Plato's View of Tyranny Antonis Coumoundouros

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Plato's View of Tyranny Antonis Coumoundouros Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 2006 Plato's View of Tyranny Antonis Coumoundouros Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Coumoundouros, A. (2006). Plato's View of Tyranny (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/435 This Immediate Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. PLATO’S VIEW OF TYRANNY A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Philosophy Department McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Antonis Coumoundouros (03/03/2006) ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I am grateful for the opportunity to thank those who have made this dissertation possible. Ron Polansky deserves special thanks for following me through every stage of this process with great rigor and insight. His energy and endless curiosity are invaluable. I would also like to express my deep gratitude to Therese Bonin and James Swindal for their support and the great care with which they took in reading this dissertation. In addition I would like to thank my colleagues and friends in the graduate school for the many conversations, insights and suggestions, and particularly Patrick Macfarlane for his enthusiasm, encouragement and sobering advice. Moreover, I would like to thank Sandrinos and Aliki for their unconditional love and support. Finally and most of all I would like to thank Tara Beth for making my life better and more meaningful and for motivating me every day. Coumoundouros––Plato’s View of Tyranny ii Table of Contents Introduction 1-8 Chapter 1: The Terminology for Tyranny Before and During Plato’s Time 9-70 1.1 Why and How to Examine the Terminology for Tyranny 10-15 1.2 Tyranny and Athenian Self-perception 15-20 1.3 The First Occurrences of the Terms: Archilochus 20-23 1.4 Herodotus’ Histories 23-32 1.5 Thucydides’ Peloponnesian War 32-42 1.6 The Tragic Poets and Aristophanes 43-53 1.7 Athenian Orators of the Fifth and Fourth Century 53-59 1.8 Isocrates 59-69 1.9 Concluding Remarks 69-70 Chapter 2: Plato’s Preliminary Account of Tyranny in Republic I and II 71-96 2.1 Republic I: Thrasymachus’ Position on Justice and Tyranny 71-89 2.2 Republic II: Glaucon and Adeimantus’ Challenge and Further Description of Tyranny 89-96 Chapter 3: The General Argument of Republic VIII 97-117 3.1 The Role of the Account of Deviant Regimes in the Main Ethical Argument: Instrumentality and Incompleteness 98-103 3.2 The Logical and Empirical Perspectives of the Account of Deviant Regimes 103-105 3.3 The Analogy of the City and the Soul 105-110 3.4 Plato’s Depiction of Regime Change 110-115 3.5 The Incompleteness of the Account of Regimes 115-117 Chapter 4: The Origins of Tyranny: Democracy and the Potential Tyrant in Republic VIII 118-149 4.1 The Place of Tyranny in the General Order of Deviant Regimes 119-122 4.2 The Implications of License or Excessive Democratic Freedom 122-131 4.3 From Freedom to Slavery: The Principle of Excess 131-137 4.4 The Rise of the Tyrant 138-149 Chapter 5: Tyranny in Power 150-186 5.1 Appearing Just and Beneficent 152-163 5.2 Going to War 163-166 5.3 Suspicion and Elimination of Citizens as Enemies, the Need for Bodyguards, and the Lack of Friends 167-175 5.4 Tyranny and Poetry: Propaganda and Ideology 175-181 5.5 Tyranny’s Resources, the Tyrant as Parricide, and Tyranny as Slavery 181-184 5.6 Tyranny and Necessity 185-186 Coumoundouros––Plato’s View of Tyranny iii Chapter 6: The Tyrant’s Psychology 187-220 6.1 The Tyrant and the Tyrannical Man 187-189 6.2 Necessary, Unnecessary, and Unnecessary and Lawless Desires 189-201 6.3 The Origin of the Tyrannical Man and the Compulsory Grip of Eros 201-208 6.4 The Tyrannical Person’s Life: Desires and Deeds 209-213 6.5 How the Tyrannical Man May Become a Tyrant 213-217 6.6 The Tyrant’s Psychology and Necessity 217-220 Chapter 7: Plato’s Arguments Against Tyranny 221-243 7.1 Thrasymachus’ Challenge 221-222 7.2 Socrates’ Emphasis on a Comprehensive perspective and the Different Levels of Argument 222-225 7.3 Two Arguments Against Tyranny: Tyranny as a Self-Defeating Regime and Tyranny as a Bad Regime for Citizens 225-228 7.4 The Impotence and Wretchedness of Tyrannical Life 229-241 7.5 Necessity and Wretchedness in Tyrannical Life 241-243 Conclusion 244-253 Bibliography 254-263 Coumoundouros––Plato’s View of Tyranny iv Introduction. The aim of this dissertation is to highlight the timeless insights and enduring relevance of