POLITICAL REALISM in APOCALYPTIC TIMES a Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in P

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

POLITICAL REALISM in APOCALYPTIC TIMES a Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in P POLITICAL REALISM IN APOCALYPTIC TIMES A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Alison Elizabeth Jennifer McQueen January 2012 © 2012 Alison Elizabeth Jennifer McQueen POLITICAL REALISM IN APOCALYPTIC TIMES Alison Elizabeth Jennifer McQueen, Ph. D. Cornell University 2012 This dissertation traces the responses of three canonical political realists—Niccolò Machiavelli, Thomas Hobbes, and Hans Morgenthau—to eruptions of apocalyptic rhetoric, imagery, and politics. I treat apocalypticism as a very particular kind of utopianism that is premised on a belief in the imminent end of the known world and the arrival of a radically new future. Contemporary realists tend to position their pragmatic approaches to politics against ‘utopian’ alternatives, which they reject for being at best unrealizable and at worst profoundly dangerous. However, in tracing the historical engagement between political realism and apocalypticism, I find a more complex and productive relationship. Through an historical and textual analysis of the work of Machiavelli, Hobbes, and Morgenthau, I argue that much of the nuance and texture in these realists’ work, and particularly their evolving conceptions of human nature and their commitments to political action, emerge from serious and extended engagements with apocalypticism. ii BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH Alison McQueen was born in Toronto, Ontario, Canada. She completed her secondary education at the Linden School in Toronto. She received her BA (with distinction) in International Development from the University of Guelph in 2003, her MA in Political Science and International Relations from the University of Toronto in 2005, and her PhD in Government from Cornell University in 2012. She is an Assistant Professor in the Department of Political Science at Stanford University. iii For my parents, David McQueen and Nancy McQueen, and in memory of my aunt, Jennifer McQueen iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS As is the case with any piece of scholarship, this dissertation was in many ways a collective endeavor. It originally took shape as a loose series of observations about Machiavelli and Hobbes. Susan Buck-Morss first encouraged me to think about extending these observations to Morgenthau, pushing me in a more ambitious and exciting direction. In her capacity as the chair of my dissertation committee, Susan consistently helped me to see the project with new eyes, to find the strange in the familiar, and to take seriously the way in which images do important political theoretical work. Peter Katzenstein brought his sharp critical eye and wide- ranging intellect to every part of this project. And, as he has done for so many, Peter modeled what it means to be a serious and generous scholar and teacher. It was in a class with John Najemy that I first began to formulate my ideas on Machiavelli and the reading I offer in this dissertation owes much to these early conversations, as well as to John’s own wonderful work on Machiavelli and Renaissance Florence. The dissertation as a whole has also benefited from John’s rare combination of a breadth of vision and an eye for detail. I must acknowledge a special debt to Jason Frank. Had it not been for several seminars and many conversations with Jason, I would not have realized that I was a political theorist. He consistently saw more in this project than I knew was there. When I would turn to Jason in frustration, he would send me back to the dissertation with a renewed sense of enthusiasm. One could not ask for more. Isaac Kramnick read early drafts of the Hobbes and Machiavelli chapters and generously agreed to read the entire dissertation in his capacity as external reader. Beyond his valuable feedback on the dissertation, I am grateful for having had the opportunity to be a teaching assistant for numerous offerings of Isaac’s introductory political thought course. It is from him that I learned how one does the history of political thought. v Many other people read and commented on one or more chapters of this dissertation. They include: Dwight Allman, Richard Bensel, Peter Breiner, Allen Carlson, Matthew Evangelista, Giovanni Giorgini, Joshua Goldstein, Benjamin Gregg, Randal Hendrickson, Al Martinich, and Travis Smith. Each of the core chapters of the dissertation was presented at a colloquium, workshop, or conference. I would like to thank the organizers and audiences at Cornell’s Political Theory Workshop and Dissertation Colloquia, the University of Texas at Austin, and at the annual meetings of the American Political Science Association, the Association for Political Theory, the Canadian Political Science Association, and the Midwest Political Science Association. This project received financial