X1 Characters Adeimantus (432/428 – >382) Is a Brother of Plato And

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

X1 Characters Adeimantus (432/428 – >382) Is a Brother of Plato And x1 Characters Below are brief descriptions of the main participants in Republic Book I, adapted from Debra Nails’ highly recommended study, The People of Plato. For a fuller study of these and other characters throughout the Platonic corpus, please consult her book. Adeimantus (432/428 – >382) is a brother of Plato and Glaucon. According to Socrates (Rep. 368a), both Glaucon and Adeimantus were recognized for their military service at a battle at Megara, which perhaps occurred at 409. Adeimantus is accompanying Polymarchus when Socrates and Glaucon arrive in the Piraeus. Cephalus ( ? – 421/415) is father of Polemarchus and Lysias. We learn from an autobiographical speech by Lysias (12) that Cephalus was invited by Pericles himself to come to Athens around 450 and as a metic became very wealthy as the owner of a shield-making factory. Clitophon ( 452 – >404) is a friend of both Lysias and Thrasymachus who intervenes briefly in the discussion between Socrates and Thrasymachus. Glaucon (ca. 429 – >382) is a brother of Plato and Adeimantus. According to Socrates (Rep. 368a) both Glaucon and Adeimantus were recognized for their military service at a battle at Megara, which perhaps occurred at 409. Both brothers will be Socrates’ chief interlocutors in Books 2-10 of the Republic. Lysias (ca. 445 – 380) is son of Cephalus and half-brother of Polemarchus. Very wealthy, he and his brother sponsored choral performances, paid war taxes (eisphora), and ransomed citizen prisoners of war (Lys. 12.20). When the Thirty temporary wrestled power from the democracy, Lysias fled the fate of his brother in 404 and returned in 403 to help restore the democracy. He became a successful speechwriter for legal clients, and many of his speeches survive today. Polemarchus (ca. 450 – 404): is a son of Cephalus and half-brother of Lysias. He was likely born in Syracuse and moved to Athens along with his father ca. 450. The house which provides the setting of the Republic is Polemarchus’.When the democracy was briefly overthrown as the end of the Peloponnesian war, the oligarchic regime known as the Thirty executed Polemarchus. Lysias recalls the events of Polemarchus’ arrest and death in a speech Against Eratosthenes (Lys. 12). Socrates (470 - 399): A stonemason by trade, Socrates acquired a reputation for discussing philosophy in public places. He did not write down his philosophical beliefs, so whatever we know about him comes from the works of a number of his contemporaries including Plato, Xenophon, and Aristophanes. Thrasymachus (ca. 455 - ? ) is a sophist from Chalcedon, a city in Asia Minor at the mouth of the Black Sea. Plato’s Socrates discusses his rhetorical style in the Phaedrus (267c-d) and later says that both Thrasymachus and Lysias provide the wrong models to acquire rhetorical skill (269d). 1 Taken from Steadman's “Plato's Republic I ' (POD, 2012).
Recommended publications
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates and Democratic Athens: the Story of the Trial in Its Historical and Legal Contexts
    Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. Version 1.0 July 2006 Josiah Ober Princeton University Abstract: Socrates was both a loyal citizen (by his own lights) and a critic of the democratic community’s way of doing things. This led to a crisis in 339 B.C. In order to understand Socrates’ and the Athenian community’s actions (as reported by Plato and Xenophon) it is necessary to understand the historical and legal contexts, the democratic state’s commitment to the notion that citizens are resonsible for the effects of their actions, and Socrates’ reasons for preferring to live in Athens rather than in states that might (by his lights) have had substantively better legal systems. Written for the Cambridge Companion to Socrates. © Josiah Ober. [email protected] Socrates and democratic Athens: The story of the trial in its historical and legal contexts. (for Cambridge Companion to Socrates) Josiah Ober, Princeton University Draft of August 2004 In 399 B.C. the Athenian citizen Socrates, son of Sophroniscus of the deme (township) Alopece, was tried by an Athenian court on the charge of impiety (asebeia). He was found guilty by a narrow majority of the empanelled judges and executed in the public prison a few days later. The trial and execution constitute the best documented events in Socrates’ life and a defining moment in the relationship between Greek philosophy and Athenian democracy. Ever since, philosophers and historians have sought to