Plato’s view of tyranny. I examine Plato’s comprehensive account of tyranny and the tyrant in the Republic, and in so doing I contribute to our understanding of: (1) Plato’s view of tyranny and the tyrant, (2) the perennial political problem of tyranny in terms of its origins, goals, function, and measures it employs, (3) the tyrant as a political figure with particular desires related to his goals, actions, and measures as a ruler, and, thus (4) the relation between tyranny as a regime and the tyrant as a type of person. Let us begin by considering why tyranny is an intriguing topic in general and why Plato’s view of tyranny in particular deserves our attention. Despite the millennia that have passed since Plato’s time, it is evident that tyrannies still exist, that they still puzzle us, and that they still present us with problems. A look around the globe makes us realize that there are numerous governments in the countries of the former Soviet Union, the Americas, Africa, and Asia that we can readily call tyrannies. Contemporary or recent tyrants such as Kim Jong Il, Saddam Hussein, Pinochet, Mao, Hitler, and Stalin, or as old as Peisitratus, Dionysius II of Syracuse, Julius Caesar, and Louis XIV, have left considerable and controversial marks in history, and have not ceased to invite our curiosity. In our own time, especially since 9/11, there has been a considerable amount of discussion concerning tyranny, terrorism, freedom, and democracy. Some wonder whether terrorism and tyranny are related, and others claim that they are fundamentally related. Others, still, wonder whether democracies can come to replace tyrannies and how this may happen. Moreover, the Nazi horrors of World War II and those of Stalinist Coumoundouros––Plato’s View of Tyranny 1 Russia in the twentieth century became an incentive for various thinkers to investigate such political systems and to reawaken discussions on freedom, justice, and tyranny. Plato’s personal and controversial entanglements with tyrants brought him close to the phenomenon of tyranny and might partially explain why he was astonished by it. Plato lived in an Athens which remembered the tyranny of the Peisistratids, and which had recently lived through the tyranny of the Thirty. Plato tells us quite a bit about his experience with the Thirty in the Seventh Letter. He tells us that the previous Athenian democracy, engaged in the Peloponnesian war, seemed a great regime compared to the tyranny, “they showed [the Thirty tyrants] in a short time that the preceding constitution had been a precious thing” (324d-e). We know that Plato’s relatives, Charmides and Critias, were members of the Thirty, rich anti-democrats established by the Spartan king in 404. In fact, Critias was the head of the Thirty, which makes him a sort of tyrant of tyrants. Both Critias and Charmides were killed in 403 in the fighting that overthrew them and re-established the democracy. Plato’s involvement with the famous tyrant Dionysius II of Syracuse has fascinated and puzzled scholars since antiquity. In the Seventh Letter, we may find his attempts and failure to educate Dionysius and to turn him into a philosopher king in the manner described in the Republic. Whether this interpretation is correct or not, it still invites questions regarding the extent of Plato’s involvement with politics and the particular tyrant. Dionysius looks very much like the tyrant described in the Republic and thus we get a rather close and curious correlation between Plato’s work and his own life. Coumoundouros––Plato’s View of Tyranny 2 Plato’s founding of the Academy shows that he was deeply concerned with the polis and its fate. His experience with tyranny seems to have motivated him to begin a school where he sought to improve some citizens by philosophic education, and generally to enhance the level of culture of his time. The Academy was a school that existed in competition with other schools, such as Isocrates’ school of rhetoric. We also know that several members of the Academy were involved in politics which makes us suspect that political education was part of the program in the Academy. Now let us turn to tyranny as Plato discusses it in the dialogues. Following the 4th century, tyranny was a substantial problem for Plato and other intellectuals such as Thucydides, Xenophon, and Aristotle. Plato’s writings reveal to us that he was deeply concerned with it and that he sought to explain it. Plato shows this concern with his inclusion of his relatives as characters in his dialogues (see the Charmides).
