Why Should Wsed Be Afraid of Kitsch? -1Lwfg4o

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Why Should Wsed Be Afraid of Kitsch? -1Lwfg4o Kitsch Harries 1 Why Should We Be Afraid of Kitsch? English original of “Waarom moeten we bang zijn voor kitsch,” transl. Jan Willem Reimtsma, Nexus, 2007, no. 47, pp. 127-147. The essay developed my contribution to the symposium “A Kitsch Culture”? (with Sidney Blumenthal, Hendrik Hertzberg, Menno Meyjes. Jack Miles, Jonathan Taplin), part of the Nexus Conference “New Notes Towards the Definition of European Culture. The Classics, Art and Kitsch,” Amsterdam, November 11, 2006. 1. Nostalgia, Kitsch, and Romanticism These reflections address questions raised by the title of the most recent Nexus Conference: “New Notes Towards the Definition of European Culture. The Classics, Art and Kitsch.” Its keynote was sounded, in the brochure I was sent, by the expression Kultur-Herbst-Gefühl, with reference to a letter Nietzsche wrote on June 21, 1871 to his friend Carl von Gersdorff, in which he responded to a report of arson said to have destroyed the Louvre and its collections. Nietzsche took it as a metaphor of a battle against culture waged by our modern civilization, leaving him for several days “entirely annihilated and dissolved in tears and doubts.” As it turned out, the report was mistaken: it was the Tuileries that went up in flames, part of the unrest that culminated in the downfall of the Paris Commune. And it was not in that letter that Nietzsche used this pathos-laden expression, so heavy with cultural nostalgia, to describe his mood, but in the first of a set of “Memorabilia,” a few words jotted down in the spring of 1878, after he had finished Human, All Too Human and was looking back, with much more questioning eyes, at something that now lay behind him: “Autumn — pain — stubble — rose- campions [Pechnelken — literally “pitch-carnations”] asters. Very similar, when the Louvre was supposed to have burned — Cultur-Herbstgefühl. Never a deeper pain.”1 In keeping with the young Nietzsche’s conviction that the civilization, of which he too was part, shared responsibility for the destruction of the supposedly lost masterpieces, the first panel of this Nexus conference thus addressed the question: why 1 Friedrich Nietzsche, Nachgelassene Fragmente, 28 = N II 6. Frühling-Sommer 1878, no. 1, in Kritische Studienausgabe, ed. G. Colli und M. Montinari (DDTV, de Gruyter: München/ Berlin/New York, 1980), vol. 8. p. 504. Kitsch Harries 2 have we abandoned the classics? But have we in fact abandoned the classics? Or were the classics simply left behind by the progress of our post-technological and increasingly global culture? And who are “we”? A small, largely self-anointed cultural elite, guardians of what remains of that culture that once provided something like a spiritual home? Does this “we” include the ungebildeten, i.e. uneducated masses? And finally, just what lets us call a work a classic? Does the very conception of a classic not presuppose a faith in Western culture as the custodian of enduring values, enshrined in certain key works, that can no longer be presupposed? The second panel continued the discussion by considering the question: “Why Art, Music, and Poetry?” That these should continue to play a decisive part in shaping our understanding of what we take to matter is by no means obvious. Does this question not also betray nostalgia for something that today no longer seems to possess more than a peripheral significance? And nostalgia was suggested once more by the question that was the title of the final session: “A Kitsch Culture”? That question does suggest that, at least in some sense, art remains significant: does not “kitsch” name first of all a certain art? To be sure, the label suggests that a culture, whose heart and soul is, to cite George Steiner, kitsch, can only be a simulacrum of true culture. As Clement Greenberg once put it, defending abstraction as a last bastion of authenticity: “Kitsch, using for raw material the debased and academicized simulacra of genuine culture, welcomes and cultivates this insensibility. It is the source of its profits. Kitsch is mechanical and operates by formulas. Kitsch is vicarious experience and faked sensations. Kitsch changes according to style, but remains always the same. Kitsch is the epitome of all that is spurious in the life of our times. Kitsch pretends to demand nothing of its customers except their money, not even their time.”2 The suggestion is that kitsch, born of and answering to a loss of culture that Greenberg links to the industrial revolution and to the capitalism it made possible, while it may pretend to demand nothing of us except our money, ends up drowning us in inauthenticity. 