    [Show full text]
  • The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(S): Darrell Dobbs Source: the American Political Science Review, Vol
    The Piety of Thought in Plato's Republic, Book 1 Author(s): Darrell Dobbs Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 88, No. 3 (Sep., 1994), pp. 668-683 Published by: American Political Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2944802 Accessed: 10/12/2010 23:53 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=apsa. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Political Science Review. http://www.jstor.org American Political Science Review Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Mitigating Operator-Induced Vehicle Mishaps
    The Life Most Worth Living: Virtue Theory in ancient and modern perspective Bill Rhodes, PhD Mitigating Operator-Induced Vehicle Mishaps Professional Education, Moral Neurophysiology, and Results-Based Assessment Philosophy • Love of wisdom • One (rough) way to “get located” – Natural – what is (no praise or blame) – Moral – what ought to be (conscience) • This course involves both aspects • And concentrates on practical application An unavoidable event—no choices An entirely avoidable mishap Pilot-induced And another . Branches of Philosophy • Metaphysics • Epistemology • Logic • Aesthetics • “Philosophy of . .” • Ethics – “The normative science of human conduct” Ethics • Two generally recognized (and interrelated) branches • Decision theories -- choosing – Deontology • Duties, rights; centered on what people deserve – Consequentialism • Greatest good for the greatest number; centered on happiness • Virtue theory and the practical question LMWL – What sort of person to be? Ancient Greeks and Liberal Arts • Socrates (479-399) • Plato (428-348) • Aristotle (384-322) • Free men with time and capacity for philosophy • Each with a sort of immortality (discussed in some depth later) Method • Dialectic – the philosopher’s laboratory • Logic and discernment • In Plato, Socrates is generally the protagonist – And he’s been told that the wisest of all men knows he does not know. – So he asks those who say they do know – Elenchus—reveals that beliefs are not always true – ( Not everyone appreciates elenchus) Republic - I • The conversation at the Piraeus • Polemarchus, Adeimantus, Glaucon, etc. • “Either prove stronger than we are, or you will have to stay here.” • A third possibility? Persuasion? • What if we won’t listen? • OK – go to Polemarchus’s house for discussion Cephalus on Justice • The old have traveled a road we will probably follow – Appetites relax; harmony ensues – Fear of death and that “stories are true” – Wealth allows speaking truth; keeping promises, repaying debts, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Republic of Plato
    THE REPUBLIC OF PLATO 'I'IlANSLATBD WInI INTJtODUCTlON AND NOTES BY FRANCIS MACDONALD CORNFORD LrrrD., F.B.A. Fellow of Trinity CoI1ege, Cambric:Igc OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS LONDON OXFORD NEW YORK OXFORD UN IVERSITY PRESS Oxford london New York Glasgow Toronto Melbourne Wellington Cape Town Salisbury Ibadan Nairobi lusaka Addis Ababa Bombay Calcutta Madras Karachi lahore Dacca Kuala lumpur Hong Kong Tokyo First published by Oxford University Press, london, 1941 First issued as an Oxford University Press paperback, 1945 This reprint, 1970-3 Printed in the United States of America CONTENTS Page xv PART I (Book I). SOME CURRENT VIEWS OF JUSTICE CHAP. I (i. 32?-33I D). Cephalus. Justice as Honesty in word and darl 2 II (331 E-336 A). Polemarchus. Justice as Helping Friends and Harming Enemies • 7 III (336 B-347 E). Thrasymachus. Justice as the Interest of the Stronger 14 IV (347 E-354 c). Thrasymachus. Is Injustice more profitable than Justice? 30 PART II (Books II-IV, 445 B). JUSTICE IN THE STATE AND IN THE INDIVIDUAL V (ii. 357 A-367 E). The Problem stated 41 VI (367 E-372 A). The Rudiments of Social Organization 53 VII (372 A-374 E). The Luxurious State 59 VIII (375 A-376 E). The Guardian's Temperament 63 IX (376 E-iii. 412 B). Primary Education of the Guardians 66 § 1 (376 E-iii. 392 c). Censorship of Literature for School Use 67 § 2 (392 c-398 B). The Influence of Dramatic Recitation 80 § 3 (398 c-4°O c). Musical Accompaniment and Metre 85 § 4 ("00 c-403 c).