Recommended publications
  • Clitophon's Challenge and the Aporia of Socratic Protreptic* Teruo Mishima
    Clitophon’s Challenge and the Aporia of Socratic Protreptic* Teruo Mishima Before I discuss the text in detail, I would like to briefly sketch the main line of arguments in the Clitophon which I am going to take up, just for the sake of anamnēsis of the readers : In the opening scene Socrates speaks to Clitophon in the third person and tells him that he heard from somebody else that Clitophon, in his conversation with Lysias, has criticised Socratic diatribai (pursuits), whereas he has lavishly praised his synousia (association) with Thrasymachus. Taking Socrates’ words as a sort of disguised criticism or complaint, Clitophon answers that the story was only half true, because although he did on the one hand criticise Socrates, he also on the other hand highly praised him. Then, he explains to Socrates why he must take such an ambiguous attitude towards him. In the first half of his speech he focuses on the aspect of Socratic teaching which he admires unreservedly, namely Socrates’ protreptic speech towards virtues. Here he refers to a lot of Socratic dicta which remind us of well known passages in the early dialogues of Plato. By contrast, in the latter half Clitophon explains where his deep frustration with Socrates lies. He says that, being already converted by Socratic protreptic and resolved to pursue virtues, what he expects now from Socrates is “what comes next”, that is a detailed account of the essence of virtues to be acquired and a piece of concrete advice on how to acquire them. But to these - Clitophon complains - neither Socrates’ company nor Socrates himself gives any convincing answer.
    [Show full text]
  • Faraone Ancient Greek Love Magic.Pdf
    Ancient Greek Love Magic Ancient Greek Love Magic Christopher A. Faraone Harvard University Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England Copyright © 1999 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Second printing, 2001 First Harvard University Press paperback edition, 2001 library of congress cataloging-in-publication data Faraone, Christopher A. Ancient Greek love magic / Christopher A. Faraone. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. ISBN 0-674-03320-5 (cloth) ISBN 0-674-00696-8 (pbk.) 1. Magic, Greek. 2. Love—Miscellanea—History. I. Title. BF1591.F37 1999 133.4Ј42Ј0938—dc21 99-10676 For Susan sê gfir Ãn seautá tfi f©rmaka Æxeiv (Plutarch Moralia 141c) Contents Preface ix 1 Introduction 1 1.1 The Ubiquity of Love Magic 5 1.2 Definitions and a New Taxonomy 15 1.3 The Advantages of a Synchronic and Comparative Approach 30 2 Spells for Inducing Uncontrollable Passion (Ero%s) 41 2.1 If ErÃs Is a Disease, Then Erotic Magic Is a Curse 43 2.2 Jason’s Iunx and the Greek Tradition of Ago%ge% Spells 55 2.3 Apples for Atalanta and Pomegranates for Persephone 69 2.4 The Transitory Violence of Greek Weddings and Erotic Magic 78 3 Spells for Inducing Affection (Philia) 96 3.1 Aphrodite’s Kestos Himas and Other Amuletic Love Charms 97 3.2 Deianeira’s Mistake: The Confusion of Love Potions and Poisons 110 3.3 Narcotics and Knotted Cords: The Subversive Cast of Philia Magic 119 4 Some Final Thoughts on History, Gender, and Desire 132 4.1 From Aphrodite to the Restless
    [Show full text]
  • THE TEMPLE PLUTARCH Rdlted by WHD ROUSE M
    THE TEMPLE PLUTARCH Rdlted by W. H. D. ROUSE M_ PLUTARCH'S LIVES '_ EI_3USHED BY 51R THOMAS NORTH INTEN VOLUMES VOI...TEN THE LIVES OF THE, NOBLE GREEKS AND ROMANS The most of them comparedtogether by that grave learned Philosopher and Historio- grapher Plutarch of Ch_ronea THE LIFE OF ARATUS Ca_tsx'_s the Philosopher (my friend Polycrates) A proverb being afraid as it seemeth of the evil sound of an corrected ancient proverb,not rightly as it was spoken, and in use, but as he thought it best, he wrote in this manner: What childrendo theirancestorscommend, But thosewhomfortunefavoursto the end? But Dionysodorus Trcezenian reproving him, doth rehearsethe proverbrightly as indeed it is : Whatchildrendo theirancestorscommend, Butthosewhoselifeis vertuousto the end? Saying,that this proverb stoppeth their mouthswho of themselves are unworthy of praise, and yet are still boning of the vertaes of their ancestors, whose praisethey highly extol. But beforethose that (as Pindarulsaith) : Domatchtheirnobleancestorsin prowessoftheirown, Andby theirfruits comme_athed stockwhencethey themsd,resaregrown. x A PLUTARCH'S LIVES The corn- (As thy self that conformest thy life unto the monweal examples and manners of thy vertuous ancestors:) of the it is no small good hap for them, often to remem- Sicy.oa- 1_n$ ber the noble deeds of their parents in hearing them spoken of, or otherwise for themselves oftentimes to remember some notable doings of their parents. For in them, it is not for lack of commendable vertues, that they report others' praise and glory : but in joining their own vertaes, to the vertues of their ancestors, they do increase their glory, as inheriting their vertuous life, a8 challenging their descent by blood.
