Pittacus of Mytilene on the Island of Lesbos
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Herakleitos (121.6Kb)
The Reign of the Whirlwind 122 Chapter 7 Herakleitos ----------- 1. Life and book We have very little reliable information about the life of Herakleitos son of Bloson, of Ephesos. It is clear from the biographical accounts that survive, that the Alexandrian scholars could find little, even though they were not fussy about reliability. They made up anecdotes to fit some of the more striking sayings of this paradox-loving writer; and as a result, “Herakleitos the Dark” became even more obscure. We have to guess, first, at his dates. He knows something about Pythagoras and Xenophanes; and Parmenides seems to know something about him. We can hazard the conjecture that his book was written by 500 BCE (when Xenophanes had still the last quarter of his long life to live, and Pythagoras was in his last years). This would make 545 BCE a reasonable guess for his birth date. He probably died before 480.i Herakleitos belonged to the ancient royal clan of Ephesos. He is said to have deposited his book in the great temple of Artemis for which his native city was famous (22 A 1).ii We can fairly suppose that it was in his eyes the worthy trophy of a greater victory than any triumph in arms. Whether he was actually melancholic (“the weeping philosopher” as he came to be called)iii we cannot say. He was certainly both an angry man, and an intellectual aristocrat. There are some The Reign of the Whirlwind 123 “sayings” of his that were not in the book. In one plausible story, he “upbraids the Ephesians . -
MONEY and the EARLY GREEK MIND: Homer, Philosophy, Tragedy
This page intentionally left blank MONEY AND THE EARLY GREEK MIND How were the Greeks of the sixth century bc able to invent philosophy and tragedy? In this book Richard Seaford argues that a large part of the answer can be found in another momentous development, the invention and rapid spread of coinage, which produced the first ever thoroughly monetised society. By transforming social relations, monetisation contributed to the ideas of the universe as an impersonal system (presocratic philosophy) and of the individual alienated from his own kin and from the gods (in tragedy). Seaford argues that an important precondition for this monetisation was the Greek practice of animal sacrifice, as represented in Homeric epic, which describes a premonetary world on the point of producing money. This book combines social history, economic anthropology, numismatics and the close reading of literary, inscriptional, and philosophical texts. Questioning the origins and shaping force of Greek philosophy, this is a major book with wide appeal. richard seaford is Professor of Greek Literature at the University of Exeter. He is the author of commentaries on Euripides’ Cyclops (1984) and Bacchae (1996) and of Reciprocity and Ritual: Homer and Tragedy in the Developing City-State (1994). MONEY AND THE EARLY GREEK MIND Homer, Philosophy, Tragedy RICHARD SEAFORD cambridge university press Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, UK Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521832281 © Richard Seaford 2004 This publication is in copyright. -
Eis-Booklet.Pdf
EX IONIA SCIENTIA – KNOWLEDGE IN ARCHAIC GREECE INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE NATIONAL AND KAPODISTRIAN UNIVERSITY OF ATHENS DEC 11-14, 2016 PROGRAM pp. 2‒7 ABSTRACTS PP. 8‒54 LIST OF PARTICIPANTS pp. 55‒58 For more information, visit our Website: http://enlightenedionia.siu.edu/ contact: USA: Dr. Robert Hahn (Southern Illinois University, Carbondale, [email protected]) EUROPE: PD Dr. Alexander Herda (Humboldt University, Berlin, [email protected]) GREECE: Dr. Sotiris Fournaros (National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, [email protected]) 1 EX IONIA SCIENTIA – KNOWLEDGE IN ARCHAIC GREECE INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE NATIONAL AND KAPODISTRIAN UNIVERSITY OF ATHENS, DEC 11-14, 2016 PROGRAM SUNDAY 11 DECEMBER Theocharakis Foundation, 9 Vasilissis Sofias & Merlin Street, 10671 Athens 16:00-16:45 WELCOME ADRESSES/INTRODUCTORY REMARKS chair: Panagiotis PANTAZAKOS 1) Meletios A. DIMOPOULOS (Rector of National and Kapodistrian University of Athens) 2) Theodosios PELEGRINIS (Former Rector of National and Kapodistrian University of Athens) 3) Marisa FOUNTOPOULOU (NKU, Head of the Department of Philosophy, Pedagogy and Psychology) 4) Elsi BACONICOLA-YIAMA (NKU, Director of the Section of Philosophy) 5) Sotiris FOURNAROS (NKU, Athens) 6) Alexander HERDA (Humboldt University Berlin) 7) Robert HAHN (Southern Illinois University, Carbondale) 16:45-18:15 KEYNOTES 16:45-17:30 1) Andrew GREGORY (University College London) Anaximander, Cosmology and the Poets 17:30-18:15 2) Alexander MOURELATOS (The University of Texas at Austin) Xenophanes of Colophon and -
Waiting for Solon: Audience Expectations in Herodotus ∗
