Moral Psychology and Political Exclusion in Kant and Mill

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Moral Psychology and Political Exclusion in Kant and Mill A Matter of Character: Moral Psychology and Political Exclusion in Kant and Mill Inder Singh Marwah A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto © Copyright by Inder S. Marwah (2011) A Matter of Character: Moral Psychology and Political Exclusion in Kant and Mill Inder Singh Marwah Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto 2011 Abstract What kind of agent does liberal political thought presuppose? Who is the subject inhabiting modern, liberal conceptions of political order? This dissertation is a study of liberal character-formation, of the kinds of persons, subjects and citizens underlying seminal works in the liberal tradition. More specifically, it explores the forms of character and agency sustaining Immanuel Kant’s and John Stuart Mill’s moral and political philosophies, as well as problems of exclusion and marginalization faced by agents who are, either naturally or circumstantially, unable to develop a properly liberal character. The project is guided by three central aims. The first is expository: the dissertation draws to light the substantial attention that Kant and Mill both devoted to the moral psychology of progressive, liberal agency, and to the conditions, processes and mechanisms forming a liberal character. The second aim is critical, examining the ways in which these ideals of liberal character stand to constrain the inclusiveness and equality at the centre of liberal moral and political doctrines. The final aim is evaluative, reflecting on how we might situate problems of exclusion, both within the broader ii architectures of Kant’s and Mill’s respective philosophical systems, and in relation to the liberalisms that we inherit from them. iii Acknowledgments While dissertations are largely written in solitude, they are certainly not built alone. For those who have, over the last few years, provided invaluable and stimulating discussion, concerted guidance, critical feedback, helpful advice, cups of coffee, company over pints and innumerable other forms of support, I owe you thanks. I owe a great debt of gratitude to my supervisor, Ronnie Beiner. Ronnie saw me through a dissertation that ended up arguing almost the complete opposite of what it initially set out to, providing me with the right combination of intellectual space and support to clamber through, and eventually fix, my own thoughts. He was a wonderfully attentive reader and critic, and was unwavering in his openness and receptivity to my sometimes half-concocted ideas. Ronnie’s deep appreciation for, and commitment to, the canonical thinkers and texts in the history of political thought is an inspiration for my own. I could not have had a better doctoral committee. Peggy Kohn not only led me towards critical literatures and perspectives from which I benefited greatly, but is, more broadly, a model of intellectual diversity and openness. She provided equal measures of inspiration and guidance throughout the process, and I continue to marvel at the breadth of her interests. Joe Carens’ analytical clarity and uncanny ability to see the forest when I could only see the trees was critically important in guiding me through this project. There are few better ways that I know to get your thoughts in order than to go for a dog walk with Joe. Simone Chambers and Lisa Ellis both provided rich comments, suggestions and insights on the dissertation, and I remain profoundly indebted to them both. Their scholarship on Kant is, quite simply, exemplary; I can only hope to one day contribute to the ongoing conversations on Kant that they each lead. The University of Toronto is a pretty fantastic place to be a political theorist for many reasons, but perhaps none more than for the colleagues and friends with whom one has an opportunity to share one’s work. More than a few of my papers and chapters benefited from the critical scrutiny of the political theory reading group, which included Erica Frederiksen, Leah Soroko, James McKee, Margaret Haderer, Jakeet Singh, Mihaela Mihai, Alex Livingston, Adrian Neer, Serdar Tekin and Kiran Banerjee; all scholars should be so lucky as to have such gifted and attentive readers and friends. In particular, I am deeply grateful to Alex, Kiran, James and Mihaela; their friendship, scholarship and willingness to read countless papers, discuss half-baked ideas and drink coffee and liquors at all hours of the day and night has made not just my work, but also my life, a