Sidgwick on Moral Motivation 1872; PPE = Principles of Political Economy, Third Edition (London: Macmil- Volume 6, No

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sidgwick on Moral Motivation 1872; PPE = Principles of Political Economy, Third Edition (London: Macmil- Volume 6, No In the first chapter I spoke of actions that we judge to be right and what ought to be done as being “reasonable,” or “rational” … and I contrasted the motive to action supplied by the recognition of such reasonableness with “non-rational” desires and inclinations. This manner of speaking is employed by writers of different schools, and seems in accordance with the common view and language … . For we commonly think that wrong con- duct is essentially irrational, and can be shown to be so by argument; and though we do not conceive that it is by reason alone that men are influenced to act rightly, we still hold that appeals to the reason are an essential part of all moral persuasion … . On the other hand it is widely maintained that, as Hume says, “Reason, mean- ing the judgment of truth and falsehood, can never of it- Sidgwick on self be any motive to the Will”; and that the motive to action is in all cases some Non-rational Desire, including under this term the impulses to action given by present Moral Motivation pleasure and pain. It seems desirable to examine with some care the grounds of this contention before we pro- ceed any further (ME 23).1 So opens Methods I.III. Sidgwick holds that moral judgments are claims about what it is reasonable to do. In Methods I.I he Robert Shaver 1 “ME” refers to Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, seventh edition (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981). References to the first edition (London: Mac- millan, 1874) are abbreviated as “ME (1)” and to the second edition (London: Macmillan, 1877) as “ME (2).” Other abbreviations refer to the following works by Sidgwick: BB = “Bentham and Benthamism in Politics and Ethics,” in Miscellaneous Essays and Addresses (London: Macmillan, 1904); CE = “Can- ons of Evidence in Psychical Research,” Proceedings of the Society for Psychi- cal Research 6, 1889; DEP = The Development of European Polity, second edi- ton (London: Macmillan, 1913); E = “Eton,” Macmillan’s Magazine, February 1861; FT = “The Feeling-Tone of Desire and Aversion,” Mind n.s. 1, 1892; GE = “Green’s Ethics,” Mind 9, 1884; LE = Lectures on the Ethics of T. H. Green, Mr. Herbert Spencer, and J. Martineau (London: Macmillan, 1902); MS = “The Morality of Strife,” in Practical Ethics (New York: Oxford University Philosophers’ Imprint Press, 1998); OHE = Outlines of the History of Ethics, fourth edition (London: <www.philosophersimprint.org/006001> Macmillan, 1896); PD = “Pleasure and Desire,” Contemporary Review, April Sidgwick on Moral Motivation 1872; PPE = Principles of Political Economy, third edition (London: Macmil- Volume 6, No. 1 lan. 1901); RS = “Review of Leslie Stephen’s The Science of Ethics,” Mind 7, February 2006 1882; UA = “Unreasonable Action,” in Practical Ethics. © 2006 by Robert Shaver Robert Shaver is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Manitoba. Robert Shaver Sidgwick on Moral Motivation writes of “rational procedure,” “rational precepts,” the “end Sidgwick holds (i) and (ii), rejecting (iii) [on one reading of of reasonable human action,” and “reasonable conduct.” (iii)]. Hume, on Sidgwick’s and the received view, holds (ii) When we fail to do what we see to be right, we are acting on and (iii), rejecting (i). I shall sometimes make reference to “irrational springs of action” or “non-rational inclinations” the debate over Smith as a way to illuminate Sidgwick. (ME 1-6). He also holds that these judgments about what it Second, when I write of moral judgments’ motivating, I is reasonable to do can motivate. He must, then, respond to intend either of two possibilities: the agent takes the moral Hume’s argument that reason cannot motivate. Most of judgment to be backed by his all-things-considered judg- Methods I.III is this response. ment about what he has most reason to do, and so desires to I shall clarify Sidgwick’s claim that moral judgments are perform, and performs, the action enjoined by the moral judgments about what it is reasonable to do (I). I then give judgment; or the agent does not take the moral judgment to two interpretations of his view of moral motivation (II-III): be backed by his all-things-considered judgment, and so has insofar as one is rational, moral beliefs cause desires; or inso- merely a desire (or “some motivation”) to perform the ac- far as one is rational, one has a standing desire to act rightly, tion, which is defeated by desires backed by other reasons. and moral beliefs combine with this desire to motivate. Sidgwick does not hold that moral judgments need always These views differ from the accounts often given by anti- be the winning motivation, even in rational agents. Humeans that rely on entities such as “besires”—accounts which there is no need to adopt (IV). I then give Sidgwick’s I argument against Hume, defending the view that judgments The topic is Hume’s objection that if moral judgments are about what is reasonable can motivate (V), and I reply to the claims about what is reasonable, they cannot motivate. But following objections (VI): the argument is question-begging; first the position Sidgwick is defending should be sketched. Hume can escape the argument by endorsing a standing- Following Smith, one can distinguish rationalism as a desire model of motivation; anti-Humean views cannot ac- count for obvious slack between belief and motivation; and conceptual position (that when I make a moral judgment, I Sidgwick’s strategy wrongly puts the burden on Hume. I am making a claim about what it is reasonable to do) from close with an objection I do not answer: Hume might ex- rationalism as a substantive position (that there are require- plain moral motivation as the noncognitivist does. ments of rationality that match up with moral require- 3 Two preliminaries. First, Sidgwick can be seen as offer- ments). By “rationalism” below, I mean rationalism as a ing a version of Michael Smith’s “moral problem”: conceptual position. Sidgwick does not give an explicit argument for rational- (i) Moral judgments are beliefs about what it is ism. He finds rationalism “in accordance with the common reasonable to do. view and language …. For we commonly think that wrong (ii) Moral judgments sometimes motivate. conduct is essentially irrational, and can be shown to be so (iii) Beliefs alone do not motivate.2 by argument” (ME 23). Rationalism is the position we need 2 See Michael Smith, The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994) p. 12. For the same problem, see David McNaughton, Moral Vision (Oxford: Black- 3 Smith, Problem pp. 63-5. well, 1988) p. 23. 2 Robert Shaver Sidgwick on Moral Motivation arguments to reject. irrational in the sense of being subject to rational criticism. This might seem far-fetched. “Irrational” has a range of Indeed, Sidgwick distinguishes between moral judgments meanings.4 On a narrow account, irrationality requires in- and claims such as “the food is disagreeable” by noting that ternal inconsistency: I believe what I think I have decisive “the peculiar emotion of moral approbation is … inseparably reason to reject, or I do what I think I have decisive reason bound up with the conviction …that the conduct approved not to do.5 It is unlikely that wrong conduct always involves is ‘really’ right—i.e., that it cannot, without error, be disap- this sort of irrationality. On a wide account, irrationality re- proved by any other mind” (ME 27). “Reason” rather than quires only that one is subject to rational criticism.6 Sidg- “moral sense” is appropriate because “the term Sense sug- wick holds that I can be subject to rational criticism without gests a capacity for feelings which may vary from A to B internal inconsistency. For example, in rejecting the view without either being in error ... and it appears to me funda- that there are only hypothetical imperatives, he writes that mentally important to avoid this suggestion” (ME 34). Ra- “[w]e do not all look with simple indifference on a man who tionalism can be thought of as claiming that moral judg- declines to take the right means to attain his happiness, on ments, unlike simple reports or expressions of feeling, are no other ground than that he does not care about happiness. subject to rational criticism, although the criticism need not Most men would regard such a refusal as irrational” (ME 7). consist in showing an internal inconsistency.8 After arguing that various axioms, such as the superven- ience of the moral on the non-moral, pass his tests for high- II est certainty, Sidgwick comments that “I regard the appre- Sidgwick seems to claim that belief and rationality are suffi- hension … of these abstract truths, as the permanent basis of cient for moral motivation. For example, “[w]hen I speak of the common conviction that the fundamental precepts of the cognition or judgment that ‘X ought to be done’ ... as a morality are essentially reasonable” (ME 383). Reasonable- ‘dictate’ or ‘precept’ of reason to the persons to whom it re- ness lies in passing epistemic tests for clarity, self-evidence, lates, I imply that in rational beings as such this cognition and consistency within and between people; internal consis- gives an impulse or motive to action” (ME 34). These cogni- tency is not enough. Similarly, Sidgwick often describes cus- toms, biases, prejudices, and privileges as being “irrational,” irrationality. But Sidgwick goes on to distinguish two “grades” of inconsis- where this seems best glossed as “against the balance of rea- tency: “Our impulses to action may be such as not to conflict, and yet not har- sons.”7 All this suggests that for Sidgwick, wrong conduct is monized or systematized: or they may be actually opposed and conflicting.” As an example of the latter, Sidgwick suggests “when desiring an end we decline to 4 For a useful discussion, see T.
