Richard Wollheim's Freud, and Philip Rieff's Freud: the Mind of the Moralist

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Richard Wollheim's Freud, and Philip Rieff's Freud: the Mind of the Moralist Notes PREFACE 1. Two other books on Freud have provided continual stimulation: Richard Wollheim's Freud, and Philip Rieff's Freud: The Mind of the Moralist. 2. Very similar ground to that covered in the latter part of Chapter 2 is covered in Laffal (1964) and Marshall (1974). There are a large number of commentaries that discuss the last section in Freud's paper on 'The Unconscious' ( 1915e) where he linked consciousness to word-presentations and unconsciousness to thing-presentations. Some of these are cited in the bibliography. A number of papers by Otto Marx have proved invaluable, especially his paper on aphasia and linguistic theory in the nineteenth century, discussed in Chapter 5. Litowitz and Litowitz (1977) attempt to relate Freudian theory to contemporary (Chomskyean) linguistics; they also include a very useful review of the historical relations between psychoanalysis and linguistics, although their interests do not overlap very much with my own. 3. The most significant contributions to the history of psychoanalysis in recent years have come from the pen of Michel Foucault, despite the fact that, as he admits, he has never directly addressed the question of its history, all the illuminating remarks he has made appearing as asides within works that have other concerns. But it is clear that, from his earliest writings on- in particular the 'Introduction' to the French translation of Ludwig Binswanger's Le reve et /'existence (1954) esp. pp. 20-7, 75-80- he has been concerned with the 'historico-conceptual' place of psychoanalysis. Despite this concern, he has never dealt with psychoanalysis face on. But, in a series of works, L 'Histoire de Ia Folie, Les Mots et les Choses, arrd the more recent La volonte de savoir, his 'contributions' to the history of psychoanaly­ sis have nothing less than revolutionary implications. These implications are of wider significance than can be dealt with here, and I refer the reader to my article, 'Michel Foucault and the History of Psychoanalysis', forthcoming in History of Science. But let us just note briefly two implications ofFoucault's work: firstly, that the possibility of psychoanaly­ sis was intimately related to the employment of the model derived from the philological sciences in the nineteenth century. We will discuss and expand upon this notion at some length in Chapter 5. Secondly, Foucault points out that the 'discourse on sexuality' is not peculiar to psychoanalysis. Rather, it should be seen as part of a more broad-ranging compulsion to confess the secret of secrets, a compulsion that has its roots in the religious tradition of spiritual regulation and the bourgeois system of social control via the construction of fields of technical expertise, fields of esoteric know!- 213 214 Language and the Origins of Psychoanalysis edge. What these two difl"erent arguments lead one to ponder are the follow­ ing: (i) The techniques of interpretation and of hermeneutic analysis are not original or specific to psychoanalysis, whose main claim to 'originality' might reside in a purification of these philological techniques and their generalization to new areas, in particular to the areas previously under the domination of a medico-biological model of disease; in other words the originality of psychoanalysis must be seen in its application to the expressive, significative or semantic modes of the body. (ii) If the idea that sexuality is somehow hidden, unspoken, crying out to be spoken, if this idea is found to have a history that stretches back to the mid eighteenth century, then the key feature of the interpretative machine that psychoanalysis sets in motion, namely, the discovery of the meaningful that is also sexual, and in some sense primary, this feature is revealed to be simply a crystallization of tendencies that doctors, teachers and moral leaders of one sort or another had been working towards for the century that precedes the moment when Freud found himself confronted by the sexual pantomime-show for which Charcot was the impresario. To put the arguments somewhat differently, Foucault's first argument, from The Order of Things, will make of The Interpretation of Dreams an original synthesis of the categories of possible knowledge available to the human sciences in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, without finding there anything more than an inversion of concepts that had served to furnish out the sciences of ethnology, philology and mythology throughout the nineteenth century. Foucault's second argument, from La volonte de savoir, will make of the Three Essays on Sexuality nothing more than a codification - and perhaps a neutralization- of the discourses on perverse and abnormal sexuality that the institutions of organized and scientific sexual confession had progressively revealed and created from the eighteenth century on. The cogency and validity of these historical theses is still in question and require much further debate and research. But it is clear that these are the most challenging historical hypotheses on the history of psychoanalysis since Freud wrote 'On the history of the psychoanalytical movement'. (See also the debate between members of the Ecole Freudienne and Foucault, which took place shortly after the publication of La volonte de savoir in Ornicar?, 10, 1977, esp. pp. 76fT.) CHAPTER I I. One of the names that Anna 0., Breuer's first patient, gave to the method she had created (Breuer and Freud (1895d) SE II 30). She employed the English words, since, at that point in the course of her neurosis, she could not speak German. 