German Philosophy 1760-1860: the Legacy of Idealism Pdf, Epub, Ebook

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

German Philosophy 1760-1860: the Legacy of Idealism Pdf, Epub, Ebook GERMAN PHILOSOPHY 1760-1860: THE LEGACY OF IDEALISM PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Terry P. Pinkard | 394 pages | 01 Nov 2002 | CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS | 9780521663816 | English | Cambridge, United Kingdom German Philosophy 1760-1860: The Legacy of Idealism PDF Book May 31, Jan rated it it was amazing. Not just talking about the history of German Philosophy but the philosophy itself. He examines the dominant influence of Kant, with his revolutionary emphasis on "self-determination," and traces this influence through the development of romanticism and idealism to the critiques of post-Kantian thinkers such as Schopenhauer and Kierkegaard. The revolution in philosophy II autonomy and the moral order. Soulless and programmatic. Krug," Kritisches Journal der Philosophie , I, no. Thanks for telling us about the problem. Be the first to ask a question about German Philosophy Reinhold also tried to prove Kant's assertion that humans and other animals can know only images that appear in their minds, never "things-in-themselves" things that are not mere appearances in a mind. Other editions. I was hoping for a little more clarity on people like Hegel and his ilk. A radically revisionist view of German idealism that takes the Idea understood in either a transcendent or immanent sense right out of it. In fact, they were experiencing a wrenching transition into modern life, and it affected how they conceived of everything [3]. Will be clean, not soiled or stained. Thus Hegel introduces two important ideas to metaphysics and philosophy: the integral importance of history and of the Other person. If the principles are applied to God, freedom, and immortality, which cannot be objects of experience, the principles would always treat these three notions as though they were mere phenomena [appearances]. Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason. His philosophy attempted to account for an eternal consciousness or mind that was similar to Berkeley 's concept of God and Hegel 's Absolute. Apr 08, Michael Holm rated it really liked it Shelves: philosophy , history. Published August 29th by Cambridge University Press. Interestingly, Pinkard's account gives more attention to analytic philosophers than one would normally find in treatises on Idealism. Pinkard does a wonderful job situating Kant's revolution in philosophy and explaining the basic tenants of the three Critiques. Again, what I'm giving you is a ridiculously abbreviated and reductive summation of Hegel's logic. If Kant, Fichte, and Hegel had wanted to write about "norms" and "perfomative acts," they would have used those terms or equivalents thereof. Request removal from index. Fichte's philosophical work has controversially been interpreted as a stepping stone in the emergence of German speculative idealism , the thesis that we only ever have access to the correlation between thought and being. He examines the dominant influence of Kant, with his revolutionary emphasis on "self-determination," and traces this influence through the development of romanticism and idealism to the critiques of post-Kantian thinkers such as Schopenhauer and Kierkegaard. Hegels analysis of mind and world the Science of Logic. Immanuel Kant 's work purported to bridge the two dominant philosophical schools in the 18th century: 1 rationalism , which held that knowledge could be attained by reason alone a priori prior to experience , and 2 empiricism , which held that knowledge could be arrived at only through the senses a posteriori after experience , as expressed by philosopher David Hume , whom Kant sought to rebut. All the while, generations of younger Germans were trying to figure out their place in the overly strictured society of the German- speaking personalities, followed in turn by the next generation, who reacted to the French revolution and the Napoleonic occupation. Schopenhauer's criticism German idealism Neo-Kantianism. Best Selling in Nonfiction See all. I rated it as four because it is well-written and very informative. The period of German idealism after Kant is also known as post-Kantian idealism , post-Kantian philosophy , or simply post- Kantianism. Pinkard presents a history of the course of German Idealism beginning with Kant and ending with Kierkegaard. PRECIS : Pinkard introduces us to the key theme of 19 th -Century philosophy — namely, freedom — from a historical, socio-cultural perspective. Overthrowing the old metaphysics, it inserted a new idea into the vocabulary in terms of which modern Germans and Europeans spoke about their lives: self- determination. Action Event Process. That is, a thing-in-itself cannot be the cause of an idea or image of a thing in the mind. Kant held in the Critique of Pure Reason that the world of appearances phenomena is empirically real and transcendentally ideal. The s Fichte. Stock photo. German Philosophy 1760-1860: The Legacy of Idealism Writer Friedrich Schleiermacher was a theologian who asserted that the ideal and the real are