whole lot better. I have been very fortunate for the opportunity to work on several research projects beyond my dissertation that have contributed to my academic, professional and personal development in more ways than I can account for. I am very grateful to Phil Triadafilopoulos, Anna Korteweg and Gökçe Yurdakul for involving me in their research and drawing me to think a little more carefully about how my theoretical interests iv intersect with the real world. Phil in particular has, over the course of these years, been a great mentor, advisor, employer, colleague and, most importantly, a wonderful friend. I am immeasurably enriched by his friendship and inspired by his example. The research that I have carried out of the course of these years has been generously supported by the University of Toronto’s Department of Political Science and School of Graduate Studies. There are not too many places that enable people to immerse themselves in the world of political theory to the degree that this department and university do; I am lucky to have had such a stimulating and supportive intellectual home. I am also thankful for my involvement with the Centre for Ethics. The Centre was not only a great source for valuable seminars, colloquia and conferences, but also provided a vibrant home for an interdisciplinary group of researchers in ethics. Under the stewardship of Melissa Williams, the Centre not only drew together a rich community of scholarship, but also reached out to graduate students. I am not alone in having benefited enormously from my involvement with the Centre. I am also grateful to the network of friends and family that have kindly put up with me as I’ve made my way through this project. Dan Newman, Kellie Davis, Matt and Isis Cowley, Carrie Gulland, Chuck Erlichman, Connie Walker, Aidan Roman-Crossland, Jeremy Coghill, Saul Davis, Céline Cressman, Dak Dekerckhove, Jennie Knopp, Nick Smith, Mark Satterthwaite, Sam and Kristin Simmons, Ian Brooks, Laura Boudreau, Amy Nugent, Tomaz Jardim, Jon Seet, Michelle Buckley: thanks for simply being your lovely selves. Thanks to my family-in-law, John, Joanna, Rupert and Verity, for so warmly embracing me in general, and more particularly, for introducing me to the joys of Cornish pasties on wonderfully memorable trips to St. Ives. And a particularly big thanks to my own family. To Jaspal, whose unceasing curiosity and steadfast refusal to follow well- worn tracks I will always find inspiring, and to my parents, Lally and Marlène, whose unwavering commitments to the value of education and learning provided all of the support a person could ever hope for, thank you. Finally, my greatest thanks go to Morwenna. She has not only tolerated the anxieties and challenges that so naturally accompany a dissertation, but has always been able to draw me out of my often-narrowed vision with warmth, perspective, love and consideration. This dissertation would not exist without her. v Table of Contents Chapter 1: Matters of Law, Questions of Character…………………….....................1 1.1 The God Who Loves You………………………………………………….....1 1.2 A Few Considerations………………………………………………………..10 1.2.1 Considerations of Method………………………………………….10 1.2.2 Considerations of Subject………………………………………….13 1.2.3 Considerations of Terminology……………………………………16 1.3 Intransigent Freedom and the Conduct of Conduct………………...…….….18 1.4 Mapping Our Way…………………………………………………………...27 Chapter 2: Unbending Crooked Timber: A Developmental Account of Kantian Moral Agency………………………………………………...39 2.1 Introduction………………………………………………………………….39 2.2 Transcendental Grounding, Empirical Contexts…………………………….45 2.2.1 Between Critique and Anthropology……………………………....45 2.2.2 Elateres Motiva: Moral Feeling and the Subjective Grounds of Choice………………………………………………...49 2.3 Making Moral Agents……………………………………………………….54 2.3.1 Micro-Formation…………………………………………………..56 i. The Fine Balance of Moral Education………………………...56 ii. Stages of Pedagogy: Discipline, Culture, Moral Training…....58 iii. Moral Training I: Habituation………………………………..61 iv. Moral Training II: Propaedeutic Aids......................................64 v. Virtue and Moral Character…………………………………...67 vi. Moral Revolution and Disposition: The Good Human Being…………………………………………………71 2.3.2 Macro-Formation…………………………………………………..76 i. History: Stages of Progress……………………………………77 ii. Culture and Civilization: Bridging Nature and Freedom……..80 vi iii. Political Education…………………………………………...83 2.4 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………...89 Chapter 3: Progressive Agents and Agents of Progress: Exclusion in Kant’s Moral and Political Thought……………………………………...92 3.1 Problems of Exclusion, Moral and Political…………………………………92 3.2 Political Exclusion.………………………………………………………......96 3.2.1 Citizens and Cobeneficiaries………………………………………96 3.2.2 Self-Mastery, Non-Mastery and Political Judgment………………98 3.3 Political Exclusion, Moral Exclusion…………………………...………….104 3.3.1 What Nature Makes of Her: Kant’s Gendered Metaphysics……..104 3.3.2 Three