Recommended publications
  • David Hume on Norms and Institutions"
    Max Weber Programme Conference "David Hume on Norms and Institutions" San Domenico di Fiesole, Villa la Fonte, 17 April 2008 Justice as Unintended Consequence Please do not cite without prior permission Russel Hardin Department of Politics, New York University © 2006, Russell Hardin 2008.04.14 Justice As Unintended Consequence Russell Hardin* NYU - Politics One of the most neglected of all major legal philosophers is David Hume. His neglect as a specifically legal philosopher has followed from at least two unrelated causes. First, Hume’s work on ethics and on political philosophy was widely opposed and even dismissed in his own time. Second, a generation or so after his death, the positive law tradition of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin took center-stage in legal philosophy and dominated the Anglo-Saxon tradition for more than a century thereafter. This latter phenomenon might not have occluded attention to Hume except that Bentham ([1789] 1970) and Austin ([1832] 1954) took over a continental and quasi Hobbesian principle that was not necessary for their approach but which came to define it in the view of many. That principle is that there must be a primary law giver who is above the law. One could read this principle as analogous to the Aristotelian assumption that there must be a first mover, in this case, a first mover to get law started. Or one could read it as a Hobbesian assumption that we require an all powerful sovereign who is above the law but who gives and enforces the law for all other citizens. Hobbes sees his requirement as both logically and causally necessary.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Pacific Division Meeting Program 2017
    The American Philosophical Association PACIFIC DIVISION NINETY-FIRST ANNUAL MEETING PROGRAM THE WESTIN SEATTLE SEATTLE, WASHINGTON APRIL 12 – 15, 2017 VIVA VOCE ENTANGLEMENTS Conversations with A System of Philosophy Italian Philosophers Crispin Sartwell Silvia Benso CENTERING NEO-CONFUCIAN AND EXTENDING ECOLOGICAL HUMANISM NEW FORMS An Essay on An Interpretive Engage- OF REVOLT Metaphysical Sense ment with Wang Fuzhi Essays on Kristeva’s Steven G. Smith (1619–1692) Intimate Politics Nicholas S. Brasovan Sarah K. Hansen and Available May 2017 Rebecca Tuvel, editors EDGAR ALLAN POE, Available June 2017 EUREKA, AND GOD AND THE SELF SCIENTIFIC IN HEGEL CONFUCIANISM, A IMAGINATION Beyond Subjectivism HABIT OF THE HEART David N. Stamos Paolo Diego Bubbio Bellah, Civil Religion, Available July 2017 and East Asia SELF-REALIZATION Philip J. Ivanhoe and THROUGH CONFUCIAN ZHUANGZI’S CRITIQUE Sungmoon Kim, editors LEARNING OF THE CONFUCIANS A Contemporary Blinded by the Human ESSAYS ON THE FOUN- Reconstruction of Kim-chong Chong DATIONS OF ETHICS Xunzi’s Ethics Siufu Tang WHITEHEAD’S C. I. Lewis RELIGIOUS THOUGHT John Lange, editor From Mechanism to Available June 2017 POETIC FRAGMENTS Organism, From Force Karoline von Günderrode to Persuasion THE VARIETY OF Translated and with Daniel A. Dombrowski INTEGRAL ECOLOGIES Introductory Essays by Nature, Culture, Anna C. Ezekiel CONFUCIANISM AND and Knowledge AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY in the Planetary Era MOUNTAINS, RIVERS, Mathew A. Foust Sam Mickey, Sean Kelly, AND THE GREAT EARTH and Adam Robbert, Reading
    [Show full text]
  • Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S
    July 2012 Three Dimensions of Classical Utilitarian Economic Thought ––Bentham, J.S. Mill, and Sidgwick–– Daisuke Nakai∗ 1. Utilitarianism in the History of Economic Ideas Utilitarianism is a many-sided conception, in which we can discern various aspects: hedonistic, consequentialistic, aggregation or maximization-oriented, and so forth.1 While we see its impact in several academic fields, such as ethics, economics, and political philosophy, it is often dragged out as a problematic or negative idea. Aside from its essential and imperative nature, one reason might be in the fact that utilitarianism has been only vaguely understood, and has been given different roles, “on the one hand as a theory of personal