united in God. By using our website, you agree to the use of cookies as described in our Privacy Policy. Get A Copy. It developed out of the work of Immanuel Kant in the s and s, [1] and was closely linked both with Romanticism and the revolutionary politics of the Enlightenment. A long time ago I lost interest in idealism. Enlarge cover. In his major work The Phenomenology of Spirit he went on to trace the formation of self-consciousness through history and the importance of other people in the awakening of self-consciousness see master-slave dialectic. Help Learn to edit Community portal Recent changes Upload file. Kant held in the Critique of Pure Reason that the world of appearances phenomena is empirically real and transcendentally ideal. That is to say, Kant, in attempting to resolve what the connections are between underlying reality and the representations we hold Pure Reason , and in figuring out a groundwork for morals and judgment, eventually arrived at the following conclusion: we are only bound by the laws of which we are ourselves the authors. To ask other readers questions about German Philosophy , please sign up. Kyle rated it really liked it Dec 10, From the Judeo-Christian theology, German Enlightenment thinkers inherited the model of human beings having to take a stand on the world as the totality of things. Peter Koslowski ed. Even some of Hegel came through. In order to establish his proof, Reinhold stated an axiom that could not possibly be doubted. Philosophy and Religion in German Idealism. Categories : German idealism Philosophical movements Continental philosophy Rationalism. Consequently, he rejected the assumption of anything that was not through and through merely our representation , and therefore let the knowing subject be all in all or at any rate produce everything from its own resources. Action Event Process. Terry Pinkard. Theodor W. The mind plays a central role in influencing the way that the world is experienced: we perceive phenomena through time , space and the categories of the understanding. Another member of the Young Hegelians, Ludwig Feuerbach , advocated for materialism, and his thought was influential in the development of historical materialism , [9] where he is often recognized as a bridge between Hegel and Marx. From this axiom, all knowledge of consciousness could be deduced. According to Schelling's "absolute identity" or "indifferentism", there is no difference between the subjective and the objective, that is, the ideal and the real. Friend Reviews. Understanding German Idealism. More attention is paid to Hegel, obviously, and while Pinkard does offer some interesting insights, it is not much of a thorough analysis. The legacy of idealism. German Philosophy 1760-1860: The Legacy of Idealism Reviews Metaphysics Epistemology Logic Ethics Aesthetics. It is saying, in effect, that art cannot give us the most satisfactory understanding of what matters most to us, and that the status of art in our collective lives has thereby changed. The predominant influence of Judeo-Christian theological assumptions are evident here in the conception of a human being as in but not entirely of this world. Truly remarkable discussion of Kant. Foulis, The term "idea-ism" is closer to this intended meaning than the common notion of idealism. Pinkard has a wonderful ability to bring clarity to difficult concepts. Edit this record. But I quickly lost interest in the chapters covering Schelling and Hegel. Readers also enjoyed. The revolution in philosophy II: Autonomy and the moral order; 3. Main article: Analytic philosophy. The s: the immediate post-Kantian reaction: Jacobi and Reinhold; 5. Part of a series on. Philosophy tends to piss me off - these fucking problems just won't go away! Gordon - - History and Theory 44 1 — It is saying, in effect, that art cannot give us the most satisfactory understanding of what matters most to us, and that the status of art in our collective lives has Hegel concluded relatively late in his career that "art, considered in its highest vocation, is and remains for us a thing of the past. See all 9 - All listings for this product. Show More. From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia. Overthrowing the old metaphysics, it inserted a new idea into the vocabulary in terms of which modern Germans and Europeans spoke about their lives: self-determination. He examines the dominant influence of Kant, with his revolutionary emphasis on "self-determination," and traces this influence through the development of romanticism and idealism to the critiques of post-Kantian thinkers such as Schopenhauer and Kierkegaard. A fantastic read that I would recommend highly to anyone interested in Continental philosophy or German history. Views Read Edit View history. Moreover, he appealed boldly and openly to intellectual intuition, that is, really to inspiration. The conundrum of reason and the thing-in-itself has been a spur to philosophers ever since. Soulless and programmatic. The Revolution Continued: Post-Kantians: 4. Packaging should be the same as what is found in a retail store, unless the item is handmade or was packaged by the manufacturer in non-retail packaging, such as an unprinted box or plastic bag.