Histos () – WAITING FOR SOLON: AUDIENCE EXPECTATIONS IN HERODOTUS ∗ Abstract: In this article, I focus not so much on what Solon actually says and does in his conversation with Croesus, but on what Herodotus’ readers, as well as Croesus himself, think Solon might say or do. I argue that Herodotus uses analogous episodes, those of Gyges, Candaules, and Candaules’ wife, of Arion and Periander, and of Bias/Pittacus and Croesus, to shape readers’ expectations of Solon’s conversation with Croesus, but he then subverts many of those expectations within the conversation itself. In so doing, Herodotus emphasises the programmatic function for the Histories of much of what Solon tells Croesus. Keywords: Herodotus, Arion, artistic patronage, audience expectations, Candaules, Croesus, Seven Sages, Solon cholars have long recognised the programmatic quality that the encounter between Solon and Croesus (.– ) has for Herodotus’ S Histories .1 Croesus’ importance alone for Herodotus’ work cannot be underestimated. In a sense, Herodotus begins the Histories with Croesus; he follows the story of Croesus and the Lydian Mermnad dynasty from its beginning with Gyges’ murder of Candaules all the way to its conclusion with Croesus’ defeat by the Persian king Cyrus. Croesus also occupies a primary position in the Histories as the first in the line of great eastern imperialists that culminates with the Persian Xerxes. On the one hand, the Solon–Croesus episode foreshadows Croesus’ impending downfall. On the other hand, the episode reflects many of Herodotus’ chief thematic concerns: the conflict between East and West and the clash between different cultures in general; the mutability of human fortune and the gods’ jealousy of human excess; the wise advisor motif and the challenge of acquiring knowledge. -
Gnōthi Sauton — “Know Thyself” © 2020 by Andrew Scholtz
Gnōthi sauton — “Know Thyself” © 2020 by Andrew Scholtz Greek Spelling, Roman Transliteration, English Translation γνῶθι σαὐτόν (or without contraction, σεαυτόν — σαὐτόν blends the epsilon into the alpha-upsilon sound) gnōthi sauton (or seauton — “au” as in “ouch!”) “Know thyself” (gnōthi, a command form, = “get to know,” “become acquainted with,” “learn [about],” “know”) Basic Information Conventionally, if somewhat inaccurately, treated, along with mēden agan (“Nothing to excess!”), as a defining catchphrase of ancient Greek culture and thought Said to have been inscribed, along with mēden agan, onto the wall of the forecourt of Apollo’s temple at Delphi Traditionally attributed to, among others, Chilon of Sparta (ca. 550 BCE) — older cer- tainly than the philosopher Socrates, with whom the saying is, nevertheless, closely associated Mini-Essay γνῶθι σαὐτόν, γnōthi sauton, “Know thyself!” — this nugget of wisdom, along with sev- eral others (“Nothing to excess,” etc.), was originally inscribed in the entrance porch of the Temple of Apollo at Delphi. That’s going to be significant: Delphi was the main place to go when you wanted answers. There, the god would speak to you via his mouthpiece, the Pythia. Her utterances would then be edited by the priests of the place and handed over to you. “Know Thyself!” A. Scholtz 2 The saying in Greek may have looked something like this — archaic alphabet, right-to- left writing, etc., sort of a guess: In the 1999 film The Matrix, there is a scene in the apartment of the character known as the Oracle. Above her kitchen door hangs a plaque with the following inscription, Nosce temet, which Latinists will recognize as a translation of gnōthi sauton, Greek for “Know thyself,” from the temple of Apollo at Delphi. -
MINEOLA BIBLE INSTITUTE and SEMINARY Philosophy II Radically
MINEOLA BIBLE INSTITUTE AND SEMINARY Page | 1 Philosophy II Radically, Biblical, Apostolic, Christianity Bishop D.R. Vestal, PhD Larry L Yates, ThD, DMin “Excellence in Apostolic Education since 1991” 1 Copyright © 2019 Mineola Bible Institute Page | 2 All Rights Reserved This lesson material may not be used in any manner for reproduction in any language or use without the written permission of Mineola Bible Institute. 2 Contents Introduction ................................................................................................................................. 7 Alexander the Great (356-323 B.C.) ........................................................................................... 8 Philip II of Macedonia (382-336 B.C.) ....................................................................................... 12 Page | 3 “Olympias the mother of Alexander was an evil woman. .......................................... 13 Philip II (of Macedonia) (382-336 BC) .............................................................................. 13 Aristotle (384-322 BC) ............................................................................................................... 15 Works .................................................................................................................................... 16 Methods ............................................................................................................................... 17 Doctrines ............................................................................................................................ -