2 Clement Greenberg, “Avant-Garde and Kitsch,” Art and Culture. Crititical Essays (Boston: Beacon, 1961), p. 10. Kitsch Harries 3 But does such elitist pathos not attribute to kitsch a sinister significance that it does not generally possess? What threat do garden gnomes and Bambi pose? Has most entertainment not always been kitsch? Who today is still afraid of kitsch? We may deplore that there is not more support for what we think really deserves to be called art, but is most kitsch, like most art, not quite harmless? Suppose ours is indeed a kitsch culture, must this be criticized? The negative connotations of the “kitsch” label may make the answer seem self- evident: from its very beginning in the elitist art-world of late 19th century Munich “kitsch” has been used as a term to condemn, initially a certain kind of cheap, too easily produced art, relying on formulas and mechanical reproduction, a mere shadow of authentic, genuine art. But what was condemned was increasingly not just a certain kind of inferior art, but the state of mind, the ethos that produced and welcomed such art: the kitsch-personality that to find Ersatz for lacking values wants to be moved and edified without having to invest too much emotional capital in what it consumes and without really having to change. Both the producer and consumer of kitsch are here condemned, not just for having bad taste, but for having a taste that suggests something like moral failure: the consumer of kitsch wants to be deceived, refusing to open his eyes to reality as it really is and to the demands it places on us, escaping from that reality to clichéd images of some happier, better world, perhaps of the good old world of the fathers, a world that selfishness and greed are supposed to have destroyed. The producer of kitsch exploits such willingness to collude with the deception and, like the old magician of Nietzsche’s Zarathustra, “knowingly, willingly lies,” substituting simulacra for what should be real and genuine. Such an understanding of “kitsch” recalls what Nietzsche had to say about romanticism: “too much energy is being wasted on all sorts of resurrections of what has died. Perhaps the whole romantic movement is best understood from this point of view.”3 Nietzsche might very well have agreed with Roger Scruton that “The romantic artist is attempting to invest human life with a religious aura, to rewrite those purely 3 Friedrich Nietzsche, Morgenröte, 159. Kitsch Harries 4 human experiences of conflict and passion as though they originated in the divine.”4 But the mature Nietzsche would have us question the way Scruton opposes the romantic artist to the creator of kitsch; he would have underscored the “as though”: is “the vision of a higher life” that romanticism is said by Scruton to sustain “in the midst of bourgeois mediocrity” supported by more than nostalgia for something already overtaken by the progress of reason and the world is has shaped? Scruton calls romantic art “a heroic attempt to re-enchant the world: to look on human beings as though they had the significance and the dignity of angels.” Once again the “as though” deserves special attention. As Kierkegaard taught, we must beware of allowing the aesthetic subjunctive to obscure the indicative of reality.5 Do romantic attempts to re-enchant a disenchanted world not also lead to kitsch, a far more demanding form of kitsch perhaps, but because of its pretensions not as harmless as some plastic Jesus dangling from a dashboard or an entertaining Hollywood movie of the fifties? The conjunction of kitsch, nostalgia, and romanticism invites the question: do those who invoke the culture of the past to condemn our post-culture as a kitsch culture not cling to something that belongs into a museum precisely because it no longer possesses genuine life? Are they not romantics in Nietzsche’s sense? By 1878 Nietzsche, as we know, had come to condemn not only Wagner, but his own Birth of Tragedy, despite all its attacks on Alexandrianism, appropriated by Greenberg in his critique of kitsch, as itself kitsch — although that word was not yet available to him — pretentious kitsch, to be sure, kitsch for a self-selected, self-validating elite, but kitsch nonetheless? Human beings have long opposed their versions of some past golden age to the decadent present. That the distinctive ugliness of our disenchanted modern world should breed nostalgia for some bygone and supposedly more authentic, more moral, more beautiful world is only to be expected. If we can call such nostalgia the mother of kitsch, 4 Roger Scruton, “Kitsch and the Modern Predicament,” City Journal, Winter 1999, http://www.google.com/search?q=cache:suDGSDR4q2kJ:www.city- journal.org/html/9_1_urbanities_kitsch_and_the.html+%2B%22Roger+Scruton%22+%2 Bkitsch&hl=en&gl=us&ct=clnk&cd=1 5 See Karsten Harries, "Transformations of the Subjunctive," Thought, vol. 55, no. 218, 1980, pp. 283-294. Kitsch Harries 5 its father could perhaps be said to be the industrial revolution and the capitalism it made possible.