Recommended publications
  • History and Theory of Philosophy
    FEDERAL STATE BUDGETARY EDUCATIONAL INSTITUTION OF HIGHER EDUCATION "BASHKIR STATE MEDICAL UNIVERSITY" OF THE MINISTRY OF HEALTHCARE OF THE RUSSIAN FEDERATION (FSBEI HE BSMU MOH Russia) HISTORY AND THEORY OF PHILOSOPHY Textbook Ufa 2020 1 UDC 1(09)(075.8) BBC 87.3я7 H90 Reviewers: Doctor of Philosophy, Professor, Head of the department «Social work» FSBEI HE «Bashkir State University» U.S. Vildanov Doctor of Philosophy, Professor at the Department of Philosophy and History FSBEIHE «Bashkir State Agricultural University» A.I. Stoletov History and theory of philosophy:textbook/ K.V. Khramova, H90 R.I. Devyatkina, Z.R. Sadikova, O.M. Ivanova, O.G. Afanasyeva, A.S. Zubairova-Valeeva, N.R. Mingazova, G.R. Davletshina — Ufa: Ufa: FSBEIHEBSMUMOHRussia, 2020. – 127 p. The manual was prepared in accordance with the requirements of the Federal State Educational Standard of Higher Education in specialty 31.05.01 «General Medicine» the current curriculum and on the basis of the work program on the discipline of philosophy. The manual is focused on the competence-based learning model. It has an original, uniform for all classes structure, including the topic, a summary of the training questions, the subject of essays, training materials, test items with response standards, recommended literature. This manual covers topics related to the periods of development of world philosophy. Designed for students in the specialty 31.05.01 «General Medicine». It is recommended to be published by the Coordinating Scientific and Methodological Council and was approved by the decision of the Editorial and Publishing Council of the BSMU of the Ministry of Healthcare of Russia.
    [Show full text]
  • The Outcome of Classical German Philosophy History 71600/CL
    The Outcome of Classical German Philosophy History 71600/CL 85000/PSC Prof. Wolin (GC 5114) Fall 2019 [email protected] Mon. 6:30-8:30 Room: GC ?? In 1886, Friedrich Engels wrote a perfectly mediocre book, Ludwig Feuerbach and the Outcome of Classical German Philosophy, which nevertheless managed to raise a fascinating and important question that is still being debated today: how should we go about evaluating the legacy of German Idealism following the mid-nineteenth century breakdown of the Hegelian system? For Engels, the answer was relatively simple: the rightful heir of classical German philosophy was Marx’s doctrine of historical materialism. But, in truth, Engels’ response was merely one of many possible approaches. Nor would it be much of an exaggeration to claim that, in the twentieth century, there is hardly a philosopher worth reading who has not sought to define him or herself via a confrontation with the legacy of Kant and Hegel. Classical German Philosophy – Kant, Fichte, Hegel, and Schelling – has bequeathed a rich legacy of reflection on the fundamental problems of epistemology, ontology and aesthetics. Even contemporary thinkers who claim to have transcended it (e.g., poststructuralists such as Foucault and Derrida) cannot help but make reference to it in order to validate their post- philosophical standpoints and claims. Our approach to this very rich material will combine a reading of the canonical texts of German Idealism (e.g., Kant and Hegel) with a sustained and complementary focus on major twentieth-century thinkers who have sought to establish their originality via a critical reading of Hegel and his heirs: Alexandre Kojève, Martin Heidegger, Michel Foucault, Theodor Adorno, and Jürgen Habermas.