morality, and on the other as a theory of public choice, or of the criteria applicable to public policy” (Sen and Williams 1982, 1-2). In this context, if we turn our eyes on economics, we can find intimate but subtle connections with utilitarian ideas. In 1938, Samuelson described the formulation of utility analysis in economic theory since Jevons, Menger, and Walras, and the controversies following upon it, as follows: First, there has been a steady tendency toward the removal of moral, utilitarian, welfare connotations from the concept. Secondly, there has been a progressive movement toward the rejection of hedonistic, introspective, psychological elements. These tendencies are evidenced by the names suggested to replace utility and satisfaction––ophélimité, desirability, wantability, etc. (Samuelson 1938) Thus, Samuelson felt the need of “squeezing out of the utility analysis its empirical implications”. In any case, it is somewhat unusual for economists to regard themselves as utilitarians, even if their theories are relying on utility analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Sidgwick's Philosophical Intuitions
    Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, X, 2008, 2, pp. 185-209 Sidgwick’s Philosophical Intuitions Anthony Skelton Department of Philosophy University of Western Ontario [email protected] ABSTRACT Sidgwick famously claimed that an argument in favour of utilitarianism might be provided by demonstrating that a set of defensible philosophical intuitions undergird it. This paper focuses on those philosophical intuitions. It aims to show which specific intuitions Sidgwick endorsed, and to shed light on their mutual connections. It argues against many rival interpretations that Sidgwick maintained that six philosophical intuitions constitute the self- evident grounds for utilitarianism, and that those intuitions appear to be specifications of a negative principle of universalization (according to which differential treatments must be based on reasonable grounds alone). In addition, this paper attempts to show how the intuitions function in the overall argument for utilitarianism. The suggestion is that the intuitions are the main positive part of the argument for the view, which includes Sidgwick's rejection of common-sense morality and its philosophical counterpart, dogmatic intuitionism. The paper concludes by arguing that some of Sidgwick's intuitions fail to meet the conditions for self-evidence which Sidgwick himself established and applied to the rules of common-sense morality. 0. One aim of Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics is to provide an argument for utilitarianism, the view that an agent acts rightly insofar as she performs that
    [Show full text]
  • The Methods of Ethics
    The Methods of Ethics Henry Sidgwick Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported between brackets in normal-sized type.—The division of the work into Books, chapters, and numbered sections is Sidgwick’s. —Cross-references follow this system: ‘chapter 3’ means ‘chapter 3 of this Book’. ‘chapter 4.2’ means ‘chapter 4, section 2, of this Book’. ‘II/3’ means ‘Book II, chapter 3’. ‘IV/3.4’ means ‘Book IV, chapter 3, section 4’. An accompanying page-number refers to the page where the passage in question starts.—This version omits most of the 2,000+ cautions that Sidgwick includes, such as ‘I think. ’, ‘I conceive. ’, ‘it seems. ’ and so on. Even with these out of the way, the work doesn’t come across as bullyingly dogmatic.—In this version, most notably on pages 166 and 196, the author addresses the reader (‘you’), but in the original it is always ‘the reader’ and ‘he’.—This version is based on the sixth edition of the work (1901), the last non-posthumous one. The first edition appeared in 1874, the year after Mill died. First launched: October 2011 The Methods of Ethics Henry Sidgwick Contents BOOK I 1 Chapter 1: Introduction........................................................1 Chapter 2: The relation of ethics to politics.............................................7 Chapter 3: Ethical judgments...................................................