Recommended publications
  • As in Milan Kundera's the Unbearable Lightness of Being
    Journal of Xi'an University of Architecture & Technology ISSN No : 1006-7930 Postmodernism and the Concept of Kitsch- As in Milan Kundera’s The Unbearable Lightness of Being Dr.Shanthichitra Associate Professor & Head, Dept. of English, College of Science and Humanities SRMIST, Chennai, India Abstract: The concept of Kitsch is one of the difficult concepts which has been so easily handles by Milan Kundera in his incredible work of art – The Unbearable Lightness of Being. Culturally accepted words and situations vs. the words which are labeled as grotesque points out that peculiar point which deviates the ordinary to sublimity. This paper studies that ordinary which is ignored in culture through Milan Kundera’s The Unbearable Lightness of Being. Keywords: Kitsch, Postmodernism, Phenomenology, Milan Kundera, Ideologies and Culture. When I came across the concept of Taipei modern Toilet diner, I was reminded of Milan Kundera’s Kitsch…This Modern Toilet diner is one of chain of themed eateries in Taiwan appealing to largely the youngsters of the city. This diner has greater relevance to the modern culture, culture in which youngsters call each other by bad words out of love…they have overcome all the grotesques!? Are they above all the human hurts?! Or is it an effort to deviate from kitsch?! Milan Kundera in his The Unbearable Lightness of Being talks about the concept of Kitsch. Kitsch is a German word that’s been adopted by a number of other languages, including English. It refers primarily to art that is overly sentimental or melodramatic, and so refers to aesthetics. What’s interesting is the way Kundera uses the concept in his novel, not to talk about art, but to talk about political ideology and about life.
    [Show full text]
  • Walter Benjamin and Kitsch Politics in the Phantasmagorical Age by Ayşegül Ergül a Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of Gradua
    Walter Benjamin and Kitsch Politics in the Phantasmagorical Age by Ayşegül Ergül A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Affairs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario © 2016, Ayşegül Ergül Abstract In this dissertation I explore the relationship between politics, aesthetics, culture and technology by (re)thinking and (re)conceptualizing the concept of kitsch as a theoretical construct in order to investigate the dream-worlds of Europe which sprang at the intersection of liberalism, social democracy and capitalism. I argue that the unexplored potentialities of kitsch, as a concept, reside in the analysis of the dream-worlds, which have been occupying the social and political imaginaries of Western individuals, communities and institutions since the disenchantment of the world. My methodological approach is built on Benjamin’s notion of historical materialism. Thus, I engage with the historical object(s) (e.g., arcades, fashion, technological reproductions etc.) not as “object(s) of experience” but as a “participant(s) in historical experience” (Caygill 2004, 90). Challenging the progressive notion of history, I argue that within the objective impenetrability of commodity fetishism a “sur-real” world of fetishized images – that is, kitsch – emerges, alienated from the individual and the collective, yet constituting and shaping them. By mapping out the implications of this “sur-real” world on “the political,” the collective (un)conscious and action, I conclude that alternative politics could arise from the unsettling interpretations of the reified and symbolic expressions of this same “sur-real” world, paving a path for new political imaginaries.
