these letters appear only sporadically. When letters do appear, each is presented either in full or as an extended quotation.2 The exception emerges in Diogenes’ last and tenth book, whose subject is Epicurus and the Epicureans. In the biog- raphy of Epicurus, the prominent vehicles are the fragmentary letter and the allusion to letters. Why letters, when creative biographers could have continued the pattern set by the use of anecdote, aphorism or clever repar- tee in the accounts of Solon, Socrates, Diogenes the Cynic, and the other philosophers?3 And why fragments of letters, when the letters of the other 1 From a letter of Epicurus as recorded by Diogenes Laertius (10. 11): πέµψον µοι τυροῦ […] κυθριδίου, ἵν’ ὅταν βούλωµαι πολυτελεύσασθαι δύνωµαι. All texts of Diogenes Laertius quoted here are from Long 1964. For texts of Epicurus, I depart from convention by citing the text of Diogenes Laertius (the only source for Epicurus’ three extant epistles). Throughout this essay, all translations are my own unless otherwise stated.
    [Show full text]
  • “Then Truly the Life of the Gods Will Pass to Men”: Contemplating Diogenes of Oenoanda’S Golden Age Wim Nijs
    “then truly the life of the gods will pass to men”: Contemplating Diogenes of Oenoanda’s Golden Age Wim Nijs PICUREANS are well known for their preoccupation with the present and their avoidance of the anxieties that may E be caused by fretting over the uncontrollable future. Since one can only exert direct influence over the present, the only viable strategy to enhance ataraxia and increase one’s hap- piness is to enjoy the present moment to the fullest by living it in accordance with the principles of Epicurean doctrine. 1. Thinking about the present, but keeping one eye on the future? When Diogenes of Oenoanda in Lycia, a wealthy citizen as well as an Epicurean philosopher, decided that, before he died,1 he wanted to share the benefits of Epicurean doctrine with present and future citizens and visitors of Oenoanda, he had stonemasons cover a stoa’s wall with a monumental inscription containing treatises on ethics, physics, and old age. Although this wall is no longer standing and the stone blocks of the inscription have been re-used elsewhere in the city, many fragments of the text have been recovered and reassembled, gradually enabling us to gain some insight in Diogenes’ philosophical legacy. One of these recovered fragments, NF 184, shows that Dioge- nes was no exception with regard to the typically Epicurean orientation towards the present, rather than to the uncertain 1 As far as Diogenes’ life and death are concerned, we know only that he probably lived during the first half of the second century A.D.
    [Show full text]
  • Lucretius' Arguments on the Swerve and Free Action
    Lucretius’ arguments on the swerve and free-action Abstract: In his version of atomism, Lucretius made explicit reference to the concept of an intrinsic declination of the atom, the atomic swerve (clinamen in Latin), stressing that the time and space of the infinitesimal atomic vibration is uncertain. The topic of this article is the Epicurean and Lucretian arguments in favour of the swerve. Our exposition of the Lucretian model of the atomic clinamen will present and elucidate the respective considerations on the alleged role of the swerve in the generation of free-action. 1. Fall and clinamen The Greek alchemists distinguished two models of material analysis: either the traditional method of the research for the four basic elements, respectively earth, water, fire and air; or the competing model that suggested that all material substances consist of atoms. The advantage of the atomist model was that it explained the phenomena that we classify under the general term of secondary qualities, for instance, color, taste, smell and sound, which were still not measurable as the primary qualities, namely, solidity, extension, motion, number and figure. Color, according to Democritus, was the effect of the turning and inclination of the shapes of the atoms. This declination of the atomic shape obtained more significance with Epicurus and Lucretius. Philodemus, Cicero, Lucretius, Plutarch, Aetius, Diogenes of Oenoanda, Galen, Plotinus and Augustine, conveyed that Epicurus introduced the model of the atomic clinamen (παρέγκλισις), as an impulsive indeterminacy in the motion of the undividable atom. This atomic swerve should be regarded as an internalization of the universal atomic motion in every single solid and indestructible atom, causing collisions and joining compounds and bodies.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction Aux Sources Documentaires Sur Épicure Konstantinos Alevizos
    Introduction aux sources documentaires sur Épicure Konstantinos Alevizos To cite this version: Konstantinos Alevizos. Introduction aux sources documentaires sur Épicure. 2020, 978-2-9574800-0-5. hal-03161654 HAL Id: hal-03161654 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-03161654 Submitted on 16 Mar 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Introduction aux sources documentaires sur Épicure. Konstantinos Alevizos Aix Marseille Univ, CNRS, PRISM, Marseille, France Introduction. Il est surprenant de penser qu’après plus de 2 300 ans, la philosophie d’Épicure reste si actuelle, au point de pouvoir se vanter de nouveaux adhérents encore aujourd’hui, même si une école formelle épicurienne, non autoproclamée comme telle, n’existe pas. L’épicuréisme aujourd’hui signifie d’une part l’étude historique, philologique et philosophique de sa doctrine, c’est-à-dire l’examen philosophique de son système afin de comprendre son fonctionnement, ce qu’il propose, ses failles, ses limites, son actualisation éventuelle et en général son évaluation dans ces parties et de manière globale. Celui-ci, si l’on accepte que son système détient une sorte de véridicité naturelle atemporelle (dans ses parties ou globalement) qui est applicable aussi en dehors d’un contexte historique et social précis.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophical Polemics in Lucretius : a Study in the History of Epicurean Criticism