Recommended publications
  • 1 on Reasonable Hope Dana Howard Prepared for the Political Theory
    On Reasonable Hope Dana Howard Prepared for the Political Theory Workshop Ohio State University Abstract: John Rawls has argued that one of the aims of a theory of justice is to offer us reasonable hope for a just future. But what makes hope reasonable? And is it misguided to think that reasonable hope is a proper aim of political philosophy? In this paper, I trace the development of Rawls’s conception of reasonable hope by looking more closely at his treatment of Immanuel Kant’s conceptions of Reasonable Faith and of philosophy as Apologia. The idea of reasonable hope goes beyond the weaker kind of “reconciliation” put forward by Rousseau’s account of a conjectural history. It is one thing to believe, with Rousseau, that our deep natures are not incompatible with the possibility of a just society. It is something further to harbor any hope for this in the future. I argue that this temporal aspect, which is built into what Kant and Rawls mean by reasonable hope, is a useful approach to the practice of political philosophy. An approach that takes the need for reasonable hope seriously is one that moves political theorizing from a more passive framework of theoretical imagination toward a more active one that entails political anticipation. 1 John Rawls asserts that political philosophy ought to be realistically utopian; that is, it ought to extend what we ordinarily take to be “the limits of practical political possibility.”1 On his view, a realistic utopia makes us aware of certain available political and social alternatives that we may have previously thought impossible given our non-ideal circumstances.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant Was Born in 1724, and Published “Religion Within The
    CHAPTER FIVE THE PHENOMENOLOGY AND ‘FORMATIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS’ It is this self-construing method alone which enables philosophy to be an objective, demonstrated science. (Hegel 1812) Immanuel Kant was born in 1724, and published “Religion within the limits of Reason” at the age of 70, at about the same time as the young Hegel was writing his speculations on building a folk religion at the seminary in Tübingen and Robespierre was engaged in his ultimately fatal practical experiment in a religion of Reason. Kant was a huge figure. Hegel and all his young philosopher friends were Kantians. But Kant’s system posed as many problems as it solved; to be a Kantian at that time was to be a participant in the project which Kant had initiated, the development of a philosophical system to fulfill the aims of the Enlightenment; and that generally meant critique of Kant. We need to look at just a couple of aspects of Kant’s philosophy which will help us understand Hegel’s approach. “I freely admit,” said Kant , “it was David Hume ’s remark [that Reason could not prove necessity or causality in Nature] that first, many years ago, interrupted my dogmatic slumber and gave a completely differ- ent direction to my enquiries in the field of speculative philosophy” (Kant 1997). Hume’s “Treatise on Human Nature” had been published while Kant was still very young, continuing a line of empiricists and their rationalist critics, whose concern was how knowledge and ideas originate from sensation. Hume was a skeptic; he demonstrated that causality could not be deduced from experience.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Pacific Division Meeting Program 2017