support from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, the Cornell School of Graduate Studies, and the Einaudi Center for International Studies. Burke Hendrix has seen me through the highs and lows of this dissertation. At every stage, the project benefited from his encouragement, questions, and gentle requests for clarification. Most of all, however, I appreciate the many ways in which Burke helped me to see the humor in an often gloomy subject. My greatest debt is to my parents, to whom this dissertation is dedicated. They first nurtured the skills required for scholarly work—reading, writing, and asking questions (not necessarily in that order). My aunt Jennifer, who died during the final stages of this project, supported and encouraged me throughout my graduate work. She was proof that it is possible to be a compassionate realist. vi TABLE OF CONTENTS 1 Introduction 1 2 Theorizing Apocalypse: Context to Concept 24 3 Niccolò Machiavelli’s Savonarolan Moment 77 4 Thomas Hobbes: “Feigning the World to be Annihilated” 127 5 Hans Morgenthau and the Postwar Apocalyptic Imaginary 187 6 Conclusion: On the Art of Living Through Catastrophe 242 Bibliography 253 vii LIST OF FIGURES 1 Botticelli, Mystic Nativity (1500-1) 95 2 Botticelli, Crucifixion (1497-8) 96 3 Luca Signorelli, Apocalypse Sequence (1499-1502) 98 4 Luca Signorelli, Apocalypse Sequence (1499-1502) 99 5 ‘C’ Illustration, John Foxe’s Acts and Monuments (1653) 134 6 Frontispiece, Thomas Hobbes’ Leviathan (1651) 176 7 Anthony Van Dyck, King Charles I (ca. 1635) 179 8 Anthony Van Dyck, Charles I, King of England (1636) 180 9 Anthony Van Dyck, Christ Healing the Paralytic (1619) 181 10 Gislebertus, The Last Judgment (1130-1135) 182 viii CHAPTER ONE INTRODUCTION [W]hen we get to May 21 on the calendar in any city or country in the world, and the clock says about — this is based on other verses in the Bible — when the clock says about 6 p.m., there’s going to be this tremendous earthquake that’s going to make the last earthquake in Japan seem like nothing in comparison. And the whole world will be alerted that Judgment Day has begun. Harold Camping, Interview, May 11, 2011 For a half a century, America defended our own freedom by standing watch on distant borders. After the shipwreck of communism came years of relative quiet, years of repose, years of sabbatical. And then there came a day of fire…By our efforts we have lit a fire as well—a fire in the minds of men. It warms those who feel its power; it burns those who fight its progress. And one day this untamed fire of freedom will reach the darkest corners of our world. President George W. Bush, Second Inaugural Address, 2005 [T]he evidence coming in from the watchers around the world brings news of an imminent shift in our climate towards one that could easily be described as Hell: so hot, so deadly that only a handful of the teeming billions now alive will survive. James Lovelock, The Revenge of Gaia: Earth’s Climate Crisis and the Fate of Humanity, 2006 In the months and days leading up to May 21, 2011, civil engineer turned radio evangelist Harold Camping preached an apocalyptic message of hope and despair. A cross-country billboard campaign urged Americans to “Save the Date!” and announced the “Return of Christ. May 21, 2011.” On this day, the faithful would be taken up to heaven in the rapture. From the safety of their heavenly perches, they would look down as a wave of divine destruction wrapped its way around the globe, consuming the world and massacring the unfaithful. Fires, wars, and plagues of the kinds described in the book of Revelation would ravage the earth for five months, 1 killing millions each day. With these predictions, Camping offered his followers a vision of the apocalypse—the imminent end of the known world and the beginning of a radically new future. When May 21 came and went without incident, Camping and his followers, some of who had quit their jobs and disposed of their assets, were widely ridiculed.1 Behind much of this ridicule was a sense that Camping and his followers were exactly what many of us expect an apocalyptic group to be—marginal, religious, and ultimately wrong. These preconceptions are often reinforced by media portrayals of apocalyptic groups. Many of us imagine a band of vulnerable people who, under the direction of a charismatic false prophet, have gathered in a rural bunker to await the imminent end of the known world. We imagine groups who have chosen to cut themselves off from mainstream society and to pursue their apocalyptic expectations to a violent consummation. Some of the most prominent cases of apocalyptic belief seem to fit this mold. For instance, the mass suicide of more than 900 members of the Peoples Temple at Jonestown, Guyana in 1978 was motivated in part by this group’s apocalyptic expectations. The Branch Davidians, a group of whom were involved in a protracted armed standoff with the FBI outside of Waco, Texas in 1993, were similarly motivated by expectations of an imminent end.