    [Show full text]
  • On Sidgwick's Demise: a Reply to Professor Deigh
    On Sidgwick’s Demise: A Reply to Professor Deigh ANTHONY SKELTON The University of Western Ontario In ‘Sidgwick’s Epistemology’, John Deigh argues that Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ and that interest in it declined considerably after Sidgwick’s death because the epistemology on which it relied ‘increasingly became suspect in analytic philosophy and eventually [it was] discarded as obsolete’. In this article I dispute these claims. In a recent article in this journal, John Deigh1 argues that Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics2 ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ (438), and that interest in it declined considerably after Sidgwick’s death because the epistemology on which it relied ‘increasingly became suspect in analytic philosophy and eventually [it was] discarded as obsolete’ (439). In this article I dispute these claims. I Deigh argues that Sidgwick’s Methods ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ (438). However, this is far from clear. First, to make his point Deigh relies on an article in Encyclopaedia Britannica and an obituary in Mind by Leslie Stephen.3 These are not decisive. Stephen announces at the outset of his obituary that he is not concerned to provide an estimate of Sidgwick’s work in philosophy, though he notes that Methods is a ‘great book’ and that Sidgwick’s work in ethics gave ‘the most important of all modern contributions towards a clear realisation of the conditions of approaching the problems involved’.4 The encyclopaedia article does not deny that Methods is a major contribution; instead, it merely fails to single it out.5 Second, a number of important philosophers were sent copies of Methods when the first edition was published in 1874, 1 John Deigh, ‘Sidgwick’s Epistemology’, Utilitas 19 (2007), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • HUME and MILL on "UTILITY of RELIGION": a BORGEAN GARDEN of FORKING PATHS?L
    TEAO~ Reuista Iberoamericana de Estudios Utilitaristas-2005, XlVII: 117-129 ISSN 1132-0877 HUME AND MILL ON "UTILITY OF RELIGION": A BORGEAN GARDEN OF FORKING PATHS?l JOSE L. TASSET2 University ofA Coruiia ABSTRACT This work is not a specific assessment of Utility ofReligion by John Stuart Mill, but a defence of what I think is a utilitarian, but not millian, view on the problem that work states, the question of the utility of religion in contemporary societies. I construct that view from neohumeanism more than from millian positions, notwithstanding, I postulate that view as a genuine utilitarian one. Every cultural tradition makes a different approach to ethical and political theories. Spanish and Ibero-American utilitarians make precisely it with Clas­ sical Utilitarianism. From that point of view, Ibero-American people identifies utilitarianism with radical and enlightened tradition linked with the reform that through XVIIIth and XIXth centuries tried to undermine the foundations of conservative society in our nations. This aim was not achieved, at least not completely; because of that, the pursuit of Utilitarianism remains opened between us. In the end,I will argue that Spanish and Ibero-American utilitarians connect utilitarianism with philosophical and political radicalism, and inside that His­ panic utilitarianism, plays an important role the criticism of social and political functions of Religion. Maybe, part of the future of Utilitarianism in our cultural context depends on a return of the Theory to its radical roots, also in religious subjects. Keywords: J ohn Stuart Mill, David Hume, Jorge Luis Borges, religion, deism, theism, functionalism, truth. RESUMEN Este trabajo no pretende ser una evaluaci6n especifica de la Utilidad de la Religi6n de John Stuart Mill, sino una defensa de 10 que creo es una posici6n 1 Date of acceptance: 26/07/2006.