    [Show full text]
  • 210 the Genesis of Neo-Kantianism
    SYNTHESIS PHILOSOPHICA Book Reviews / Buchbesprechungen 61 (1/2016) pp. (207–220) 210 doi: 10.21464/sp31116 of his book is that the movement’s origins are to be found already in the 1790s, in the Frederick Charles Beiser works of Jakob Friedrich Fries, Johann Frie- drich Herbart, and Friedrich Eduard Beneke. They constitute “the lost tradition” which pre- The Genesis of served the “empiricist-psychological” side of Neo-Kantianism Kant’s thought, his dualisms, and things-in- themselves against the excessive speculative idealism of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel who Oxford University Press, tried to rehabilitate the dogmatic rationalist Oxford 2014 metaphysics of Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff after Kant’s critical project. Frederick Charles Beiser, professor of phi- The first chapter of the first part (pp. 23–88) losophy at Syracuse University (USA) whose is concerned with the philosophy of Fries field of expertise is the modern German phi- who tried to base philosophy on empirical losophy, is one of the most erudite historians psychology, and epistemology on psychol- of philosophy today. His first book The Fate ogy which could recognize the synthetic a of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant priori but not prove it. His book Reinhold, to Fichte (1987) didn’t only present a fresh Fichte und Schelling (1803) saw the history account of German philosophy at the end of of philosophy after Kant as the “struggle of th the 18 century, but it also introduced a new rationalism to free itself from the limits of method of historical research. His more re- the critique”. In his political philosophy Fries cent works, starting with The German His- was an anti-Semite, but gave the leading role toricist Tradition (2011) until the most recent to public opinion which could correct even Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philoso- the ruler, although he encountered problems phy, 1860–1900 (2016), have focused on the in trying to reconcile his liberal views with th main currents of the 19 century German the social injustice that liberalism created.
    [Show full text]
  • Rachel Elizabeth Zuckert Department of Philosophy 5728 N. Kenmore
    Rachel Elizabeth Zuckert Department of Philosophy 5728 N. Kenmore Ave, 3N Northwestern University Chicago, IL 60660 Kresge 3-512 1880 Campus Drive home: (773) 728-7927 Evanston, IL 60208 work: (847) 491-2556 [email protected] Education: 2000 PhD, University of Chicago, Department of Philosophy and the Committee on Social Thought 1995 MA, University of Chicago, Committee on Social Thought 1992 B.A. (1), Oxford University (Philosophy and Modern Languages) 1990 B.A. (Summa Cum Laude; Highest Honors in Philosophy; Phi Beta Kappa), Williams College Areas of Specialization: Kant and eighteenth-century philosophy Aesthetics Areas of Competence: Early modern philosophy Nineteenth-century philosophy Feminist philosophy Languages: French German Academic Employment: 2018- Professor of Philosophy, Northwestern University; affiliated with the German Department 2008-18 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Northwestern University; affiliated with the German Department 2011-18 2006-2008 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Northwestern University 2001-2006 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Rice University 1999-2001 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Bucknell University Zuckert 2 Publications: Books Kant on Beauty and Biology: An Interpretation of the Critique of Judgment, Cambridge University Press, 2007. Awarded the American Society for Aesthetics Monograph Prize (2008); reviewed in British Journal for the History of Philosophy, Comparative and Continental Philosophy, Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, Journal of the History of Philosophy, Metascience, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, Review of Metaphysics, and subject of review essays in Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism and Kant Yearbook Herder’s Naturalist Aesthetics, Cambridge University Press, forthcoming (2019). Edited Volume Hegel on Philosophy in History, co-edited with James Kreines, Cambridge University Press, 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Psychology Faculty Publications Psychology 1982 Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E. Leary University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/psychology-faculty- publications Part of the Theory and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Leary, David E. "Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology." In The Problematic Science: Psychology in Nineteenth- Century Thought, edited by William Ray Woodward and Mitchell G. Ash, 17-42. New York, NY: Praeger, 1982. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Psychology at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Psychology Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E. Leary Few thinkers in the history of Western civilization have had as broad and lasting an impact as Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). This "Sage of Konigsberg" spent his entire life within the confines of East Prussia, but his thoughts traveled freely across Europe and, in time, to America, where their effects are still apparent. An untold number of analyses and commentaries have established Kant as a preeminent epistemologist, philosopher of science, moral philosopher, aestheti­ cian, and metaphysician. He is even recognized as a natural historian and cosmologist: the author of the so-called Kant-Laplace hypothesis regarding the origin of the universe. He is less often credited as a "psychologist," "anthropologist," or "philosopher of mind," to Work on this essay was supported by the National Science Foundation (Grant No.