    [Show full text]
  • The Republic
    The Republic - BOOK I “But do you see,” he rejoined, “how many we are?” SOCRATES - GLAUCON “Of course.” I went yesterday to the Piraeus with Glaucon the son of Ariston, that I might offer up my “And are you stronger than all these? for if not, prayers to the goddess; and also because I you will have to remain where you are.” wanted to see how they would celebrate the festival, which was a new thing. I was delighted “May there not be the alternative,” I said, with the procession of the inhabitants; but that “that we may persuade you to let us go?” of the Thracians was equally, if not more, beautiful. When we had finished our prayers “But can you persuade us, if we refuse to and viewed the spectacle, we turned toward the listen to you?” he said. city; and at that instant Polemarchus the son of Cephalus chanced to catch sight of us from a “Certainly not,” replied Glaucon. distance as we were starting on our way home, and told his servant to run and ask us to wait “Then we are not going to listen; of that you for him. The servant took hold of me by the may be assured.” cloak behind, and said: “Polemarchus wants you to wait.” Adeimantus added: “Has no one told you of the torch-race on horseback in honor of the I turned round, and asked him where his master goddess which will take place in the evening?” was. “With horses!” I replied: “That is a novelty. “There he is,” said the youth, “coming after Will horsemen carry torches and pass them one you, if you will only wait.” to another during the race?” “Certainly we will,” said Glaucon; and in a few “Yes,” said Polemarchus, “and not only so, but minutes Polemarchus appeared, and with him a festival will he celebrated at night, which you Adeimantus, Glaucon's brother, Niceratus the certainly ought to see.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato I PHIL301 the Task Prof. Oakes Updated: 2/27/14 1:44 PM
    Plato I PHIL301 The Task Prof. Oakes updated: 2/27/14 1:44 PM Republic I-II: The Task pp. 369-407 (327a-367e) - In this section, the subject of justice is broached; we see a Socratic-style elenctic exchange with Thrasymachus and others end in impasse; Glaucon and Adeimantus prevail upon Socrates to advance a positive account of justice. - This section is significant for its presentation of the traditional Socratic style and for a general sense of disappointment with that method and subsequent intention to provide a positive account of justice. Note, as always, Plato’s skill as a dramatist, and in particular the differences in Socrates’ responses to his interlocutors as their attitudes towards him and justice vary. Initial Discussion – Cephalus and Polemarchus - Plainly, neither Cephalus nor Polemarchus knows what justice is. Moreover, their ignorance – and, we might say, their ignorance of their ignorance – makes them vulnerable to moral failing.1 - Socrates gets Cephalus to say that justice is paying debts and telling the truth. But Cephalus is evidently ignorant of moral truth or indifferent to it. He has little interest in a serious discussion of it, and excuses himself by saying, untruthfully, that he must attend to a religious ceremony. (Another interpretation: Cephalus isn’t willing to undergo a Socratic examination, and wisely, politely, excuses himself. Question: is Cephalus a sympathetic character, or not?) - Polemarchus is at least willing to examine his own beliefs, though whether from a proper understanding of the value of doing so, or from a sense of filial duty, is unclear. (As usual, Plato is making claims by means of subtle dramatic exchanges: properly cognizant of moral truth, one would know perfectly well that one should investigate such matters.
    [Show full text]
  • Metics and Identity in Democratic Athens
    METICS AND IDENTITY IN DEMOCRATIC ATHENS By MATTHEW JOHN KEARS A thesis submitted to the University of Birmingham for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Institute of Archaeology and Antiquity College of Arts and Law University of Birmingham March 2013 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. ABSTRACT This thesis investigates the metics, or resident aliens, in democratic Athens and how they affected ideas of identity, with a particular focus on the fourth century BC. It looks at definitions of the metics and how the restrictions and obligations which marked their status operated; how these affected their lives and their image, in their own eyes and those of the Athenians; how the Athenians erected and maintained a boundary of status and identity between themselves and the metics, in theory and in practice; and how individuals who crossed this boundary could present themselves and be characterised, especially in the public context of the lawcourts. The argument is that the metics served as a contradiction of and challenge to Athenian ideas about who they were and what made them different from others.