    [Show full text]
  • Beautiful and Sublime Kitsch: Framing the Prologue of Lars Von Trier's
    Beautiful and Sublime Kitsch: Framing the Prologue of Lars von Trier’s Melancholia as Avant-Garde Video Art Aleksandr Andreas Wansbrough University of Sydney Lars von Trier’s film Melancholia (2011) begins with a memorable and enigmatic prologue.1 Distinct from the film’s diegesis and played before the title credits, the prologue seems out of sync with the rest of the film’s trajectory, and even indicates the narrative’s key features before the story commences. Yet, while Melancholia’s narrative is representationally presented in this prologue, the film’s scenes are allegorical rather than literal; they possess a premonitory, dreamlike quality, which is enhanced by slow motion. For the viewer, these slow-motion effects engender a kind of hypnosis, a feeling that is itself enriched by the film’s imagery, which recalls the imagery, poetry and paintings of German romanticism. However, the prologue also evokes a precarious ambivalence concerning the film’s aesthetic features. The power of visual images to evoke both pleasure and disdain has long been documented within the sensual and violent — and Philament 22: Precarity philamentjournal.com 87 88 Philament 22: Precarity indeed the carnal — realms.2 However, many of Melancholia’s viewers may also find the film’s grandiose imagery lacking in aesthetic cred- ibility, and the digital perfection attained by the film to be uncom- fortable or disaffecting. The prologue induces a range of experiences with imagery that is both sublime and beautiful, but also kitsch. By reading the prologue to Melancholia as a work of video art, one can see the how the film’s concerns cross over with those of avant-garde video and digital installations, as well as how it moves beyond these concerns.
    [Show full text]
  • Vaughn Whitney Garland Final Paper Adorno and Greenberg 1933 to 1939
    Adorno and Greenberg, 1933 to 1939 By Vaughn Whitney Garland Decenber 13, 2010 Modernism & the Dialectic Dr. Victoria Scott 2 “‘When you spend Saturday night in a illegal dance hall, there is no energy left for Sunday-morning mass.’”1 In the debates about aesthetics, culture, music and visual arts in postwar American Modernism, the names Clement Greenberg and Theodor W. Adorno appear frequently. Greenberg and Adorno championed a high modernist aesthetic that connected the avant- garde and the cultured elite. The simultaneous emergence of popular culture and new aesthetic philosophies, in terms of a national, social, and cultural identity, brought Adorno and Greenberg’s concepts to life. Despite what is typically thought about the origins of the arguments regarding avant-garde and kitsch argument in the art world and its theoretical reliance on Greenberg as the primary and original source, it was Adorno, not Greenberg, who began the discussion about the roles and responsibilities of the avant- garde. While the ideas put forward by both Greenberg in his essay “Avant-garde and Kitsch” and Adorno’s work “On Jazz” are the impetus for many of the arguments made regarding the role of the avant-garde, I will suggest that the modernist discourse concerning popular culture and its relationship to the avant-garde began instead with an article published by Theodor Adorno in 1936. Since the publication of “Avant-garde and Kitsch,” the aesthetic discourse in the United States has frequently focused on Greenberg. However, Adorno’s article “On Jazz,” which was published earlier, with its critique on the bourgeois and proletariat music jazz, may have actually been the foundation of modernist theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Literary Theory and Intellectual Kitsch
    Literary Theory and Intellectual Kitsch Denis Dutton That postmodernism is a general cultural mood and a style in art, architecture, and literature is uncontroversial. But does post­ modernism present a coherent intellectual doctrine or theory of politics, art, or life? In the discussion which follows, I will concentrate on two aspects of the intellectual pretensions of postmodernism. First, I examine the postmodernist claim to justify the idea that the postmodern world is characterized by a general indeterminacy of meaning. Next I will look at aspects of the postmodernist contention that the present age has witnessed the decline of individuality. If there is an intellectual core to posunodernism, it will be found in French-derived poststructuralist thought. At the centre of poststTucturalism is the idea that the Enlightenment has run its course, that the seventeenth century's grand narratives, its ambitions to provide universal keys to reality, have failed. Such postmodem talk of the end of the Enlightenment is premature. Of course, there is no question that many of the grand narratives which captivated the imaginations of our forebears have indeed collapsed. The seventeenth-century idea that the study of matter in motion would eventually allow us to predict not only the motions of the planets, but even human behaviour is dead-as dead as the idea that the will of God dramatized by the passion and resurrection of Jesus could explain all of human history. Marxism, the grand narrative which gave shape to the intellectual aspirations of youth of many French poststructuralliterary theorists, has also fallen into its own decline, at least as an all-encompassing theoretical scheme.
