Three Chronic Errors: Some Misconceptions Concerning the Direction of Time

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Three Chronic Errors: Some Misconceptions Concerning the Direction of Time 1 Three Chronic Errors: Some Misconceptions concerning the Direction of Time In a subject in which differing opinions are rife, it is difficult to discern anything like a consensus on what constitutes the direction of time. Physicists routinely identify it with the direction of increasing entropy, and then part company over whether this is in turn founded on such esoterica as the expansion of the universe (Gold), the no-boundary condition + weak anthropic principle (Hawking), a broken time-symmetry at the microscopic level (Prigogine), or the surfeit of entropy produced by a massive inflation of spacetime in the first –35 10 seconds of the universe’s existence (Guth, Davies).1 Philosophers, on the other hand, have been skeptical of attempts to define time’s direction in terms of entropy considerations, at least since the failure of Reichenbach’s efforts in mid-century.2 Grünbaum has abandoned the idea of a ‘direction’ in favor of an anisotropy between the two possible directions of time3; Earman doubts the relevance of entropy4; and Mehlberg, Horwich and Price see time as intrinsically symmetric.5 There is, nevertheless, an orthodoxy of sorts. For, despite their differences over the origin or relevance of the Second Law of Thermodynamics, all these authors (save Prigogine) agree on the following premises as their point of departure: the direction of time is not the direction in which events “come to be”, since temporal becoming is a mere facet of 1 Thomas Gold, “Cosmic Processes and the Nature of Time”, in Mind and Cosmos, ed. Robert G. Colodny (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966), 311-329; Stephen Hawking, “The No- Boundary Condition and the Arrow of Time”, in The Physical Origins of Time Asymmetry ed. J. J. Halliwell, J. Perez-Mercader and W. H. Zurek (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), pp. 346-57; and Ilya Prigogine, From Being to Becoming (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1980), ch. 8; Paul Davies, “The Inflationary Universe: Was the cosmos born in a fleck of foam?”, The Sciences 23, 2, 32-37. 2 Hans Reichenbach, The Direction of Time (Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1956). 3 Adolf Grünbaum, “The Meaning of Time,” in Basic Issues in the Philosophy of Time , ed. Eugene Freeman and Wilfrid Sellars (La Salle, Ill., Open Court, 1971), pp. 196-227. 4 John Earman, “Irreversibility and Temporal Asymmetry”, Journal of Philosophy, LXIV, 18, 543- 549, 1967 5 Henryk Mehlberg, “Philosophical Aspects of Physical Time”, in Basic Issues, ed. Freeman and Sellars (1971); pp. 16-60; Paul Horwich, Asymmetries in Time (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), ch. 3; and Huw Price, Time’s Arrow and Archimedes’ Point (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996). 1 2 subjective experience. That is, the laws of physics do not distinguish between past and future; events simply “are” in spacetime; they do not “become” in serial fashion.6 As Grünbaum expresses it, there is nothing more to temporal change than the (“tenseless”) occurrence of events or states at different times. Thus, although his point of view denies “that physical events themselves happen in the tensed sense of coming into being apart from anyone’s awareness of them”, it nevertheless asserts that they “do happen independently of any mind in the tenseless sense of merely occurring at certain clock times in the context of objective relations of earlier and later”.7 Given these premises it is easy enough to see how the direction of time becomes a “problem”. For if all events simply lie in a relation of temporal succession to other events in the four-dimensional spacetime manifold, yet do not actually come to be out of those that preceded them, then we can equally well read the order in either direction. This then raises the question, how does our conception of time’s direction arise? Why is it that we experience events as coming to be in one direction only? Why are so many facets of our experience temporally asymmetric? The standard answer to these questions has been to explain all of these facts as arising from the existence of irreversible processes. If there were no such processes, it is claimed, then time would be intrinsically symmetric. It would be just like one of the spatial dimensions, on which we can conventionally order objects asymmetrically, for instance from left to right. But this corresponds to no preferred direction of the line itself, and to no feature of the objects lying on the line: it is merely imposed by us. Irreversible processes, however, are thought (by most) to spoil this symmetry. There is all the difference in the world between the kinds of processes one sees in a typical video, and the impossible processes one sees when the video is played backwards, such as spilled coffee and shards of china miraculously composing into a cup of coffee leaping up in a graceful parabola onto some nearby table. The process of a cup of coffee falling off the table and smashing is irreversible, 6 Cf. Hermann Weyl’s famous remark: “The objective world simply is, it does not happen”, Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science ( ), p. 116; and Adolf Grünbaum, “Time, Irreversible Processes and the Physical Status of Becoming”, in J. J. C. Smart, Problems of Space and Time (New York: Macmillan, 1964), pp. 397-425: “the relativistic picture of the world … conceives of events not as ‘coming into existence’ but as simply being and thus allowing us to ‘come across’ them” (417). 