    The American Philosophical Association PACIFIC DIVISION NINETY-FIRST ANNUAL MEETING PROGRAM THE WESTIN SEATTLE SEATTLE, WASHINGTON APRIL 12 – 15, 2017 VIVA VOCE ENTANGLEMENTS Conversations with A System of Philosophy Italian Philosophers Crispin Sartwell Silvia Benso CENTERING NEO-CONFUCIAN AND EXTENDING ECOLOGICAL HUMANISM NEW FORMS An Essay on An Interpretive Engage- OF REVOLT Metaphysical Sense ment with Wang Fuzhi Essays on Kristeva’s Steven G. Smith (1619–1692) Intimate Politics Nicholas S. Brasovan Sarah K. Hansen and Available May 2017 Rebecca Tuvel, editors EDGAR ALLAN POE, Available June 2017 EUREKA, AND GOD AND THE SELF SCIENTIFIC IN HEGEL CONFUCIANISM, A IMAGINATION Beyond Subjectivism HABIT OF THE HEART David N. Stamos Paolo Diego Bubbio Bellah, Civil Religion, Available July 2017 and East Asia SELF-REALIZATION Philip J. Ivanhoe and THROUGH CONFUCIAN ZHUANGZI’S CRITIQUE Sungmoon Kim, editors LEARNING OF THE CONFUCIANS A Contemporary Blinded by the Human ESSAYS ON THE FOUN- Reconstruction of Kim-chong Chong DATIONS OF ETHICS Xunzi’s Ethics Siufu Tang WHITEHEAD’S C. I. Lewis RELIGIOUS THOUGHT John Lange, editor From Mechanism to Available June 2017 POETIC FRAGMENTS Organism, From Force Karoline von Günderrode to Persuasion THE VARIETY OF Translated and with Daniel A. Dombrowski INTEGRAL ECOLOGIES Introductory Essays by Nature, Culture, Anna C. Ezekiel CONFUCIANISM AND and Knowledge AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY in the Planetary Era MOUNTAINS, RIVERS, Mathew A. Foust Sam Mickey, Sean Kelly, AND THE GREAT EARTH and Adam Robbert, Reading
    [Show full text]
  • 5. What Matters Is the Motive / Immanuel Kant
    This excerpt is from Michael J. Sandel, Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do?, pp. 103-116, by permission of the publisher. 5. WHAT MATTERS IS THE MOTIVE / IMMANUEL KANT If you believe in universal human rights, you are probably not a utili- tarian. If all human beings are worthy of respect, regardless of who they are or where they live, then it’s wrong to treat them as mere in- struments of the collective happiness. (Recall the story of the mal- nourished child languishing in the cellar for the sake of the “city of happiness.”) You might defend human rights on the grounds that respecting them will maximize utility in the long run. In that case, however, your reason for respecting rights is not to respect the person who holds them but to make things better for everyone. It is one thing to con- demn the scenario of the su! ering child because it reduces overall util- ity, and something else to condemn it as an intrinsic moral wrong, an injustice to the child. If rights don’t rest on utility, what is their moral basis? Libertarians o! er a possible answer: Persons should not be used merely as means to the welfare of others, because doing so violates the fundamental right of self-ownership. My life, labor, and person belong to me and me alone. They are not at the disposal of the society as a whole. As we have seen, however, the idea of self-ownership, consistently applied, has implications that only an ardent libertarian can love—an unfettered market without a safety net for those who fall behind; a 104 JUSTICE minimal state that rules out most mea sures to ease inequality and pro- mote the common good; and a celebration of consent so complete that it permits self-in" icted a! ronts to human dignity such as consensual cannibalism or selling oneself into slav ery.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle, Kant, JS Mill and Rawls Raphael Cohen-Almagor
    1 On the Philosophical Foundations of Medical Ethics: Aristotle, Kant, JS Mill and Rawls Raphael Cohen-Almagor Ethics, Medicine and Public Health (Available online 22 November 2017). Abstract This article aims to trace back some of the theoretical foundations of medical ethics that stem from the philosophies of Aristotle, Immanuel Kant, John Stuart Mill and John Rawls. The four philosophers had in mind rational and autonomous human beings who are able to decide their destiny, who pave for themselves the path for their own happiness. It is argued that their philosophies have influenced the field of medical ethics as they crafted some very important principles of the field. I discuss the concept of autonomy according to Kant and JS Mill, Kant’s concepts of dignity, benevolence and beneficence, Mill’s Harm Principle (nonmaleficence), the concept of justice according to Aristotle, Mill and Rawls, and Aristotle’s concept of responsibility. Key words: Aristotle, Immanuel Kant, John Stuart Mill, autonomy, beneficence, benevolence, dignity, justice, nonmaleficence, responsibility, John Rawls Introduction What are the philosophical foundations of medical ethics? The term ethics is derived from Greek. ἦθος: Noun meaning 'character' or 'disposition'. It is used in Aristotle to denote those aspects of one's character that, through appropriate moral training, develop into virtues. ἦθος is related to the adjective ἠθικός denoting someone or something that relates to disposition, e.g., a philosophical study on character.[1] 2 Ethics is concerned with what is good for individuals and society. It involves developing, systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong behaviour. The Hippocratic Oath (c.