    [Show full text]
  • “Austrian” and “German” Philosophy in the 19Th Century
    Christian Damböck (Dis-)Similarities: Remarks on “Austrian” and “German” Philosophy in the 19th Century In this paper, I re-examine Barry Smith’s 1994 list of features of Austrian Philosophy. I claim that the list properly applies only in a somewhat abbreviated form to all significant representatives of Austrian Philosophy. Moreover, Smith’s crucial thesis that the features of Austrian Philosophy are not shared by any German philosopher only holds if we compare Austrian Philosophy to a canonical list of Ger- man Philosophy II. This list, however, was established in 20th century as a result of historical misrep- resentations. If we correct these misrepresentations, we obtain another list of hidden representatives called German Philosophy I. German Philosophy I is fundamentally identical to Austrian Philosophy, whereas German Philosophy II is entirely different from both Austrian Philosophy and German Phi- losophy I. Therefore, a slightly modified version of Smith’s Austrian Philosophy account still makes sense as a tool to position the pro-scientific and rational currents of Austrian Philosophy and German Philosophy I against the tendentially anti-scientific and irrational current of German Philosophy II. Although Austria and Germany1 were independent nations in the 19th century, there are many aspects that overlap between the countries. Austria and Germany share the same language, and the borders between Austria and Germany were always more or less open for academics to move from one country to the other.2 Religious differences do exist, but they do not coincide with national borders. Whereas Austria is mainly Catholic and Germany is mainly Protestant, important parts of (southwestern) Germany are mainly Catholic as well.
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel After Augustine, an Essay on Political Theology Geoffrey J.D
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Transcending Subjects: Hegel After Augustine, an Essay on Political Theology Geoffrey J.D. Holsclaw Marquette University Recommended Citation Holsclaw, Geoffrey J.D., "Transcending Subjects: Hegel After Augustine, an Essay on Political Theology" (2013). Dissertations (2009 -). Paper 303. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/303 TRANSCENDING SUBJECTS: HEGEL AFTER AUGUSTINE, AN ESSAY ON POLITICAL THEOLOGY by Geoffrey J. D. Holsclaw, B.A., M.Div. A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Milwaukee, Wisconsin December 2013 ABSTRACT TRANSCENDING SUBJECTS: HEGEL AFTER AUGUSTINE, AN ESSAY ON POLITICAL THEOLOGY Geoffrey J. D. Holsclaw, B.A., M.Div. Marquette University, 2013 From where do political reformers and radicals come who are willing and prepared to challenge the status quo? Where are people formed who are capable of initiating change within a political system? Some worry belief in transcendence closes off authentic political engagement and processes of transformation. Others think that a transcendent orientation is the only means to protect and promote a more free and just society. Some see a positive commitment to transcendence as inimical to democratic practices, while others see such a commitment as indispensible for such a project. These general issues concern transcendence, immanence, and subjectivity as they bear on the question of political transformation. Explaining the differences between these fundamental orientations prompts an investigation of the philosophical and theological systems of Hegel and Augustine. Examining Hegel and Augustine around the issues of transcendence and freedom offers a way to understand these more localized disagreements between political philosophers and theologians, and even between theologians.