    [Show full text]
  • Theodor W. Adorno's Struggle with the Concept
    BETWEEN MODERN AND POSTMODERN WORLDS: THEODOR W. ADORNO’S STRUGGLE WITH THE CONCEPT OF MUSICAL KITSCH Molly L. Barnes A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in the Department of Music. Chapel Hill 2012 Approved by: Advisor: Felix Wörner Reader: Tim Carter Reader: Jon Finson © 2012 Molly L. Barnes ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii ABSTRACT MOLLY L. BARNES: Between Modern and Postmodern Worlds: Theodor W. Adorno’s Struggle with the Concept of Musical Kitsch (Under the direction of Felix Wörner) The concept of “kitsch” remains a perennial concern for philosophers of aesthetics. Many distinguished writers have contributed to the literature on kitsch, yet the valuable work of the musicologist, sociologist, and philosopher Theodor Adorno (1903-1969) has been largely overlooked. Adorno nurtured an abiding interest in the topic of musical kitsch in particular, but was profoundly troubled by its implications for the cultural edification and psychological health of modern society. His writings also indicate that his ambivalence regarding kitsch became more acute with time. Through a close study of four texts by Adorno, including his analyses of specific musical works, I propose that Adorno’s increasingly conflicted attitude toward musical kitsch reflects growing tensions between modernist and postmodernist cultural perspectives in the mid-twentieth century, tensions that have persisted strongly into the twenty-first century. Indeed, Adorno’s thoughts regarding kitsch may help us understand musical aesthetics in his era as well as our own. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I have many people to thank for their help in bringing this thesis to completion.
    [Show full text]
  • KITSCH in the PROSE WORKS of THEODOR STORM By
    KITSCH IN THE PROSE WORKS OF THEODOR STORM by RACHEL CARNABY, B.A. Thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Germanic Studies University of Sheffield. March 1985 ABSTRACT RACHEL CARNABY KITSCH IN THE, PROSE WORKS OF THEODOR STORM. The twofold purpose of this study is to clarify, on the one hand, the question of literary evaluation in general and of kitsch in particular, and, on the other, to analyse the prose works of Theodor Storm in the light of the theories of literary evaluation thus established. It therefore follows that the investigation falls into two main sections. The first is in essence theoretical. It consists of seven chapters, in which are examined the terminology, etymology and history of literary evaluation; the many different approaches to tackling and understanding the problem of kitsch (pedagogic, socio—economic, political, religious, moral, philosophical etc.); kitsch in its relationship to art; kitsch in literature and elsewhere (kitsch of both style and philosophy); kitsch and the consumer, especially the female consumer; kitswh's causes and functions under a variety of political and socipa regimeA4.and, lastly, the possible dangers of kitsch and the remedies suggested to help counteract it. The second section commences with a survey of prominent trends in Storm research old and new, followed by an exploration of Storm's awareness of and relationship to his reading public and to his publishers, and the effect on his work of the demands of family finances. Three chapters are devoted specifically to Storm's wide—ranging techniques for appealing to his reading public, and four to one of the most important aspects of his work in relation to kitsch, the women figures and love and marriage in the 'Novellen'.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato Or Schopenhauer?