Recommended publications
  • A Commentary on the Book of by Harry
    A JOURNAL OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY May & Sept. 1984 Volume 12 Numbers 2 & 3 141 Robert Sacks The Lion and the Ass: a Commentary on the Book of Genesis (Chapters 44-50) 193 Kent Moors Justice and Philosophy in Plato's Republic: the Nature of a Definition 225 Mario Lewis, Jr. An Interpretation of Plato's Euthyphro (Introduction; Part I, Sections 1-3) 261 Jack D'Amico The Virtii of Women: Machiavelli's Mandragola and Clizia 275 Jim MacAdam Rousseau's Contract with and without his Inequality 287 David Boucher The Denial of Perennial Problems: the Negative Side of Quentin Skinner's Theory 301 David Schaefer Libertarianism and Political Philosophy: a Critique of Robert Nozick's Anarchy, State, and Utopia Discussion 335 Laurence Berns Spiritedness in Ethics and Politics: a Study in Aristotelian Psychology 349 Ernest Fortin Rational Theologians and Irrational Philosophers: a Straussian Perspective 357 Stanley Corngold & Michael Jennings Walter Benjamin / Gershom Scholem 367 Charles M. Sherover The Political Implications of Heidegger's Being and Heidegger' Time" Time: on s "Being and and the Possibility of Political Philosophy by Mark Blitz 381 Mark Blitz Response to Sherover Book Review 387 Will Morrisey Algeny by Jeremy Rifkin Short Notices 391 Will Morrisey How Democratic is the Constitution? and How Capitalistic is the Constitution? edited by Robert A. Goldwin & William A. Schambra; Statesmanship: Essays in Honor of Sir Winston S. Churchill edited by Harry V. Jaffa; Winston Churchill's World View by Kenneth W. Thompson; Richard Hooker and the Politics of a Christian England by Robert K. Faulkner; Education and Culture in the Political Thought of Aristotle by Carnes Lord; Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: the Discourses on Livy by Harvey C.
    [Show full text]
  • Machiavelli's Public Conspiracies
    MediaTropes eJournal Vol II, No 1 (2009): 60–83 ISSN 1913-6005 MACHIAVELLI’S PUBLIC CONSPIRACIES JAMES MARTEL When it comes to his treatment of political conspiracies, Machiavelli can seem indifferent to whether his advice serves princes or subjects, or both. In the beginning of his chapter “Of Conspiracies” in the Discourses, he writes: It seems to me proper now to treat of conspiracies, being a matter of so much danger both to princes and subjects; for history teaches us that many more princes have lost their lives and their states by conspiracies than by open war. But few can venture to make open war upon their sovereign, whilst every one may engage in conspiracies against him. On the other hand, subjects cannot undertake more perilous and foolhardy enterprises than conspiracies, which are in every respect more difficult and dangerous; and thence it is that, although so often attempted, yet they so rarely attain the desired object. And therefore, so that princes may learn to guard against such dangers, and that subjects may less rashly engage in them, and learn rather to live contentedly under such a government as Fate may have assigned to them … I shall treat the subject at length, and endeavor not to omit any point that may be useful to the one or the other. 1 1 Niccolò Machiavelli, The Prince and the Discourses (New York: The Modern Library, 1950), p. 410. Cited henceforth as either The Prince or The Discourses. All translations from this edition, although at times I supply the Italian when it is useful.