A Presocratics Reader
2. THE MILESIANS Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes were all from the city of Miletus in Ionia (now the western coast of Turkey) and make up what is referred to as the Milesian “school” of philosophy. Tradition reports that Thales was the teacher of Anaximander, who in turn taught Anaximenes. Aristotle begins his account of the history of philosophy as the search for causes and principles (in Metaphysics I) with these three. 2.1. Thales Thales appears on lists of the seven sages of Greece, a traditional catalog of wise men. The chronicler Apollodorus suggests that he was born around 625 BCE. We should accept this date only with caution, as Apollodorus usually calculated birthdates by assuming that a man was forty years old at the time of his “acme,” or greatest achievement. Thus, Apollodorus arrives at the date by assuming that Thales indeed predicted an eclipse in 585 BCE, and was forty at the time. Plato and Aristotle tell stories about Thales that show that even in ancient times philosophers had a mixed reputation for practicality. 1. (11A9) They say that once when Thales was gazing upwards while doing astronomy, he fell into a well, and that a witty and charming Thracian serving-girl made fun of him for being eager to know the things in the heavens but failing to notice what was just behind him and right by his feet. (Plato, Theaetetus 174a) 2. (11A10) The story goes that when they were reproaching him for his poverty, supposing that philosophy is useless, he learned from his astronomy that the olive crop would be large. -
The Seven Sages.Pdf
Document belonging to the Greek Mythology Link, a web site created by Carlos Parada, author of Genealogical Guide to Greek Mythology Characters • Places • Topics • Images • Bibliography • PDF Editions About • Copyright © 1997 Carlos Parada and Maicar Förlag. The Seven Sages of Greece Search the GML advanced Sections in this Page Introduction: The Labyrinth of Wisdom The Seven Sages of Greece Thales Solon Chilon Pittacus Bias "… wisdom is a form of goodness, and is not scientific knowledge but Cleobulus another kind of cognition." (Aristotle, Eudemian Ethics 1246b, 35). Periander Anacharsis Myson Epimenides Pherecydes Table: Lists of the Seven Sages Notes and Sources of Quotations Introduction: The Labyrinth of Wisdom For a god wisdom is perhaps a divine meal to be swallowed at one gulp without need of mastication, and that would be the end of the story. The deities are known for their simplicity. The matter of human wisdom, however, could fill all archives on earth without ever exhausting itself. Humanity is notorious for its complexity. And men proudly say "Good things are difficult." But is wisdom a labyrinth, or "thinking makes it so"? And when did the saga of human wisdom begin and with whom? The Poet When humans contemplated Dawn for the first time, wisdom was the treasure of the poet alone. Of all men he was the wisest, for the gods had chosen his soul as receptacle of their confidences. Thus filled with inspiration divine, the poet knew better than any other man the secrets of the world. And since Apollo found more pleasure in leading the Muses than in warming his tripod, neither the inspiration of the Pythia nor that of seers could match the poet's wisdom. -
Literary Quarrels
Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics (1) The Cicala's Song: Plato in the Aetia Benjamin Acosta-Hughes University of Michigan, Ann Arbor Version 1.2 © Benjamin Acosta-Hughes, [email protected] (2) Literary Quarrels Susan Stephens Stanford University Version 1.0 © Susan Stephens Abstract: Scholars have long noted Platonic elements or allusions in Callimachus' poems, particularly in the Aetia prologue and the 13th Iambus that center on poetic composition. Following up on their work, Benjamin Acosta-Hughes and Susan Stephens, in a recent panel at the APA, and in papers that are about to appear in Callimachea II. Atti della seconda giornata di studi su Callimaco (Rome: Herder), have argued not for occasional allusions, but for a much more extensive influence from the Phaedo and Phaedrus in the Aetia prologue (Acosta-Hughes) and the Protagoras, Ion, and Phaedrus in the Iambi (Stephens). These papers are part of a preliminary study to reformulate Callimachus' aesthetic theory. 1 The Cicala's Song: Plato in the Aetia* This paper prefigures a larger study of Callimachus and Plato, a study on which my Stanford colleague Susan Stephens and I have now embarked in our co-authored volume on Callimachus.1 Awareness of Platonic allusion in Callimachus is not new, although its significance has not really been appreciateda close reading of the two authors remains a real desideratum, and it is indeed this need that we hope our work will one day fulfill. The main focal points of the present paper are two passages of Callimachus, and two passages of Plato, that, read together, configure a remarkable intertextual dialogue on poetry, reading, and the inspired voice. -