    [Show full text]
  • When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’S Development Into a Normative Ideal
    When the Kingdom of God Became the Kingdom of Ends: Altruism’s Development into a Normative Ideal A Senior Honor Thesis Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for graduation with distinction in Political Science in the College of Social and Behavioral Sciences by Benjamin T. Jones The Ohio State University December 10, 2006 Project Advisors: John M. Parrish, Department of Political Science (Loyola Marymount University) Michael A. Neblo, Department of Political Science (The Ohio State University) Table of Contents Abstract ii Acknowledgements iii Introduction 1 The Paradox at the Heart of Altruism 4 Defining Altruism and Normativity 6 What Are We Looking For? 11 Roadmap of What’s to Come 14 Part I Towards a Problem: The Ancient Debate over Public Life 17 Eudaimonia and Ancient Ethics 18 Plato and Aristotle 24 Epicurus and the Stoics 40 A Solution from an Unlikely Source 47 Augustine’s Reconciliation of the Two Cities 55 Conclusion 63 Part II Self-Love’s Fall from Grace: How Normative Altruism Developed out of the Augustinian Tradition 65 Entangled in Self-love: Augustine’s Normative Argument 67 Augustine Goes Secular 75 Kant’s Problematic Solution 83 Reworking Kant—And Altruism 89 Conclusion 91 Part III The Problems with Normative Altruism 93 Two Conceptions of Altruism 93 Evidence for Altruism on a Descriptive Level 95 Motivational Barriers to Normative Altruism 113 Changing the Way We Talk About Altruism 121 Conclusion 126 Bibliography 131 i Abstract In contemporary moral philosophy, altruism holds a place of prominence. Although a complex idea, the term seeps into everyday discourse, by no means confined to the esoteric language of philosophers and psychologists.
    [Show full text]
  • On Sidgwick's Demise: a Reply to Professor Deigh
    On Sidgwick’s Demise: A Reply to Professor Deigh ANTHONY SKELTON The University of Western Ontario In ‘Sidgwick’s Epistemology’, John Deigh argues that Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ and that interest in it declined considerably after Sidgwick’s death because the epistemology on which it relied ‘increasingly became suspect in analytic philosophy and eventually [it was] discarded as obsolete’. In this article I dispute these claims. In a recent article in this journal, John Deigh1 argues that Henry Sidgwick’s The Methods of Ethics2 ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ (438), and that interest in it declined considerably after Sidgwick’s death because the epistemology on which it relied ‘increasingly became suspect in analytic philosophy and eventually [it was] discarded as obsolete’ (439). In this article I dispute these claims. I Deigh argues that Sidgwick’s Methods ‘was not perceived during his lifetime as a major and lasting contribution to British moral philosophy’ (438). However, this is far from clear. First, to make his point Deigh relies on an article in Encyclopaedia Britannica and an obituary in Mind by Leslie Stephen.3 These are not decisive. Stephen announces at the outset of his obituary that he is not concerned to provide an estimate of Sidgwick’s work in philosophy, though he notes that Methods is a ‘great book’ and that Sidgwick’s work in ethics gave ‘the most important of all modern contributions towards a clear realisation of the conditions of approaching the problems involved’.4 The encyclopaedia article does not deny that Methods is a major contribution; instead, it merely fails to single it out.5 Second, a number of important philosophers were sent copies of Methods when the first edition was published in 1874, 1 John Deigh, ‘Sidgwick’s Epistemology’, Utilitas 19 (2007), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Compassion and Sympathy As Moral Motivation Moral Philosophy Has Long Taken an Interest in the Emotions
    Compassion and Sympathy as Moral Motivation Moral philosophy has long taken an interest in the emotions. Ever since Plato’s defense of the primacy of reason as a source of motiva- tion, moral philosophers have debated the proper role of emotion in the character of a good person and in the choice of individual actions. There are striking contrasts that can be drawn among the main tradi- tions in moral philosophy as to the role they assign to the emotions, and to the particular emotions that they evaluate positively and nega- tively. Here are some examples. Utilitarianism is often presented as a the- ory which simply articulates an ideal of sympathy, where the morally right action is the one that would be favored by someone who is equally sympathetic to the pleasure and pains of all