2 3 and knowing that its time-reverse is impossible allows us to determine which way time is “flowing” for the processes filmed in the video. Processes go from a state of low entropy to a state of high entropy (at least in isolated systems, over a sufficiently long time). Thus entropy can be used to fix the “arrow of time”. Or, on Grünbaum’s more considered version of this view, the existence of irreversible processes allows us to single out one of the directions along the time axis as preferred, and enables us to fix the direction of increasing entropy as that from earlier to later.8 Now I do not at all accept this consensus, and this is because I do not accept the premise on which it is based: the denial of the reality of becoming and process. I shall not argue directly for the reality of becoming here;9 my intention is rather to show how its denial has led to certain deep-going errors in discussions of the direction of time–the “chronic errors” of my title. (By the way, in calling the errors “chronic” I do not mean to suggest they are “egregious”, to use Grünbaum’s favourite term for bemoaning his critics’ errors; I only call them this because they run deep and have been around for some time; and, of course, because I couldn’t resist the pun). And since I do not believe a coherent account of the direction of time is possible which does not in some way presuppose becoming or lapse into incoherency, then to the extent that my critique of orthodoxy is successful it should constitute an indirect argument for my view. Let me be more explicit about what my view is. I maintain that temporal becoming is an objective fact; and this is entirely sufficient to explain the direction of time neatly and without residue. That is, each and every event or happening comes into existence out of earlier events and conditions; a sequence of such events ordered by the relation of “comes to be out of” or “is later than” is what we call a process; and the direction in which this becoming occurs is what we call the direction of time. Otherwise stated, the order of 7 Grünbaum, “Meaning” (1971), p. 213-14. 8 Grünbaum, “Meaning” (1971), p. 210? Even those who reject the explanation of time's direction in terms of entropy (with the notable exception of Earman) agree that time has two possible directions, and that if they cannot be distinguished from one another by means of irreversible processes or some other such criterion, then time is intrinsically symmetric. See Mehlberg, Price. 3 4 temporal succession is intrinsically asymmetric, and this is what constitutes the time- orientedness of every natural process. Stated so baldly, this will so far seem not much more than a contradiction of some of the main tenets of the orthodox position, such as the distinction between time asymmetry and time direction or anisotropy. Worse, it seems to assert as a physical fact what the usual theories set about trying to explain, the origin of time asymmetry. Compared to the sophistication of the attempts to ground time asymmetry on an asymmetry in boundary conditions, or on a broken time-symmetry at the microscopic level, or on the surfeit of entropy produced by a massive inflation of spacetime in the first 10-35 seconds of the universe’s existence, a mere assertion of intrinsic asymmetry is bound to appear prosaic. I acknowledge these objections; but I cannot do anything to assuage them, since I am persuaded that the attempts to found time asymmetry in something more basic are ultimately incoherent. I shall argue that the existence of irreversible processes is one thing, the violation of the symmetry of time reversal invariance another, and the asymmetry of time another, and that the conflation of these matters is a cause of much of the difficulty in this subject. The Three Errors But I believe three errors in particular have bedevilled discussion of the direction of time. Let me begin by outlining them. I have already mentioned that many leading philosophers of science have expressed skepticism about the viability of defining the direction of time on the basis of the second law of thermodynamics.
Recommended publications
  • The Role of Philosophy in a Naturalized World
    EuJAP | Vol. 8 | No. 1 | 2012 ORIGINAL SCIENTIFIC PAPER UDK: 1 Dummett, M. 1:53 530.1:140.8 113/119 THE ROLE OF PHILOSOPHY IN A NATURALIZED WORLD JAN FAYE University of Copenhagen ABSTRACT 1. Introduction This paper discusses the late Michael Dummett’s Why are humanists and natural scientists characterization of the estrangement between unable to understand one another? Th is physics and philosophy. It argues against those physicists who hold that modern physics, seems to be one of the two main questions rather than philosophy, can answer traditional that concern Sir Michael in his thought- metaphysical questions such as why there is provoking essay “Th e Place of Philosophy something rather than nothing. The claim is that in the European Culture.” He does not physics cannot solve metaphysical problems since metaphysical issues are in principle himself supply us with any defi nite answer, empirically underdetermined. The paper closes but suggests that philosophers in general with a critical discussion of the assumption of do not know much about the natural some cosmologists that the Universe was created sciences, and therefore do not dare to speak out of nothing: In contrast to this misleading up against the natural scientists (and those assumption, it is proposed that the Universe has a necessary existence and that the present epoch who do are not interested in the same kind after the Big Bang is a contingent realization of of problems as the scientists.) Moreover, the Universe. because of the great success of the natural sciences scientists are often arrogant by Keywords: : Dummett, physics, philosophy, meta- assuming that the only knowledge we physics, underdetermination, cosmology can have is the knowledge they are able to provide.