    The philosophical polemics in Lucretius : a study in the history of Epicurean criticism Autor(en): Kleve, Knut Objekttyp: Article Zeitschrift: Entretiens sur l'Antiquité classique Band (Jahr): 24 (1978) PDF erstellt am: 10.10.2021 Persistenter Link: http://doi.org/10.5169/seals-660664 Nutzungsbedingungen Die ETH-Bibliothek ist Anbieterin der digitalisierten Zeitschriften. Sie besitzt keine Urheberrechte an den Inhalten der Zeitschriften. Die Rechte liegen in der Regel bei den Herausgebern. Die auf der Plattform e-periodica veröffentlichten Dokumente stehen für nicht-kommerzielle Zwecke in Lehre und Forschung sowie für die private Nutzung frei zur Verfügung. Einzelne Dateien oder Ausdrucke aus diesem Angebot können zusammen mit diesen Nutzungsbedingungen und den korrekten Herkunftsbezeichnungen weitergegeben werden. Das Veröffentlichen von Bildern in Print- und Online-Publikationen ist nur mit vorheriger Genehmigung der Rechteinhaber erlaubt. Die systematische Speicherung von Teilen des elektronischen Angebots auf anderen Servern bedarf ebenfalls des schriftlichen Einverständnisses der Rechteinhaber. Haftungsausschluss Alle Angaben erfolgen ohne Gewähr für Vollständigkeit oder Richtigkeit. Es wird keine Haftung übernommen für Schäden durch die Verwendung von Informationen aus diesem Online-Angebot oder durch das Fehlen von Informationen. Dies gilt auch für Inhalte Dritter, die über dieses Angebot zugänglich sind. Ein Dienst der ETH-Bibliothek ETH Zürich, Rämistrasse 101, 8092 Zürich, Schweiz, www.library.ethz.ch http://www.e-periodica.ch II Knut Kleve THE PHILOSOPHICAL POLEMICS IN LUCRETIUS A Study in the History of Epicurean Criticism I. THE PROBLEM The main problem in Lucretius' polemics has been who were his opponents. He names four of them, Heraclitus, Empedocles, Anaxagoras and Democritus, the others remain anonymous. For at least a hundred years the commentators have collected sources referring to thinkers who conceivably could have been attacked by him, and, at least since C.
    [Show full text]
  • Epicurus in Lycia P
    The Classical Review http://journals.cambridge.org/CAR Additional services for The Classical Review: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Epicurus in Lycia P. Gordon: Epicurus in Lycia: the Second­century World of Diogenes of Oenoanda. Pp. 140. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1996. £29.95/$37.50. ISBN: 0­472­10461­6. R. W. Sharples The Classical Review / Volume 48 / Issue 01 / April 1998, pp 89 ­ 90 DOI: 10.1017/S0009840X00330530, Published online: 09 March 2010 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/ abstract_S0009840X00330530 How to cite this article: R. W. Sharples (1998). The Classical Review,48, pp 89­90 doi:10.1017/ S0009840X00330530 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/CAR, IP address: 144.82.107.43 on 10 Sep 2012 THE CLASSICAL REVIEW 89 EPICURUS IN LYCIA P. GORDON: Epicurus in Lycia: the Second-century World of Diogenes of Oenoanda. Pp. 140. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1996. £29.95/$37.50. ISBN: 0-472-10461-6. Diogenes of Oenoanda's Epicurean inscription has usually been discussed as evidence for the doctrines of the founder of the school. G.'s aim is rather to place it in its second-century A.D. context, relating it to the archaizing culture characteristic of the 'second Sophistic', while insisting that Diogenes does not share all the values of that culture and is adapting a distinctively Epicurean message to the circumstances and the modes of discourse of his own time. For example, G. argues (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Epicurean Justice and Law
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2016 Epicurean Justice and Law Jan Maximilian Robitzsch University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Classics Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Robitzsch, Jan Maximilian, "Epicurean Justice and Law" (2016). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1976. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1976 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1976 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Epicurean Justice and Law Abstract This dissertation concerns a cluster of related issues surrounding the Epicurean conception of justice. First, I show that the Epicureans defend a sophisticated kind of social contract theory and maintain a kind of legal positivism, views that are widely held today and so are of continuing interest for contemporary readers. In doing so, I argue that thinking about justice and law forms an integral part of Epicurean philosophy (pace the standard view). Second, I take up some neglected issues regarding justice and so provide detailed accounts of the metaphysics of moral properties in Epicureanism as well as of Epicurean moral epistemology. After the introduction in chapter 1, I set out the main features of the Epicurean view of justice and law in chapters 2-4. In chapter 2, I explain the basics of the Epicurean conception of justice as an agreement and relate it to Epicurean ethics as whole. In chapter 3, I examine Epicurean culture stories and I point out in what way the Epicurean view is a kind of social contract theory.
    [Show full text]