    [Show full text]
  • Machiavelli's La Umana Commedia
    Akira Murata: Machiavelli’s La Umana Commedia Political Philosophy No.24 Machiavelli’s La Umana Commedia: key thoughts on understanding his major political works Akira Murata* Abstract: This paper clarifies the originality of Machiavelli’s political philosophy, explaining Th e P rince and Discourses on Livy in the context of his comedies Mandragola and Clizia. Tw o comedies are characterized by the optimistic vision of human affairs, i.e., the vision of human comedy (umana commedia). The vision of human comedy expressed in Machiavelli’s comedies is based on two principles: the first is the consideration of motion or change as superior to standstill, and the second involves the idea that new things trump old things – that is, youth triumphs over the aged. The vision incorporates the optimistic belief that, relying on these principles, a happy grand finale can be achieved in this world, solely through human free w ill (libero arbitrio). The p o lit ical philosophy of Machiavelli took on matchless originality by injecting the prospect of human comedy into the gravest subjects of the public sphere. 1. The originality of Machiavelli Adequate comprehension of Machiavelli’s comedies Mandragola and Clizia underlies a proper grasp of the originality behind his political philosophy. Researchers have made efforts to explain the originality of Machiavelli, i.e., his departure from the traditions of classical antiquity and Biblical religion, as observed in The Prince and Discourses on Livy (Berlin, 1979, pp. 33 – 49). However, these efforts have often been thwarted by the fact that Machiavelli regarded himself not only as the founder of “new modes and orders” (modi ed ordini nuovi) but also as an optimal follower o f the tradition of classical antiquity (D., I, proemio [I, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Niccolò Machiavelli. a Paradoxical Success
    Niccolò Machiavelli. A Paradoxical Success Robert Black Niccolò Machiavelli (1469-1527) is history’s most startling and influential political commentator. The Prince is the world’s most famous (and infamous) work of political theory. 1 The Discourses on Livy are the cornerstone of modern republican thought. 2 Mandragola is the greatest play written in the Italian language.3 The Florentine Histories constituted the first successful neo- classical humanist history in Italian rather than Latin.4 In Machiavelli’s day, Aristotle was the most famous political thinker; in our time, it is Machiavelli.5 In the sixteenth century, more than two hundred printed editions of his writings were published, a further hundred in the next century, and in the eighteenth more than a hundred and seventy.6 Just as today Freud and Marx are universal common currency, so was Machiavelli during the Renaissance.7 In the first century after his death he had his advocates (for example Jean Bodin, who ‘praised him as an exemplary reader of history’,8 and Francis Bacon, who argued ‘that Machiavelli proposed a new intellectual instrument or weapon well adapted to (...) politics’9) but for the most part he was known as the wicked ‘Machiavel’, the godless champion of evil. 10 Machiavelli’s champions praised his realistic vision of politics, whereas his critics condemned his amoral separation of politics from ethics. 1 Niccolò Machiavelli, Il principe, G. Inglese ed. (Turin 2013). 2 Niccolò Machiavelli, Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio, F. Bausi ed. (Rome 2001). 3 Niccolò Machiavelli, La Mandragola. Storia e filologia, P.