    I Plato or Schopenhauer? All beautiful things, the Greek philosopher Plotinus wrote in the third century a.d., produce “awe and a shock of delight, passionate longing, love and a shudder of rapture.” All beautiful things: natural objects and works of art, bodies and souls, ways of life, knowledge, virtue, and much else besides. Our time, by contrast, has confined such feel­ ings to everyday life. It has drawn a heavy curtain between them and the true pleasures of art, which ordinary people, as Ortega y Gasset charged in 1925, are incapable of experiencing: “To the majority of people aesthetic pleasure means a state of mind which is essentially indistinguishable from their ordinary behavior. As they have never practiced any other attitude but the practical one in which a man’s feelings are aroused and he is emotionally involved, a work that does not invite sentimental intervention leaves them without a cue”; ordi­ nary people wallow in emotions not only different “from true artistic pleasure, but . incompatible with aesthetic enjoyment proper.” Philosophy, too, has abandoned Plotinus’s broad vision. Suspicious of passion, it limited itself to a kind of beauty to which desire seemed inappropriate—the beauty in great art and the wonders of nature, concentrated in museums and national parks. And so the beauty that mattered to philosophy, to criticism, and often to the arts themselves, if it mattered at all, was separated from the beauty that mattered to the rest of the world, to whom it seemed irrelevant and empty: the higher and more refined its pleasures, the less like pleasures they seemed.
    [Show full text]
  • A Fetish for Fugitive Aesthetics: Cinematic Kitsch and Visual Pleasure in the Tales of Hoffmann David Scott Diffrient
    A Fetish for Fugitive Aesthetics: Cinematic Kitsch and Visual Pleasure in The Tales of Hoffmann David Scott Diffrient “Your production of Tales of Hoffmann has proven that you can have everything. For the first time in my life I was treated to Grand Opera where the beauty, power and scope of the music was equally matched by the visual presentation.” — Extract from Cecil B. DeMille’s letter to Messrs. Powell and Pressburger (Powell 138) Under the collaborative pseudonym “The Archers,” British director Michael Powell and Hungarian-born screenwriter Emeric Pressburger gained fame throughout the 1940s and 1950s for a number of visually arresting films whose brazen romanticism might have seemed anachronistic to many wartime and postwar audiences. Over the course of a seventeen-year- long creative partnership, this celebrated duo concocted eccentrically stylized motion pictures that not only frustrated categorization, but also challenged taste-based distinctions between highbrow, middlebrow, and lowbrow forms of cultural production and consumption. From the vertiginous Himalayan fever-dream of Black Narcissus (1946) to the hallucinatory ballet of The Red Shoes (1948), the Archers’ color-drenched films blend the sacred and the secular, the sublime and the sometimes ridiculous. Indeed, their musicals, melodramas, and costume adventures are so mystically inflected, their emotional allegories so phantasmogorical at times, that the resulting tension between fantasy and reality, the rational and the irrational, is stretched to the point of absurdity and rendered in a style approximating kitsch. By critically interrogating what is undoubtedly the decorative, if not artistic, culmination of their career—the 1951 episodic opera film The Tales of Hoffmann—I seek to address some of the aesthetic and ideological implications of cinematic kitsch as seen through the overlapping lenses of queer theory, resistant spectatorship, and art history.
    [Show full text]
  • Bloch's 'Traces': the Philosophy of Kitsch
    Theodor Adorno Bloch’s ‘Traces’: the philosophy of Kitsch The title Traces1 mobilizes for the purposes of philosophical theory the primary experiences derived from reading Red Indian stories. A broken twig, a foot- print on the ground, speak volumes to the eagle eye of the child who speculates about them, instead of resting content with what anyone can see. There is something here, something hidden, in the midst of ordinary, unobtrusive normality: ‘There’s more here than meets the eye’ (p. 15). What it is, no-one knows, and Bloch, taking a leaf from the book of the gnostics, suggests that it may not be there at all yet, that it may be in the process of becoming. But il y a quelque chose qui cloche,2 and the more mysterious the source of the trace, the more persistent the feeling that something is really there. This is the point at which speculative thought seeks a foothold. As if in mockery of the dispassionate, scientific reflections of phenomenology, the speculative thinker sets out in search of the ineffable, feeling his way experimentally towards an interpretation. Indefatigably, the philosophical moth flutters against the pane of glass between itself and the light. The conundrums of what Bloch once called the shape of the 49 unformulatable question are made to crystallize out into whatever answers they may fleetingly suggest. His traces are survivals of the ineffable experience of childhood which once upon a time communi- cated everything. Many friends are quoted in the book. I would like to wager that they date from adolescence, Ludwigshafen cousins of Brecht’s cronies from Augsburg, George Pflanzelt and Müllereisert.