    [Show full text]
  • Beauty on Display Plato and the Concept of the Kalon
    BEAUTY ON DISPLAY PLATO AND THE CONCEPT OF THE KALON JONATHAN FINE Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2018 © 2018 Jonathan Fine All rights reserved ABSTRACT BEAUTY ON DISPLAY: PLATO AND THE CONCEPT OF THE KALON JONATHAN FINE A central concept for Plato is the kalon – often translated as the beautiful, fine, admirable, or noble. This dissertation shows that only by prioritizing dimensions of beauty in the concept can we understand the nature, use, and insights of the kalon in Plato. The concept of the kalon organizes aspirations to appear and be admired as beautiful for one’s virtue. We may consider beauty superficial and concern for it vain – but what if it were also indispensable to living well? By analyzing how Plato uses the concept of the kalon to contest cultural practices of shame and honour regulated by ideals of beauty, we come to see not only the tensions within the concept but also how attractions to beauty steer, but can subvert, our attempts to live well. TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements ii 1 Coordinating the Kalon: A Critical Introduction 1 1 The Kalon and the Dominant Approach 2 2 A Conceptual Problem 10 3 Overview 24 2 Beauty, Shame, and the Appearance of Virtue 29 1 Our Ancient Contemporaries 29 2 The Cultural Imagination 34 3 Spirit and the Social Dimension of the Kalon 55 4 Before the Eyes of Others 82 3 Glory, Grief, and the Problem of Achilles 100 1 A Tragic Worldview 103 2 The Heroic Ideal 110 3 Disgracing Achilles 125 4 Putting Poikilia in its Place 135 1 Some Ambivalences 135 2 The Aesthetics of Poikilia 138 3 The Taste of Democracy 148 4 Lovers of Sights and Sounds 173 5 The Possibility of Wonder 182 5 The Guise of the Beautiful 188 1 A Psychological Distinction 190 2 From Disinterested Admiration to Agency 202 3 The Opacity of Love 212 4 Looking Good? 218 Bibliography 234 i ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS “To do philosophy is to explore one’s own temperament,” Iris Murdoch suggested at the outset of “Of ‘God’ and ‘Good’”.
    [Show full text]
  • Sorcerer's Apprentices
    Faculty & Research The Spirit of Despotism: Understanding the Tyrant Within by M. Kets de Vries 2004/17/ENT Working Paper Series The Spirit of Despotism: Understanding the Tyrant Within Manfred F. R. Kets de Vries* * Raoul de Vitry d’Avaucourt Clinical Professor of Leadership Development, INSEAD, France & Singapore. Director, INSEAD’s Global Leadership Centre. 1 Abstract The objective of this article is to better understand the developmental history of despotic regimes and the existence of leadership by terror. To gain greater insight into this phenomenon, the unusual relationship between leaders and followers in despotic regimes is explored, and the self-destructive cycle that characterizes such regimes is examined. The price paid in the form of human suffering and the breakdown of the moral fabric of a society is highlighted. In this article, particular attention is paid to highly intrusive totalitarian regimes. The levers used by such regimes to consolidate their power base are discussed in detail. The role of ideology, the enforcement of mind-control, the impact of the media, the inception of the illusion of solidarity, and the search for scapegoats are part of the review. Finally, suggestions are made on how to prevent despotic leaders from gaining a hold on power. Observations are made about the newly founded International Criminal Court, a permanent international judicial body that has been specially set up to try despotic rulers for genocide, crimes against humanity, and war crimes. KEY WORDS: Despotism; tyrant; leadership; totalitarianism; autocracy; tyranny; dictatorship; societal regression; democracy; paranoia; narcissism; scapegoat; ideology; mind-control; aggression; violence; sadism; terror; genocide; war; crimes against humanity; war criminal; International Criminal Court.