    [Show full text]
  • Luis-Alberto CORDERO-LECCA)
    Luis-Alberto CORDERO-LECCA) Full Professor of Philosophy and History, City University of New York at the CUNY Graduate Center and Queens College CUNY. Director of Graduate Studies, Philosophy Department, Queens College, CUNY. Numerary Member of the Academie Internationale de Philosophie des Sciences and of the Institute de Hautes Sciences Theoriques, Brussels. Doctor, Honoris Causa, Universdad Nacional Mayor de San Marcos; Doctor Honoris Causa, Universidad Peruana Ricardo Palma, Lima; Doctor Honoris Causa, Universidad, Universidad Nacional del Altiplano, Puno, Peru; Doctor Honoris Causa, Universidad Nacional Hermilio Valdizán, Huánuco. Honorary Professor, Universidad Peruana Cayetano Heredia, Lima, Peru. Former Chairman of the Philosophy Panel of the Research Foundation, CUNY. Former Chairman of the Columbia University Seminar on the History & Philosophy of Science. Former University Director of the Library, Publications and Museums of Cayetano Heredia University (Lima-Peru). Former Chairman of the Department of Physics & Mathematics and Honorary Director of the Program for Scientific Thought, Universidad Peruana Cayetano Heredia, Lima, Peru. Fields: Philosophy of science and the philosophical history of science; scientific realism, foundations of physics, contemporary naturalism. ALBERTO CORDERO (Luis-Alberto Cordero-Lecca) Curriculum Vitae, January, 2021) FIELDS: Philosophy of science and the philosophical history of science; scientific realism, foundations of physics, contemporary naturalism. NATIONALITY: Peruvian HIGHER EDUCATION
    [Show full text]
  • Science and Reality
    Science and reality Jan Faye Department of Media, Cognition and Communication, University of Copenhagen Since the heyday of logical positivism, the dominant view in philosophy of science has been Realism. But over the last two or three decades its prominence seems to decline. No one wants to return to the excesses of logical positivism, but as the dust after the battle settled, it became more and more clear that not everything the defeated part stood for was without merit. And, as we shall see, Realism has its excesses and problems too. Hardcore instrumentalists believed that the scientific theories are mere tools for predictions and calculations and that they contain no content telling us how the world really is, being conceptual tools that are neither true nor false. Theories help us to organize empirical data in virtue of the claim of theoretical entities, but theoretical entities are, and always will be, fictitious mental constructions because their alleged existence would transcend anything that could be established by sense experience. Realism grows out of the practical and observational success of science it- self. Instrumentalism, in contrast, is generated by a philosophical desire to strip metaphysics of any veil of legitimacy and to dress science in armour of epistemic warrant. As long as astronomy, physics, chemistry and biology dealt mainly with macroscopic objects which could be observed, as was the case to the end of 19th century, the acceptance of the instrumentalist view had no far-reaching implica- tions, neither with respect to the number of theoretical entities explained away, nor with respect to possible technological consequences of a belief in these enti- ties.