    [Show full text]
  • Problemi Di Gusto. Hume E Dorfles
    Testi Andrea Mecacci Problemi di gusto. Hume e Dorfles di Andrea Mecacci [email protected] The essay aims to highlight the links between Dorfles’ Le oscillazioni del gusto (The Oscillations of Taste) (1958 and 1970) and David Hume’s classic essay Of the Standard of Taste (1757). Taste becomes the core of aesthetic experience, making the relationship between subjectivity and shared values problematic, but necessary. Like Hume, Dorfles also conceives taste, despite its variety and variability, as a process of cultural exercising that finds its operative grammar in the balance between facility and novelty and in the dimension of delicacy. Keywords: Dorfles, Hume, gusto, kitsch Se si dovesse sintetizzare in un’unica parola la riflessione strettamente estetologica di Dorfles la parola da scegliere sarebbe senza alcun dubbio “gusto”. L’interrogazione di Dorfles sul gusto si situa in un momento ben preciso delle alterne vicende di questa categoria che aveva segnato il battesimo dell’estetica come disciplina autonoma. Da categoria centrale dell’estetica settecentesca, il gusto si era ritrovato nel secolo sucessivo vittima di una rimozione, nemmeno tanto problematica, da parte delle estetiche idealistiche e romantiche, per poi svolgere nel Novecento un ruolo ambiguo, di verifica delle disfunzioni estetiche della cultura di massa, segnando il passaggio da una dimensione affermativa del soggetto – come era stato tematizzato da Hume e Kant – a una condizione di mistificazione collettiva in cui il gusto si era mutato più che altro in cattivo gusto. L’indagine di Dorfles sul gusto si colloca esattamente in questa fase di ripresa ex negativo del gusto. Forzando l’analisi che Dorfles compie nel suo testo Le oscillazioni del gusto e negli studi sul kitsch, è possibile assistere a un implicito recupero della riflessione humiana sul gusto alla luce delle istanze che aveva sollevato la società di massa negli anni Cinquanta e Sessanta.
    [Show full text]
  • Art and Aesthetics After Adorno
    The Townsend Pa P e r s i n T h e h u m a n i T i e s No. 3 Art and Aesthetics After Adorno Jay M. Bernstein Claudia Brodsky Anthony J. Cascardi Thierry de Duve Aleš Erjavec Robert Kaufman Fred Rush Art and Aesthetics After Adorno The Townsend Pa P e r s i n T h e h u m a n i T i e s No. 3 Art and Aesthetics After Adorno J. M. Bernstein Claudia Brodsky Anthony J. Cascardi Thierry de Duve Aleš Erjavec Robert Kaufman Fred Rush Published by The Townsend Center for the Humanities University of California | Berkeley Distributed by University of California Press Berkeley, Los Angeles, London | 2010 Copyright ©2010 The Regents of the University of California ISBN 978-0-9823294-2-9 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Art and aesthetics after Adorno / J. M. Bernstein...[et al]. p. cm. — (The Townsend papers in the humanities ; no. 3) ISBN 978-0-9823294-2-9 1. Aesthetics, Modern—20th century 2. Aesthetics, Modern—21st century 3. Adorno, Theodor W., 1903–1969. Ästhetische Theorie. I. Bernstein, J. M. BH201.A78 2010 111’.850904—dc22 2010018448 Inquiries concerning proposals for the Townsend Papers in the Humanities from Berkeley faculty and Townsend Center affiliates should be addressed to The Townsend Papers, 220 Stephens Hall, UC Berkeley, Berkeley, CA 94720- 2340, or by email to [email protected]. Design and typesetting: Kajun Graphics Manufactured in the United States of America Credits and acknowledgements for quoted material appear on page 180–81.
    [Show full text]