    [Show full text]
  • German Legal Philosophy
    Michigan Law Review Volume 16 Issue 5 1918 German Legal Philosophy John M. Zane Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation John M. Zane, German Legal Philosophy, 16 MICH. L. REV. 287 (1918). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol16/iss5/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MICHIGAN LAW REVIEW VOL. XVI. MARCH, 1918 No. 5 .. GERMAN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY. "We shall not light up our temple from that unhallowed fire. It will be illuminated with other lights. It will be perfumed with o'ther incense than the infectious stuff which is imported by the smugglers of adulterated metaphysics."-Burke. NNEXED as an appendix to the translation of Kohler's Phil­ A osophy of Law is an appreciation of the work bv Adolf Las­ son,1 who complains that he himself once wrote a philosophy of law which has sunk into oblivion, probably for the reason, as he modestly suggests, that he knew so much of systematic philosophy that he had no time to acquire any "special scientific learning either 1 A professor at the University of :Berlin, who published in 1882 a "System der Rechtsphilosophie" w)lich is the work to which he refers as characterized by little knowl­ edge of law.
    [Show full text]
  • The Outcome of Classical German Philosophy History 71600/CL
    The Outcome of Classical German Philosophy History 71600/CL 85000 Prof. Wolin Fall 2014 [email protected] Mon. TBA x8446 In 1886, Friedrich Engels wrote a perfectly mediocre book, Ludwig Feuerbach and the Outcome of Classical German Philosophy, which nevertheless managed to raise a fascinating and important question that is still being debated today: how should we go about evaluating the legacy of German Idealism following the mid-nineteenth century breakdown of the Hegelian system? For Engels, the answer was relatively simple: the rightful heir of classical German philosophy was Marx’s doctrine of historical materialism. But, in truth, Engels’ response was merely one of many possible approaches. Nor would it be much of an exaggeration to claim that, in the twentieth-century, there is hardly a philosopher worth reading who has not sought to define him or herself via a confrontation with the legacy of Kant and Hegel. Classical German Philosophy – Kant, Fichte, Hegel, and Schelling – has bequeathed a rich legacy of reflection on the fundamental problems of epistemology, ontology and aesthetics. Even contemporary thinkers who claim to have transcended it (e.g., poststructuralists such as Foucault and Derrida) cannot help but make reference to it in order to validate their post- philosophical standpoints and claims. Our approach to this very rich material will combine a reading of the canonical texts of German Idealism (e.g., Kant and Hegel) with a sustained and complementary focus on major twentieth-century thinkers who have sought to establish their originality via a critical reading of Hegel and his heirs: Alexandre Kojève, Martin Heidegger, Michel Foucault, Theodor Adorno, and Jürgen Habermas.