sentient beings. And, on another level, utilitarianism tends to evaluate highly actions motivated by sympathy and compassion, and to evaluate negatively actions motivated by malice and spite. Kantianism (or deontology, as it is often called) has a completely different structure and, conse- quently, a different attitude towards the emotions. It conceives of morality as the self-imposed laws of rational agents, and no emotion is thought to be involved in the generation of these laws. It is true that Kant himself does find a special role for the emotion—if that is the right word—of respect for rational agents and for the laws they impose on themselves. But Kant seems to regard respect as a sort of effect within us of our own inscrutable moral freedom, and not as the source of moral legislation.
    [Show full text]
  • For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? Constructive Complicity in Appropriations of the Canon Dilek Huseyinzadegan Emory University, [email protected]
    Feminist Philosophy Quarterly Volume 4 | Issue 1 Article 3 2018 For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? Constructive Complicity in Appropriations of the Canon Dilek Huseyinzadegan Emory University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/fpq Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, European History Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, Other Feminist, Gender, and Sexuality Studies Commons, Race, Ethnicity and Post-Colonial Studies Commons, and the Women's Studies Commons Recommended Citation Huseyinzadegan, Dilek. 2018. "For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? Constructive Complicity in Appropriations of the Canon." Feminist Philosophy Quarterly 4, (1). Article 3. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/fpq/vol4/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Feminist Philosophy Quarterly by an authorized editor of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Huseyinzadegan: For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? Constructive Complicity in Appropriations of the Canon Dilek Huseyinzadegan Abstract As feminist scholars, we hope that our own work is exempt from structural problems such as racism, sexism, and Eurocentrism, that is, the kind of problems that are exemplified and enacted by Kant’s works. In other words, we hope that we do not re-enact, implicitly or explicitly, Kant’s problematic claims, which range from the unnaturalness of a female philosopher, “who might as well have a beard,” the stupid things that a black carpenter said “because he was black from head to foot,” the poor women “living in the greatest slavery in the Orient,” to the “sheep-like existence of the inhabitants of Tahiti.” In this piece, I argue that we cannot simply hope to avoid these problems unless we are vigilant about incorporating the full picture of Kant’s and Kantian philosophy into our feminist appropriations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rise of Liberal Utilitarianism: Bentham and Mill Piers Norris
    The Rise of Liberal Utilitarianism: Bentham and Mill Piers Norris Turner, Ohio State University [DRAFT: final version forthcoming in The Blackwell Companion to 19th Century Philosophy, ed. J.A. Shand] I. Introduction By the turn of the nineteenth century, Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) was a well-known moral and legal reformer. A child of the Enlightenment, writing at the time of the American and French revolutions, Bentham had offered wide-ranging critiques of customary institutions and ways of thinking. He was particularly critical of appeals to natural law and intuition that, consciously or not, provided mere cover stories for people’s preferences. Such appeals, he argued, fail to provide real reasons: The various systems that have been formed concerning the standard of right and wrong… consist all of them in so many contrivances for avoiding the obligation of appealing to any external standard, and for prevailing upon the reader to accept of the author’s sentiment or opinion as a reason in itself. (An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation [IPML], II.14; B i.8)1 Because these cover stories are guided by people’s preferences, Bentham also argued that they are incapable of grounding a principled and well-organized set of public institutions. They instead protect established powers, whose likes and dislikes carry the most weight. His earliest writings, for instance, detail how the vagaries of the common law served entrenched interests rather than the public at large. What Bentham needed was a public principle that could guide a scientific program of legal codification and political reform.