    [Show full text]
  • Royal Power, Law and Justice in Ancient Macedonia Joseph Roisman
    Royal Power, Law and Justice in Ancient Macedonia Joseph Roisman In his speech On the Crown Demosthenes often lionizes himself by suggesting that his actions and policy required him to overcome insurmountable obstacles. Thus he contrasts Athens’ weakness around 346 B.C.E. with Macedonia’s strength, and Philip’s II unlimited power with the more constrained and cumbersome decision-making process at home, before asserting that in spite of these difficulties he succeeded in forging later a large Greek coalition to confront Philip in the battle of Chaeronea (Dem.18.234–37). [F]irst, he (Philip) ruled in his own person as full sovereign over subservient people, which is the most important factor of all in waging war . he was flush with money, and he did whatever he wished. He did not announce his intentions in official decrees, did not deliberate in public, was not hauled into the courts by sycophants, was not prosecuted for moving illegal proposals, was not accountable to anyone. In short, he was ruler, commander, in control of everything.1 For his depiction of Philip’s authority Demosthenes looks less to Macedonia than to Athens, because what makes the king powerful in his speech is his freedom from democratic checks. Nevertheless, his observations on the Macedonian royal power is more informative and helpful than Aristotle’s references to it in his Politics, though modern historians tend to privilege the philosopher for what he says or even does not say on the subject. Aristotle’s seldom mentions Macedonian kings, and when he does it is for limited, exemplary purposes, lumping them with other kings who came to power through benefaction and public service, or who were assassinated by men they had insulted.2 Moreover, according to Aristotle, the extreme of tyranny is distinguished from ideal kingship (pambasilea) by the fact that tyranny is a government that is not called to account.
    [Show full text]
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Transantiquity
    TransAntiquity TransAntiquity explores transgender practices, in particular cross-dressing, and their literary and figurative representations in antiquity. It offers a ground-breaking study of cross-dressing, both the social practice and its conceptualization, and its interaction with normative prescriptions on gender and sexuality in the ancient Mediterranean world. Special attention is paid to the reactions of the societies of the time, the impact transgender practices had on individuals’ symbolic and social capital, as well as the reactions of institutionalized power and the juridical systems. The variety of subjects and approaches demonstrates just how complex and widespread “transgender dynamics” were in antiquity. Domitilla Campanile (PhD 1992) is Associate Professor of Roman History at the University of Pisa, Italy. Filippo Carlà-Uhink is Lecturer in Classics and Ancient History at the University of Exeter, UK. After studying in Turin and Udine, he worked as a lecturer at the University of Heidelberg, Germany, and as Assistant Professor for Cultural History of Antiquity at the University of Mainz, Germany. Margherita Facella is Associate Professor of Greek History at the University of Pisa, Italy. She was Visiting Associate Professor at Northwestern University, USA, and a Research Fellow of the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation at the University of Münster, Germany. Routledge monographs in classical studies Menander in Contexts Athens Transformed, 404–262 BC Edited by Alan H. Sommerstein From popular sovereignty to the dominion
    [Show full text]
  • Pt: Must Translate By: 2
    Solution to Challenge 3 Start by using the description of the MPSC cipher and Hint 1. We have: pt: m u s t Translate by: 2 3 4 5 CT: P Y X Z What this tells you: 1. If “m” was shifted two to the right to arrive at “p”, the “n” or “o” must be missing in between them. That means that “n” or “o” (but not both) appear in the keyword. This assumes that “m” isn’t in the keyword, but since it lies two letters from “p” it looks like it is in the normal alphabetical sequence. 2. One of “v”, “w”, or “x” must also be in the keyword. (The keyword is not “kryptos” !). Again, this assumes that “u” is not in the keyword. 3. Once again, since “s” is about 4 letters from “x” in the normal alphabet, we assume that “s” and “x” are not in the keyword but appearing in alphabetical order. This agrees nicely with #2: “v” or “w” is in the keyword AND “t” and “u” are NOT in the keyword (since we need these letters to keep “s” and “x” 4 letters apart. 4. If “v” or “w” is in the keyword, this makes “t” 5 letters from “z” if “y” and “z” are not in the keyword. Then end of the alphabet line looks like: … m (n o ) p… s t u (v w) x y z where parentheses were used to indicate groupings where one letter is missing (and appears earlier in the keyword). In order to make further progress, one might start guessing at possible two letter words that could reasonably precede “must”: “we” and “it” come to mind.