    [Show full text]
  • The Great Math Mystery Mario Livio (1950 - ) Astrophysicist and Writer Astrofísico Y Escritor Astrophysicien Et Écrivain Space Telescope Science Institute
    “How is it possible that mathematics, a product of human thought that is independent of experience, fits so excellently the objects of physical reality?” “¿Cómo es posible que la matemática, un producto del pensamiento humano independiente de la experiencia, se adapte tan admirablemente a los objetos de la realidad?”1 Albert Einstein (1879-1955) “Intelligent people would never say, ‘I don’t care about art, or music. But it is totally okay to say, ‘I hate math.’” The Great Math Mystery Mario Livio (1950 - ) Astrophysicist and writer Astrofísico y escritor Astrophysicien et écrivain Space Telescope Science Institute LIVIO, Mario, “The Great Math Mystery”. This is a Nova Production for WGBF Boston. © 2015 WGBF Educational Foundation. All rights reserved. This program was produced by WGBF, which is solely responsible for its content. Cf.: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=pPUTrIgdCZI 1 JAMMER, Max, Einstein and Religion, Princeton University Press, 1921, p. 124. The Great Math Mystery Documentary New 2015 HD http://docuwiki.net/index.php?title=T... The Great Math Mystery Documentary New 2015 HD NOVA leads viewers on a mathematical mystery tour –a provocative exploration of math’s astonishing power across the centuries. We discover math’s signature in the swirl of a nautilus shell, the whirlpool of a galaxy, and the spiral in the center of a sunflower. Math was essential to everything from the first wireless radio transmissions to the successful landing of rovers on Mars. But where does math get its power? Astrophysicist and writer Mario Livio, along with a colorful cast of mathematicians, physicists, and engineers, follow math from Pythagoras to Einstein and beyond, all leading to the ultimate riddle: Is math an invention or a discovery? Humankind’s clever trick or the language of the universe? Whether we think we’re good with numbers or not, we all use math in our daily lives.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 514 – from Physics to Metaphysics
    PHI 514 – From Physics to Metaphysics Weeks 4–6, 10–12: Indeterminacy in Quantum Mechanics (Halvorson) 1. Logic and probability in classical physics [Bub97, pp. 13–22], [Var85, Chap. 1] 2. The uncertainty relations and their interpretation [UH01], [Jam74, Chap. 3]. (a) Some thought experiments (b) The epistemic interpretation. Heisenberg’s disturbance interpre- tation [Hei30, pp. 13-20]. (c) The statistical interpretation (Popper) [Pop82, pp. 52-64, 144ff.], [Jam74, pp. 448–453] (d) The conceptual interpretation (Bohr); complementarity 3. From uncertainty to indeterminacy: Operationlism, positivist criteria of meaning (a) Operationalist definitions of concepts [Bri27] (b) Historical fact: Bohr doesn’t infer indeterminacy from uncer- tainty [Gr¨u57], [Mur87, pp. 139–154], [How00]. 4. Logic and probability in quantum mechanics Resources: Clifton’s notes [Cli96] are thorough and self-contained. There are shorter introductions in [Ism00], [Alb92, pp. 17–60], [Red89, pp. 5–32, 170–178], and [Bub97, pp. 23–39, 246–274]. For a more in- depth treatment, see [Hug89, Chaps. 1–5] or [van92, pp. 139–237]. 5. Against the disturbance interpretation (a) (For a technical critique – making use of details of the gamma- ray microscope – see [BR81]. I do not plan to discuss this in the seminar.) (b) The “no hidden variables” theorems of von Neumann and Kochen- Specker [Red89], [Hea79] (c) The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument 6. Contextual hidden variables; de-occamization [Shi93a] 1 7. Which quantities are real? (a) Eigenstate-Eigenvalue Link (This is what Fine [Fin87] calls the “rule of silence” and “rule of law.”); Collapse of the Wavefunction (b) Booleanism (c) The problem of the non-maximal observable (d) Definability and the Bub-Clifton theorem [BC96] 8.