' Sophia ' and ' Epistēmē ' in the Archaic and Classical Periods
1 ‘ Sophia ’ and ‘ Epistēmē ’ in the Archaic and Classical Periods David Wolfsdorf 1. Introduction My aim here is to discuss the philosophical use of the terms ‘ sophia ’ and ‘ epistēmē ’ in relation to one another from their earliest occurrences through Aristotle. I begin with pre- philosophical use for this will help to explain the philosophers’ employment and adaptation of the terms. 2. Pre- philosophical uses of ‘ sophiē ’ In philosophical contexts the originally Ionic noun ‘ sophiē ’, later Attic ‘ sophia ’, is standardly translated as ‘wisdom’, the adjective ‘ sophos ’ as ‘wise’. But this will not do for the earliest, pre- philosophical use (cf. Snell 1924 : 1– 20; Gauthier and Jolif 1959 : 479– 89; Gladigow 1965 ; Meier 1970 ). In eighth- and seventh- century poetry ‘ sophiē ’ means ‘skill’, ‘ sophos ’ ‘skilled’ or ‘skilful’. 1 As we will see, wisdom is skill; but in the early poets the skills denoted by these terms are not forms of wisdom. Formal semanticists have noted that ‘skill’, ‘skilful’, and ‘skilled’ are semantically incomplete terms in the sense that a person who has skill or is skilful isn’t skilful simpliciter , but in a particular domain. Compare ‘citizen’, which is semantically incomplete in a distinct, but related way: one is not a citizen simpliciter , but of a particular political body. T ere are various theories of such semantic incompleteness. In the case of ‘skilful’ one view is that in its so- called logical, as opposed to surface grammatical, form the predicate contains a domain variable whose value is supplied by context 99781474258272_pi-260.indd781474258272_pi-260.indd 1111 228-Mar-188-Mar-18 112:47:402:47:40 PPMM 12 Knowledge in Ancient Philosophy (be it linguistic or extralinguistic). -
Self-Knowledge, Tyranny, and the Delphic Oracle in Plato's Charmides
Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 1-7-2006 Self-Knowledge, Tyranny, and the Delphic Oracle in Plato's Charmides Alan Pichanick George Washington University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Pichanick, Alan, "Self-Knowledge, Tyranny, and the Delphic Oracle in Plato's Charmides" (2006). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 357. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/357 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Self-Knowledge, Tyranny, and the Delphic Oracle in Plato’s Charmides Alan Pichanick, George Washington University SAGP at Philologists, Montreal January 2006 1. The Problem of the Charmides In Plato’s Charmides1 Socrates conducts an inquiry with the young Charmides and his guardian and cousin Critias, in order to find the elusive quality, sôphrosunê. As T.G. Tuckey says, the word has a variety of meanings, referring to “wisdom, discretion, self-respect, moderation, chastity, temperance, prudence.”2 Most translators render it as “moderation” or “temperance” or even “self-discipline”. A more literal translation of sôphrosunê would be “sound-mindedness”. For “sophron” is the result of a combination of two other Greek words, sôs and phrên.34 Perhaps the best approach, though, is to leave sôphrosunê untranslated, and that is what I shall do. -
Encounters at Delphi Rosicrucian Library Research Staff
Encounters at Delphi Rosicrucian Library Research Staff ver the millennium of its activity, the Oracle at Delphi gave advice to those Ofrom many walks of life, with some times surprising results. Collected here are some of these Oracular responses, as recorded by ancient historians and supplicants of the Oracle. 1 Know Thyself of the Pythian oracle, can easily conform One of the great inscriptions at the themselves to all the affairs of life, and Temple of Apollo at Delphi was Gnothi bear them handsomely; considering their Seauton (“Know Thyself”). Sages have nature, so that they are neither lifted up debated its meaning and achievability for to arrogance upon a prosperous event, nor the thousands of years since prophecy began when an adverse happens, are dejected into at Delphi: complaint through pusillanimity and that “When he was asked what was very fear of death which is so congenial to us; difficult, Thales said, ‘To know one’s self.’ both which proceed from the ignorance of And what was easy, ‘To advise another.’ those things which fall out in human life by What was most pleasant? ‘To be successful.’ necessity and fatal decree.”3 To the question, ‘What is the divinity?’ he “The maxim ‘Know thyself’ comes down replied ‘That which has neither beginning to us from the skies; it should be imprinted in 2 nor end.’ ” the heart, and stored in the memory.”4 “There are two sentences inscribed upon the Delphic oracle, hugely accommodated to the usages of a human being’s life, Know thyself, and Nothing too much; and upon Take Council with the Majority these all other precepts depend.