    [Show full text]
  • The Republic
    Leo Strauss Plato’s Republic (1957) Seminar in Political Philosophy: Plato’s Republic A course given in the spring quarter, 1957 Department of Political Science, The University of Chicago Edited and with an introduction by Peter Ahrensdorf Peter Ahrensdorf is James Sprunt Professor of Political Science and affiliated professor of classics at Davidson College. He is the author of The Death of Socrates and the Life of Philosophy: An Interpretation of Plato’s Phaedo (State University of New York Press, 1995) and other works on ancient philosophy and drama. © 1975 Joseph Cropsey © 2014 The Estate of Leo Strauss. All Rights Reserved. TABLE OF CONTENTS Editor’s Introduction i-v The Leo Strauss Transcript Project vi-vii Editorial Headnote viii Session 1: Introduction, Book I 1-18 Session 2: Book I 19-34 Session 3: Book I 35-51 Session 4: Review, Book II 52-68 Session 5: Books II, III 69-82 Session 6: Books III, IV 83-100 Session 7: Book IV 101-113 Session 8: Books IV, V 114-128 Session 9: Books V, VI, VII 129-140 Session 10: Book VII 141-155 Session 11: Book VII 156-173 Session 12: Book VIII 174-190 Session 13: Books VIII, IX 191-204 Session 14: Books IX, X 205-218 Session 15: Book X; summary points 219-221 Plato’s Republic, spring 1957 i Introduction to Leo Strauss’s 1957 Spring Seminar on Plato’s Republic Peter J. Ahrensdorf Plato’s Republic had already played a leading role in Leo Strauss’s intellectual life long before he taught his seminar on that dialogue during the spring quarter of 1957.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato the REPUBLIC1 BOOK I SOCRATES
    24 Certainly not, replied Glaucon. Plato 328 1 Then we are not going to listen; of that you may be THE REPUBLIC assured. Adeimantus added: Has no one told you of the torch- BOOK I race on horseback in honour of the goddess which will SOCRATES - GLAUCON take place in the evening? 327 I WENT down yesterday to the Piraeus with Glaucon With horses! I replied: That is a novelty. Will horsemen the son of Ariston, that I might offer up my prayers to the carry torches and pass them one to another during the goddess; and also because I wanted to see in what manner race? they would celebrate the festival, which was a new thing. I was delighted with the procession of the inhabitants; but Yes, said Polemarchus, and not only so, but a festival that of the Thracians was equally, if not more, beautiful. will he celebrated at night, which you certainly ought to When we had finished our prayers and viewed the see. Let us rise soon after supper and see this festival; spectacle, we turned in the direction of the city; and at that there will be a gathering of young men, and we will have instant Polemarchus the son of Cephalus chanced to catch a good talk. Stay then, and do not be perverse. sight of us from a distance as we were starting on our way Glaucon said: I suppose, since you insist, that we must. home, and told his servant to run and bid us wait for him. The servant took hold of me by the cloak behind, and said: Very good, I replied.
    [Show full text]
  • The Republic
    PLATO The Republic G. R. F. FERRARI University of California, Berkeley TOM GRIFFITH The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge , United Kingdom The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge , UK http://www.cup.cam.ac.uk West th Street, New York, -, USA http://www.cup.org Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne , Australia Ruiz de Alarcón , Madrid, Spain © In the translation and editorial matter Cambridge University Press This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typeface Monotype Ehrhardt ./ pt. System QuarkXPress™ [] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication data Plato. [Republic. English] The republic / Plato ; edited by G. R. F.Ferrari ; translated by Tom Griffith. p. cm. – (Cambridge texts in the history of political thought) Includes index. --- (pbk) ‒ --- (hardback) . Political science–Early works to . Utopias–Early works to . Ferrari, G. R. F.(Giovanni R. F.) . Griffith, Tom. Title. Series . Ј.–dc - hardback paperback Contents Translator’s preface page vii Editor’s preface ix Introduction xi The Thirty xi Faction xiii A Spartan utopia? xiv The philosopher and the king xviii A political work? xxii City and soul xxv Mathematics and metaphysics xxix A guide to further reading
    [Show full text]
  • Thrasymachus' Sophistic Account of Justice in Republic I
    Ancient Philosophy 36 (2016) ©Mathesis Publications 1 Thrasymachus’ Sophistic Account of Justice in Republic i Merrick E. Anderson It is now widely recognized that Socrates’ discussion with Thrasymachus is crucially important for understanding the philosophic trajectory of Plato’s Republic .1 Thrasymachus is the first character explicitly to raise considerations about justice in the political sphere, and he introduces the concept of the ‘ruler in the strict sense’, which is later developed in the discussion of the philosopher- king. In Socrates’ responses to Thrasymachus certain themes are developed that prove fundamental to the Republic ’s later arguments, such as the identification of virtue as that which unifies the elements of our soul. Finally, books 2-10 are (in one form or another) a response to Thrasymachus’ claim that it is more profitable to live an unjust life than a just life. 2 It is easy to see why there is such a consen - sus that getting a clear understanding of Thrasymachus’ view is so important for understanding the Republic . And yet we are very far from understanding what Thrasymachus is up to. Even a brief survey of scholarship reveals that an amazingly diverse set of views and theories have been attributed to the anti-hero of the Republic . At various times he has been interpreted as an enlightened legalist (Hourani 1962), a confused con - ventionalist (Everson 1998), and a cynic (Samaras 2012). At other times he has been called ‘an ethical nihilist’ (Guthrie 1971, 96), a natural right theorist (Sparshott 1966), an immoralist or an amoralist (Williams 1985 and 2006), and an empirical sociologist (Santas 2006).
    [Show full text]