    [Show full text]
  • Bohr's Relational Holism and the Classical-Quantum Interaction1
    1 Bohr’s Relational Holism and the classical-quantum Interaction1 Mauro Dorato Department of Philosophy Communication and Media Studies University of Rome “Roma Tre”, Via Ostiense 234, 00144, Rome, Italy [email protected] 1 Introduction: a conflict in Bohr’s philosophy? Bohr’s philosophy of quantum mechanics has often been charged for what is allegedly one of its major shortcomings, namely the advocacy of an unambiguous classical/quantum distinction (let me refer to this view with the label the distinction thesis). As is well known, such a distinction is needed to defend Bohr’s view that any communicable measurement outcome must presuppose a classically describable instrument, with respect to which any reference to the quantum of action can be neglected (Bohr 1958, 4). Critics have then often insisted on the fact that the distinction in question is hopelessly vague (Bell 1987, 29) or at least strongly contextual (Ghirardi 2004), so that Bohr’s interpretation of quantum mechanics suffers from the same vagueness and adhoc-ness. The resulting problem is, allegedly, a renunciation to describe the dynamical interaction between system and apparatus in a physically precise, theoretically based and non-contextual way, and therefore to offer a much-needed solution to the measurement problem. In my paper I will present and critically discuss the main strategies that Bohr used and could have used to defend from this charge his interpretation of quantum mechanics. In particular, in the first part I will reassess the main arguments that Bohr used to advocate the 1 Thanks to Henry Folse and Jan Faye for their attentive reading of a previous draft of the paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant, Gödel and Relativity1
    1 Kant, Gödel and Relativity1 Mauro Dorato Dept. of Philosophy Università di Roma Tre Via Ostiense 234 00146, Rome, Italy tel. +39-06-54577523; fax +39-06-54577540 e-mail: [email protected] Forthcoming in P. Gardenfors, K. Kijania-Placek and J. Wolenski (eds.), Proceedings of the invited papers for the 11th International Congress of the Logic Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Synthese Library, Kluwer, Dordrecht, 2002, pp.329-346. Abstract Since the onset of logical positivism, the general wisdom of the philosophy of science has it that the kantian philosophy of (space and) time has been superseded by the theory of relativity, in the same sense in which the latter has replaced Newton’s theory of absolute space and time. On the wake of Cassirer and Gödel, in this paper I raise doubts on this commonplace. I first suggest some conditions that are necessary to defend the ideality of time in the sense of Kant, and I then bring to bear some contemporary physical theories on such conditions. 1 What is “the problem of time”? Time is absolutely central in our inner experience, but at least since the foundation of modern physics, it also plays an important role in the description of the outer world. To the extent that there is a physical and a mental time, one can safely surmise that the problem of trying to establish whether and how they are related is one of the most fundamental issues in the philosophy of time. Are physical and mental time in conflict, or we can regard the former as some sort of appropriate extension to the outer world of the main features of the latter? These questions, important as they are, already presuppose, however, that there are two sides of the problem, namely that there is, at a fundamental level of description, a physical time.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Science: a Philosophical Introduction to the Unity of Science
    RETHINKING SCIENCE Science and humanity are usually seen as very different: the sciences of nature aim at explanations whereas the sciences of man seek meaning and understanding. This book shows how these contrasting descriptions fail to fit into a modem philosophical account of the sciences and the arts. Presenting some of the major ideas within the philosophy of science on facts, explanation, interpretation, methods, laws, and theories, Jan Faye compares various approaches, including his own. Arguing that the sciences of nature and the sciences of man share a common practice of acquiring knowledge, this book offers a unique introduction to key aspects in the philosophy of science. ASHGATE NEW CRITICAL THINKING IN PHILOSOPHY The Ashgate New Critical Thinking in Philosophy series aims to bring high quality research monograph publishing back into focus for authors, the international library market, and student, academic and research readers. Headed by an international editorial advisory board of acclaimed scholars from across the philosophical spectrum, this new monograph series presents cutting-edge research from established as well as exciting new authors in the field; spans the breadth of philosophy and related disciplinary and interdisciplinary perspectives; and takes contemporary philosophical research into new directions and debate. Series Editorial Board: Professor David Cooper, University of Durham, UK Professor Peter Lipton, University of Cambridge, UK Professor Sean Sayers, University of Kent at Canterbury, UK Dr Simon Critchley,
    [Show full text]
  • Causality, Contiguity, and Construction