    [Show full text]
  • The Question of Esoteric Writing in Machiavelli's Works
    The Question of Esoteric Writing in Machiavelli’s Works rasoul namazi Leo Strauss Center, University of Chicago The question addressed by this article is whether esotericism or secret teachings exist in Machiavelli’s writings. This question has been a major point of contention between the commentators of Machiavelli, with many denying the existence of esoteric teaching in the Machiavellian corpus. This article will explore the controversy by studying Machiavelli’s own works, and on this basis it will be contended that there are many references and elements present in Machiavelli’s works that justify an esoteric interpretation. Consequently, it is reasonable to assume that Machiavelli has esoteric intentions that are different from the surface meaning of his texts. It is therefore necessary for commentators to go beyond the surface of his writings to uncover his deeper teachings. Cet article se penche sur la question de la présence d’éléments ésotériques ou d’enseignements secrets dans l’œuvre de Machiavel. Le sujet est un point de désaccord important parmi les commentateurs de l’œuvre de Machiavel, puisque plusieurs nient l’existence d’un tel enseignement. L'article explore cette controverse en examinant l’œuvre de Machiavel, pour ensuite montrer qu’il s’y trouve plusieurs références et éléments justifiant une interprétation ésotérique. En conséquence, il est vraisemblable que Machiavel ait eu des intentions ésotériques différentes du propos apparent de ses écrits. Il s’avère donc nécessaire que les commentateurs aillent plus loin que la surface de son œuvre afin de découvrir ses enseignements cachés. ny commentator who begins the study of Niccolò Machiavelli will be Asurprised by the number of works written on his thought.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cambridge Companion to Machiavelli Edited by John M
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-67846-9 - The Cambridge Companion to Machiavelli Edited by John M. Najemy Frontmatter More information the cambridge companion to machiavelli Niccolò Machiavelli (1469–1527) is the most famous and controversial figure in the history of political thought and one of the iconic names of the Renaissance. The Cambridge Companion to Machiavelli brings together sixteen original essays by leading experts, covering his life, his career in Florentine government, his reaction to the dramatic changes that affected Florence and Italy in his lifetime, and the most prominent themes of his thought, including the founding, evolution, and corruption of republics and principalities, class conflict, liberty, arms, reli- gion, ethics, rhetoric, gender, and the Renaissance dialogue with antiquity. In his own time Machiavelli was recognized as an original thinker who provocatively challenged conventional wisdom. With penetrating analyses of The Prince, Discourses on Livy, Art of War, Florentine Histories, and his plays and poetry, this book offers a vivid portrait of this extraordinary thinker as well as assess- ments of his place in Western thought since the Renaissance. john m. najemy is Professor of History at Cornell University. His previous work includes Corporatism and Consensus in Florentine Electoral Politics, 1280– 1400 (1982), Between Friends: Discourses of Power and Desire in the Machiavelli–Vettori Letters of 1513–1515 (1993), A History of Florence, 1200–1575 (2006) and essays on Machiavelli and Renaissance political thought. A complete list of books in the series is at the back of this book © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-67846-9 - The Cambridge Companion to Machiavelli Edited by John M.
    [Show full text]
  • UNIVERSITY of CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO the Recovery of Virtù
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO The Recovery of Virtù: Imitation and Political Practices in the Works of Niccolò Machiavelli A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction for the requirements of the degree Doctor in Philosophy in Political Science by Aaron Cotkin Committee in Charge: Professor Tracy B Strong, Chair Professor Harvey Goldman, Co-Chair Professor Fonna Forman Professor Marcel Hénaff Professor Peter Stacey 2017 Copyright Aaron Cotkin, 2017 All rights reserved The Dissertation of Aaron Cotkin is approved, and it is acceptable in quality and form for publication on microfilm and electronically: _____________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________ Co-Chair _____________________________________________________________________ Chair University of California, San Diego 2017 iii DEDICATION This is dedicated to my father, Spencer Cotkin, in recognition of his constant support, encouragement, and enthusiasm for my academic pursuits. Thank you, Dad! iv EPIGRAPH How different practice is from theory! Many are those who understand things well, who either do not remember them or do not know how to put them into action! And they who do that, their intelligence is useless; because it is like having a treasure stored in an ark with the obligation that it can never be taken out. Francesco Guicciardini v TABLE OF CONTENTS Signature Page………………………………………………………………………...iii Dedication……………………………………………………………………………..iv
    [Show full text]
  • “Vox Populi”: Machiavelli, Opinione, and the Popolo, from Il Principe to the Istorie Fiorentine”*
    “Vox Populi”: Machiavelli, Opinione, and the Popolo, from Il Principe to the Istorie Fiorentine”* Albert Russell Ascoli Ma quanto alla prudenzia ed alla stabilità, dico, come un popolo è più prudente, più stabile e di migliore giudizio che un principe. E non sanza cagione si assomiglia la voce d'un popolo a quella di Dio: perché si vede una opinione universale fare effetti maravigliosi ne' pronostichi suoi; talché pare che per occulta virtù ei prevegga il suo male ed il suo bene. (Discorsi I.58)1 In a famous passage from the dedicatory letter to the Principe, which we will analyze in detail shortly, Machiavelli paradoxically authorizes himself as an expert concerning the high and the mighty by claiming to speak with “the voice of the people.” On the face of it the Principe contains one lesson after another in how a “virtuous” leader can manipulate and control the populace to his own ends. On the other hand, from shortly after the composition of the treatise, readers have asserted that Machiavelli is secretly, ironically, allegorically, expressing opinions that place him on the side of the “popolo” against the repressive regimes of such as Cesare Borgia and Julius II. Rather than taking sides in this still unresolved, and perhaps unresolvable, debate, I will argue here that the Principe, in the letter to Lorenzo and throughout, delineates the problematic nature of Machiavelli’s relationship to the “people”—and with it the unstable contours of his “subject position” as opinionated commentator on politics and history—posing questions which will continue to haunt his writings from the near contemporary Discorsi to his final masterpiece, the Istorie Fiorentine.