    [Show full text]
  • The Dualism of Practical Reason and the Autonomy: Sidgwick's
    UDK: 141.2 FILOZOFIJA I DRUŠTVO XXVII (4), 2016. DOI: 10.2298/FID1604749D Original scientific article Received: 4.11.2016 — Accepted: 29.11.2016 Aleksandar Dobrijević The Dualism of Practical Reason and the Autonomy: Sidgwick’s Pessimism and Kant’s Optimism Abstract The question this paper is concerned with is: what if Immanuel Kant found a solution to the problem of the dualism of practical reason before Henry Sidgwick even came to formulate it? A comparison of Sidgwick’s and Kant’s approach to the problem of the dualism of practical reason is presented only in general terms, but the author concludes that this is sufficient for grasping the advantage of Kant’s solution to the problem. Keywords: Henry Sidgwick, Immanuel Kant, the dualism of practical reason, autonomy, pessimism, optimism An amusing and persistent anecdote that had followed Henry Sidgwick 749 for decades – namely, that he is the most famous philosopher that no one has ever heard of – cannot really be associated with his name any more.1 To become aware of this one needs only to take a look at the monographs written in the past several years about or inspired by his ethics.2 Surely, in professional academic circles Sidgwick’s book The Methods of Ethics (1981 [1907]) has been acknowledged since it’s first edition (1874) as one of the most important achievements in the history of ethics, as a classic work – and it’s still recognized as such.3 However, even those who proclaim the book to be an unsurpassable study in philosophical ethics admit that it is sometimes dull (Parfit 2011: xxxiii), written in the style of a complicated, technical treatise (Singer 2000: xiv).
    [Show full text]
  • Strange Science: Investigating the Limits of Knowledge in the Victorian
    0/-*/&4637&: *ODPMMBCPSBUJPOXJUI6OHMVFJU XFIBWFTFUVQBTVSWFZ POMZUFORVFTUJPOT UP MFBSONPSFBCPVUIPXPQFOBDDFTTFCPPLTBSFEJTDPWFSFEBOEVTFE 8FSFBMMZWBMVFZPVSQBSUJDJQBUJPOQMFBTFUBLFQBSU $-*$,)&3& "OFMFDUSPOJDWFSTJPOPGUIJTCPPLJTGSFFMZBWBJMBCMF UIBOLTUP UIFTVQQPSUPGMJCSBSJFTXPSLJOHXJUI,OPXMFEHF6OMBUDIFE ,6JTBDPMMBCPSBUJWFJOJUJBUJWFEFTJHOFEUPNBLFIJHIRVBMJUZ CPPLT0QFO"DDFTTGPSUIFQVCMJDHPPE Revised Pages Strange Science Revised Pages Revised Pages Strange Science Investigating the Limits of Knowledge in the Victorian Age ••• Lara Karpenko and Shalyn Claggett editors University of Michigan Press Ann Arbor Revised Pages Copyright © 2017 by Lara Karpenko and Shalyn Claggett All rights reserved This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, including illustrations, in any form (beyond that copying permitted by Sections 107 and 108 of the U.S. Copyright Law and except by reviewers for the public press), without written permission from the publisher. Published in the United States of America by the University of Michigan Press Manufactured in the United States of America c Printed on acid- free paper 2020 2019 2018 2017 4 3 2 1 A CIP catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging- in- Publication Data Names: Karpenko, Lara Pauline, editor. | Claggett, Shalyn R., editor. Title: Strange science : investigating the limits of knowledge in the Victorian Age / Lara Karpenko and Shalyn Claggett, editors. Description: Ann Arbor : University of Michigan Press, [2017] | Includes bibliographical references
    [Show full text]
  • The Scholarship and Praxis of Communication Ethics
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Fall 2005 The cholS arship and Praxis of Communication Ethics: Rhetorical Interruptions in Historical Narratives Melissa Cook Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Cook, M. (2005). The choS larship and Praxis of Communication Ethics: Rhetorical Interruptions in Historical Narratives (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/433 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DUQUESNE UNIVERSITY THE SCHOLARSHIP AND PRAXIS OF COMMUNICATION ETHICS: RHETORICAL INTERRUPTIONS IN HISTORICAL NARRATIVES A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DEPARTMENT OF COMMUNICATION & RHETORICAL STUDIES MCANULTY COLLEGE AND GRADUATE SCHOOL OF LIBERAL ARTS IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY MELISSA A. COOK PITTSBURGH, PENNSYLVANIA CONVOCATION DECEMBER 2005 The Scholarship and Praxis of Communication Ethics Copyright © August 22, 2005 Melissa A. Cook ii The Scholarship and Praxis of Communication Ethics Acknowledgements It is with heartfelt gratitude that I thank the following people who have supported my completion of the Ph.D. Program in Rhetoric at Duquesne University: The students who agreed to join my first Communication Ethics seminar held during Intercession of 2004 at Washington & Jefferson College. My current students at St. Vincent College, and those who joined the special topics class on communication ethics in the spring of 2005. This is the reason for my passion .