    __________________________________ Papers ________________________________ Causality, Contiguity, and Construction Jan Faye Abstract: The paper discusses the regularity account of causation but finds it insufficient as a complete account of our notion of causality. The attractiveness of the regularity account is its attempt to under- stand causation in terms of empirically accessible features of the world. However, this account does not match our intuition that singu- lar causality is prior in normal epistemic situations and that there is more to causation than mere succession. Apart from succession and regularity, the concept of causality also contains a modal feature which allows us to engage in counterfactual discourses about singular causal events and to claim that a particular cause is both sufficient and neces- sary for its effect in the circumstances. However, we may directly ob- serve singular causes, but the modal element is not something we can possibly observe. Rather, this element is something we add to our per- ception of succession. Thus, the paper suggests that the modal feature of causality is a mental construction which was originally formed by our knowledge of certain structural features of similar events in other situations. It stems not from what we actually observe but from what we have observed or may observe under different but relevant cir- cumstances. So the concept of causation has partly an empirical con- tent and partly a constructed one. Keywords: causation, the regularity account, causal modality. The concept of causality is commonly regarded as essential for understanding the difference between accidental and non-accidental happenings and the relation between the actual and the possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Niels Bohr and Contemporary Philosophy Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
    NIELS BOHR AND CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY BOSTON STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Editor ROBERT S. COHEN, Boston University Editorial Advisory Board THOMAS F. GLICK, Boston University ADOLF GRUNBAUM, University ofPittsburgh SAHOTRA SARKAR, Dibner Institute M.l. T. SYLVAN S. SCHWEBER, Brandeis University JOHN J. STACHEL, Boston University MARX W. WARTOFSKY, Baruch College of the City University ofNew York VOLUME 153 NIELS BOHR AND CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY Edited by JAN FAYE Carlsberg Foundation, Copenhagen , Denmark and HENRY J. FOLSE Department ofPhilosophy, Loyola University, New Orleans, U. S. A. ...,~ Springer-Science+Business Media, B.Y. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Niels Bohr and contemporary phIlosophy / edited by Jan Faye and Henry J. Folse. p. cm . -- (Boston studIes in the phi losophy of scIence; v. 153) Includes bIblIographIcal references and index. 1. Physlcs--Phl10sophy. 2 . PhIlosophy. Modern. I . Faye. Jan . II. Folse. Henry J .• 1945- III. Series. [DNLM : 1. Bohr. Niels Henrik DaVid. 1885-1962--Views on phIlosophy.] aC16.B65N493 1993 530' .01--dc20 DLC for Library of Congress 93-24825 ISBN 978-90-481-4299-6 ISBN 978-94-015-8106-6 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-8106-6 Printed on acid-free paper All Rights Reserved © 1994 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1994. Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover 1st edition 1994 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechancial, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner.
    [Show full text]
  • Bohr Meets Rovelli: a Dispositionalist Account of the Quantum Limits of Knowledge
    Bohr meets Rovelli: a dispositionalist account of the quantum limits of knowledge Mauro Dorato Department of Philosophy, Communication and Media Studies Università degli Studi Roma Tre, Via Ostiense 234, 00146, Rome, Italy 1) Introduction: ignoramus and ignorabimus?1 In the last couple of centuries, the history of physics has at times been sparkled by two opposite attitudes, which to simplify we could denote a radically pessimistic and an overoptimistic one. As a famous representative of the former first camp, we find the German physiologist Emile Du Bois- Reymond, who in a famous speech held in 1880 at the Berlin Academy of science claimed that there were seven world enigmas (Die Sieben Welträtzel) that neither science nor philosophy could ever solve. Among these mysteries, he listed the nature of matter and force, the origin of life, the origin of intelligent thought and the question of free will. As a representative of the overoptimistic camp, we can enlist Lord Kelvin when, a couple of decades later (April 27, 1900) gave a speech at the Royal Institute entitled "Nineteenth-Century Clouds over the Dynamical Theory of Heat and Light”, in which he defended the view that physical knowledge was complete, so that the only future task for physicists was the “minor” one of providing more precise experimental measures of already known quantities. However, more realistically, deeply cognizant as he was of contemporary physical theories, mentioned “two clouds” - that as we now know, will lead to a thunderstorm! - namely the failure of Michelson and Morley’s experiment and the ultraviolet catastrophe (clouds that have been swept away thanks to the special theory of relativity and to quantum mechanics respectively).
    [Show full text]
  • Is Time an Abstract Entity?
    Is Time an Abstract Entity? Jan Faye, Copenhagen Introduction Time is a shadowy entity. On the one hand, it appears elusive, intangi- ble, and invisible. What we see is not time itself but changes of things and thoughts. In its proper form time seems to be given to us in the immediate experience as things and thoughts undergoing change prior to any concep- tual understanding. Th us immediate experience and the temporal conscious- ness of the world have profound implications for how we reach a grasp of time. Some philosophers therefore think that the actuality of the present is a fundamental property of any change and see this feature as a manifesta- tion of temporal becoming from the past to the future. On the other hand, modern physics takes the combination of space and time to be a real entity which may even have an infl uence on the distribution of energy and matter. Th is is why others maintain that the study of physics can give us a complete and correct answer concerning the nature of time. It is in this perspective that I shall suggest that time is not a concrete but an abstract particular. If we apply all the common criteria of abstractness, it turns out that time is able to meet each and every one of them. I think this is because our concept of time is a result of an abstraction from our experience of concrete, physical things undergoing change. We need such a concept in order to be able to name and measure such things and events.
    [Show full text]