    [Show full text]
  • Poetics and Politics
    Poetics and Politics Unauthenticated Download Date | 9/7/18 2:19 PM Unauthenticated Download Date | 9/7/18 2:19 PM Poetics and Politics Net Structures and Agencies in Early Modern Drama Edited by Toni Bernhart, Jaša Drnovšek, Sven Thorsten Kilian, Joachim Küpper, Jan Mosch Unauthenticated Download Date | 9/7/18 2:19 PM This book is published in cooperation with the project DramaNet, funded by the European Research Council ISBN 978-3-11-053665-2 e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-053669-0 e-ISBN (EPUB) 978-3-11-060352-1 This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 4.0 License. For details go to http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Control Number: 2018017860 Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2018 Toni Bernhart, Jaša Drnovšek, Sven Thorsten Kilian, Joachim Küpper, Jan Mosch, published by Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston Typesetting: Meta Systems Publishing & Printservices GmbH, Wustermark Printing and binding: CPI books GmbH, Leck Cover illustration: photodeedooo/iStock/Thinkstock www.degruyter.com Unauthenticated Download Date | 9/7/18 2:19 PM Acknowledgements This book is a collection of papers presented at an international conference at Freie Universität Berlin on 29–30 April 2015. Bringing together experts of early modern drama and music, the event was a wonderful example of transnational and interdisciplinary collaboration in the academy. We would like to thank everybody who participated for the insightful talks and stimulating discussions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Machiavellian Reformation. an Essay in Political Theory Jyväskylä: University of Jyväskylä 2006, 171 P
    JYVÄSKYLÄ STUDIES IN EDUCATION, PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL RESEARCH 290 Paul-Erik Korvela The Machiavellian Reformation An Essay in Political Theory JYVÄSKYLÄN YLIOPISTO Copyright © , by University of Jyväskylä ABSTRACT Korvela, Paul-Erik The Machiavellian Reformation. An Essay in Political Theory Jyväskylä: University of Jyväskylä 2006, 171 p. (Jyväskylä Studies in Education, Psychology and Social Research ISSN 0075-4625; 290) ISBN 951-39-2666-4 Diss. The study explores Niccolò Machiavelli’s (1469-1527) views on Christianity. The question of Machiavelli’s relation to religion in general and to Christianity in particular has aroused much discussion. Most commonly he is seen as some sort of neo-Pagan aiming to paganise rather than secularise or reform Christianity. In previous research, his opposition to Christianity often has been assumed but seldom clarified. The view that Machiavelli was simply an advocate of paganism against Christianity is inaccurate. Machiavelli criticised Christianity, but this does not mean that he was an anti- Christian or an anti-religious thinker. He thought that religion should be used like the ancients used it, but he does not demand that the religion in question should be the same as the ancients had. Thus, he was not attempting any kind of resurrection of paganism. As is commonly known, Machiavelli harked back to ancient Rome and its practices. The same methods were not used in his time, he thought, because Christianity had already carved men into its liking and made them effeminate and contemplative rather than virtuous and active. But Machiavelli did not claim that it would be better for a society to get rid of religion altogether.
    [Show full text]