    [Show full text]
  • [5] Mill Selections from on Liberty
    On Liberty Mill, John Stuart Published: 1859 Categorie(s): Non-Fiction, Human Science, Philosophy Source: Feedbooks 1 About Mill: John Stuart Mill (20 May 1806 – 8 May 1873), English philo- sopher, political theorist, political economist, civil servant and Member of Parliament, was an influential liberal thinker of the 19th century whose works on liberty justified freedom of the individual in opposition to unlimited state control. He was an exponent of utilitarianism, an ethical theory developed by Jeremy Bentham, although his conception of it was very differ- ent from Bentham's. He clearly set forth the premises of the scientific method. Also available on Feedbooks for Mill: • Utilitarianism (1863) Note: This book is brought to you by Feedbooks http://www.feedbooks.com Strictly for personal use, do not use this file for commercial purposes. 2 "The grand, leading principle, towards which every argument unfolded in these pages directly converges, is the absolute and essential importance of human development in its richest diversity." Wilhelm von Humboldt, Sphere and Duties of Government 3 To the beloved and deplored memory of her who was the in- spirer, and in part the author, of all that is best in my writ- ings—the friend and wife whose exalted sense of truth and right was my strongest incitement, and whose approbation was my chief reward—I dedicate this volume. Like all that I have written for many years, it belongs as much to her as to me; but the work as it stands has had, in a very insufficient degree, the inestimable advantage of her revision; some of the most im- portant portions having been reserved for a more careful re-ex- amination, which they are now never destined to receive.
    [Show full text]
  • In Praise of Liberalism: an Assessment of Liberal Political Thought from the 17Th Century to Today
    Review of Contemporary Philosophy Vol. 14, 2015, pp. 11–36, ISSN 1841-5261 IN PRAISE OF LIBERALISM: AN ASSESSMENT OF LIBERAL POLITICAL THOUGHT FROM THE 17TH CENTURY TO TODAY MICHAEL B. FRIEDMAN [email protected] School of Social Work, Columbia University ABSTRACT. The author of this essay maintains that liberalism has been the primary source of progressive change in the United States since its earliest history. To support his claim, he traces the philosophical and political history of liberalism in England and the United States. The specific forms of liberalism have varied in different periods of history; but, he maintains, there is an underlying spirit of liberalism that has persisted throughout the past 350 years and can be the source of dynamic progressive social change in the 21st century. Throughout history, he maintains, liberalism has been committed to social progress and has sought to improve the lives of populations that are economically and politically disadvantaged. This underlying spirit, the author argues, can be the source for an energized liberal agenda for the 21st century. Keywords: liberalism; political philosophy; political history 1. Introduction Conservative – and even centrist – opponents of liberalism reject it because they identify it with cumbersome government; reckless spending; high tax- ation; naiveté about economics, crime, and world power; and lack of moral values. What a mistake! In fact, liberalism has been the source of social and political progress in the Western world since the 17th century. The idea that rights set a limit on the legitimate power of government is a liberal idea. The idea that govern- ment must respect the liberty of individuals is a liberal idea.
    [Show full text]