    [Show full text]
  • The Economic Foundations of Authoritarian Rule
    University of South Carolina Scholar Commons Theses and Dissertations 2017 The conomicE Foundations of Authoritarian Rule Clay Robert Fuller University of South Carolina Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Fuller, C. R.(2017). The Economic Foundations of Authoritarian Rule. (Doctoral dissertation). Retrieved from https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd/4202 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you by Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE ECONOMIC FOUNDATIONS OF AUTHORITARIAN RULE by Clay Robert Fuller Bachelor of Arts West Virginia State University, 2008 Master of Arts Texas State University, 2010 Master of Arts University of South Carolina, 2014 Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science College of Arts and Sciences University of South Carolina 2017 Accepted by: John Hsieh, Major Professor Harvey Starr, Committee Member Timothy Peterson, Committee Member Gerald McDermott, Committee Member Cheryl L. Addy, Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School © Copyright Clay Robert Fuller, 2017 All Rights Reserved. ii DEDICATION for Henry, Shannon, Mom & Dad iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Special thanks goes to God, the unconditional love and support of my wife, parents and extended family, my dissertation committee, Alex, the institutions of the United States of America, the State of South Carolina, the University of South Carolina, the Department of Political Science faculty and staff, the Walker Institute of International and Area Studies faculty and staff, the Center for Teaching Excellence, undergraduate political science majors at South Carolina who helped along the way, and the International Center on Nonviolent Conflict.
    [Show full text]
  • Law and the Metaethics of Discord
    Katja Maria Vogt, katjavogt.com, Columbia University 1 Law and the Metaethics of Discord, NYU Colloquium in Legal, Political, and Social Philosophy, Draft 08-2020 For: Special issue on the Normativity of Law, Ancient Philosophy Today: Dialogoi Law and the Metaethics of Discord Plato’s Euthyphro, I argue, lays out a metaethics that responds to persistent and unresolved value disagreement, and that is a genuine contender for us today. With this proposal, I reject centuries of scholarship, not to speak of countless anthologies and syllabi in ethics and the philosophy of law.1 The Euthyphro begins with three cases of unresolved value disagreement. These cases are to be adjudicated by the law, which turns out to be difficult. Today if an author starts with three examples, we expect that the subsequent text is going to address them. This, I submit, is the structure of the Euthyphro. Against my reading, discussions of the Euthyphro tend to focus almost exclusively on a brief section in which Plato discusses what is now known as the Euthyphro Problem. Socrates asks whether the gods love the pious because it is pious, or whether the pious is pious because it is loved by the gods. In the idiom of contemporary metaethics, the puzzle may seem to be this: is value attitude-independent or is value conferred by attitudes?2 Alternatively, in the idiom of traditional Divine Command Theory, do the gods —or, does God, since Divine Command Theory tends to be monotheistic—recognize value, or is value conferred by divine approval?3 1 Much of the literature on the Euthyphro focuses on two out of fifteen pages of the dialogue, where the so- called Euthyphro Problem is discussed.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms
    Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms Plato's theory of Forms or theory of Ideas[1] [2] [3] asserts that non-material abstract (but substantial) forms (or ideas), and not the material world of change known to us through sensation, possess the highest and most fundamental kind of reality.[4] When used in this sense, the word form is often capitalized.[5] Plato speaks of these entities only through the characters (primarily Socrates) of his dialogues who sometimes suggest that these Forms are the only true objects of study that can provide us with genuine knowledge; thus even apart from the very controversial status of the theory, Plato's own views are much in doubt.[6] Plato spoke of Forms in formulating a possible solution to the problem of universals. Forms Terminology: the Forms and the forms The English word "form" may be used to translate two distinct concepts that concerned Plato—the outward "form" or appearance of something, and "Form" in a new, technical nature, that never ...assumes a form like that of any of the things which enter into her; ... But the forms which enter into and go out of her are the likenesses of real existences modelled after their patterns in a wonderful and inexplicable manner.... The objects that are seen, according to Plato, are not real, but literally mimic the real Forms. In the allegory of the cave expressed in Republic, the things that are ordinarily perceived in the world are characterized as shadows of the real things, which are not perceived directly. That which the observer understands when he views the world mimics the archetypes of the many types and properties (that is, of universals) of things observed.
    [Show full text]