    [Show full text]
  • (1724-1804). Immanuel Kant Was Born and Spent His Life in Königsberg, Prussia, Now Kaliningrad, Russia
    1 KANT, IMMANUEL (1724-1804). Immanuel Kant was born and spent his life in Königsberg, Prussia, now Kaliningrad, Russia. Although his family was poor, Kant was educated in a good Pietist school and attended the University of Königsberg from 1740- 1747. From 1747-1755 he worked as a private tutor for various families in the Königsberg area. From 1755 -1770 he was a Privatdozent at the University, lecturing on subjects as diverse as logic, mathematics, metaphysics, ethics, anthropology, and geography. In 1770 he became Professor of Logic and Metaphysics. He taught until 1796, and died in 1804. Restricted to a quiet life by a modest income, delicate health, and a demanding workload, Kant never married or traveled. Popular tradition portrays Kant as rigid and moralistic, as devoted to system and rule in his life as he was in his work. This picture must be tempered by the less familiar set of images handed down to us by his friends and students: of a genial host famous for his powers of conversation; of an immensely popular teacher whose students claimed that they “never left a single lecture in his ethics without having become better men”; and of “the Old Jacobin” whose passionate defense of the French Revolution astonished and inspired his contemporaries. EARLY VIEWS AND THE CRITICAL PROJECT. Kant was educated in the predominant “Leibniz-Wolffian philosophy,” an extreme form of dogmatic rationalism, but its influence on him was mitigated by his interest in British philosophy and science. A disposition to question the power of pure reason shows up even in his “pre-critical” works, those written before he made the discoveries that led to the three Critiques.
    [Show full text]
  • John Locke in the German Enlightenment: an Interpretation Klaus P
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Chapman University Digital Commons Chapman University Chapman University Digital Commons Philosophy Faculty Articles and Research Philosophy 1975 John Locke in the German Enlightenment: An Interpretation Klaus P. Fischer Chapman University Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/philosophy_articles Part of the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Mind Commons Recommended Citation Fischer, Klaus P. "John Locke in the German enlightenment: an interpretation." Journal of the History of Ideas (1975): 431-446. DOI:10.2307/2708655 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Chapman University Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Articles and Research by an authorized administrator of Chapman University Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. John Locke in the German Enlightenment: An Interpretation Comments This article was originally published in Journal of the History of Ideas in 1975. DOI: 10.2307/2708655 Copyright University of Pennsylvania Press This article is available at Chapman University Digital Commons: http://digitalcommons.chapman.edu/philosophy_articles/1 JOHN LOCKE IN THE GERMAN ENLIGHTENMENT: AN INTERPRETATION BY KLAUSP. FISCHER I. A favorite assumptionof Anglo-Americanscholarship, endlessly repeated in textbooks and monographs,is that Locke's philosophy triumphed in every nook and cranny of Western Europe. By im- plication,it is also assumed that other philosophicsystems, especially those of Descartes and Leibniz, withered away without much op- position. The reigningphilosophy of the Enlightenment,we are told, was that of Locke and his disciples in Englandand on the Continent.
    [Show full text]
  • THE CRISIS of NEO-KANTIANISM and the REASSESSMENT of KANT AFTER WORLD WAR I: PRELIMINARY Remarkphil 346 17..40
    © 2010 The Philosophical Forum, Inc. THE CRISIS OF NEO-KANTIANISM AND THE REASSESSMENT OF KANT AFTER WORLD WAR I: PRELIMINARY REMARKphil_346 17..40 PETER UWE HOHENDAHL The papers to be presented at this conference deal with a decisive turning point in the understanding of Immanuel Kant in the first half of the 20th century. What we can observe is an increasingly radical transformation, not only with respect to the interpretation of Kant but also concerning the attitude toward Critical Philosophy, that is, Kantianism in general. My remarks will try to throw some light on this turn or divide, which in the minds of those involved was sometimes referred to as the divide between the old and the new way of thinking. I have decided to focus on two issues. First of all, I want to look at the stakes of this conference. Why is it important to reexamine the turn in Kant studies in the early 20th century? Second, I want to look briefly at five thinkers to show what is involved in the challenge to and the break with the Kant orthodoxy of the prewar era. My examples will be Georg Lukács, Rudolf Carnap, Edmund Husserl, Martin Heidegger, and finally Max Horkheimer. In discussing these authors, I will focus more on the moment of redefining the approach to Kant without fully exploring the history of their prior involvement with Kant or the neo-Kantians. The result of this method is potentially an overemphasis on the moment of opposition and critique while aspects of continuity are mentioned but not stressed.1 It would not be difficult for instance to show the continued influence of neo-Kantianism in the German academy of the 1920s.
    [Show full text]