    [Show full text]
  • BART SCHULTZ, Phd
    BART SCHULTZ, PhD Senior Lecturer, Philosophy Department, Division of the Humanities Executive Director, Civic Knowledge Project, Office of Civic Engagement, University of Chicago Work Addresses: Division of the Humanities/Office of Civic Engagement Philosophy Dept./Civic Knowledge Project University of Chicago Edelstone Bldg. 133 Gates-Blake 126 (mail to Cobb MB# 133) 6030 S. Ellis Av. 5845 S. Ellis Av. Chicago, Il. 60637 Chicago, Il. 60637 Phone: 773-702-6007 or 773-834-3929 ext. 1 E-Mail: [email protected], website: http://civicknowledge.uchicago.edu Research and Teaching Interests: Contemporary Social, Political, and Ethical Theory, History of Modern Social, Political, and Ethical Theory, Chicago Studies, LGBTQ Studies, Victorian Studies, Happiness Studies, Critical Race Theory, Philosophy of Education/Precollegiate Philosophy, Environmental Studies, Utilitarian Studies, and Philosophy of Social Science. Publications Books: Memoirs. In preparation. Editor, Sacred Ground: The Chicago Streets of Timuel D. Black, by Timuel D. Black, with Susan Klonsky (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, forthcoming 2018). The long-awaited memoirs of Prof. Timuel D. Black, educator, oral historian, civil rights activist, and the Senior Statesman of Chicago’s South Side. The Happiness Philosophers: The Lives and Works of the Great Utilitarians (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2017). This book provides an original interpretation of the philosophers, social critics and reformers William Godwin and Mary Wollstonecraft, Jeremy Bentham,
    [Show full text]
  • Guest Editor's Preface. Sidgwick and the Universe
    113 Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XVIII, 2016, 1, pp. 113-117 GUEST EDITOR’S PREFACE. SIDGWICK AND THE UNIVERSE: AN INTRODUCTION A SYMPOSIUM ON KATARZYNA DE LAZARI-RADEK AND PETER SINGER, THE POINT OF VIEW OF THE UNIVERSE: SIDGWICK AND CONTEMPORARY ETHICS BART SCHULTZ University of Chicago [email protected] It has taken 140 years, but the Victorian era philosopher Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics, first published in 1874, has finally received a full-scale and tru- ly formidable defense of its central claims about the rational basis of ethical judgment, a hedonistic account of the good, and act utilitarianism--Katarzyna de Lazari-Radek and Peter Singer’s The Point of View of the Universe: Sidgwick and Contemporary Ethics(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014). To be sure, many brilliant philosophers, including those who contributed essays to this symposium, have celebrated the Methods as a masterpiece of philosophical ethics. And de Lazari-Radek and Singer certainly recognize this and give credit where credit is due: In this book, we have followed the main lines of Sidgwick’s thinking about ethics, and tested his views both against our own reasoning and against the best of the vast body of recent and current philosophical writing on the topics he addresses. The overarching question we have sought to answer is whether Sidgwick’s form of utili- tarianism can be defended. In most respects we believe it can be. Parfit’s claim that, in the long tradition of ethics, ‘Sidgwick’s book contains the largest number of true and important claims’ stands up well.
    [Show full text]