2. From the beginning of his psychoanalytic work, Freud detached himself from two doctrines, obviously related to each other, that we can call Notes 215 'physicalism' and 'organicism'. The first had a more philosophical sense, namely, the prescription that all possible medically explanatory entities had a physical reference, a scientific examination of the other side of the implicit dualism being either fruitless, impossible or, allowing of a complete translation into scientific languages which included no reference to 'mind'. In 1890, Freud had noted the finding that 'in some at least of these (nervous) patients the signs of their illness originate from nothing other than a change in the action of their minds upon their bodies and that the immediate cause of their disorder is to be looked for in their minds. What may be the remoter causes of the disturbance which affects their minds is another question, with which we need not now concern ourselves'. ((1890a) SE VII 286), and the continual postponement of any approach to a physicalist reduction of 'the action of the mind' throughout psychoanalytic writings is a witness to the irrelevance of recourse to physical explanations. Apart from a short flirtation with psychophysical parallelism, Freud was an unrepentant and rather old-fashioned dualist in his theory and in his practice, if not on every occasion when pressed to give an opinion concerning the final causes of the phenomena that psychoanalysis discovered. As to organicism, this doctrine had a more specifically medical flavour, being the general term to cover those theories of 'disease' that presumed to find the explanatory entities in the bodily organs. There was thus an emphasis on the spatial locality of the causes. We might, indeed, contrast physicalism and organicism on this point: physicalist theories were not necessarily concerned with the actual locus of a disease. For many physicalists, to speak of 'nervous fibres' or even Jackson's 'nervous arrangements' would qualify a theory as physicalist. But an organicist would search for specific loci: the search for the specific cerebral artery whose anaemia or hyperaemia had caused a certain disturbance of the mental faculties would be a typically organicist project. In this sense, Freud had renounced organicism in psychology by the time he published On Aphasia but was still prepared to embark upon a physicalist programme in the Project, even if the units of'matter in motion' soon got squeezed out of what became an essentially non-reductionist account. 3. See, for instance, Freud(l900a) SE IV 18ln; SE V 553, 562-4,594-6,604- 5. Cf. Steinbach (1953). 4. The best general account of the history of physiology touching on the reductionism of the late nineteenth century is Rothschuh (1953, 1973), although the classic Lange, vol. III (1865, 1925) and the unsurpassed Merz (1904-12) are more thought-provoking. More specifically, the works of Amacher, Bernfeld, Cranefield, Gode-von-Aesch, Riese, Stengel, Young give the background to what Bernfeld called the 'school of Helmholtz', which Cranefield renamed 'the biophysics movement'. Jones, vol. I is accurate, although limited by the form of the biography. On Vienna in particular, see Lesky ( 1965), and Hoff and Seitelberger ( 1952). For the place ofmedicinein Austrian culture the best source is Johnston (all cited in full in bibliography). 5. For Breuer's early work, see Cranefield (1958, 1972). For Freud's early work as a pathologist, Amacher (1965), Andersson (1962), Brautigam (1960) Brun (1936), Dorer (1932), Ellenberger (1970), Galdston (1956), 216 Language and the Origins of Psychoanalysis Jones (1953), Konig (1962), Lebzeltern (1973), Levin (1974), Rosen (1972), Spehlman (1953), Stewart (1969). 6. For instance, the 'cure' achieved by Zoe in Jensen's Gradiva consisted in her helping Hanold to recognize that he had displaced his love from Zoe Bertgang to the Pompeian Gradiva. '[The analyst] brings about something like what Norbert Hanold grasped at the end of the story when he translated back the name "Gradiva" into "Bertgang" [both mean 'who steps along brilliantly']. The disorder vanishes while being traced back to its origin; analysis, too, brings simultaneous cure.' (Freud (1907a) SE IX 89). 7. There is no comprehensive account of theories of nervous diseases in the nineteenth century. My work is drawn from those partial accounts that do exist, mainly focused on theories of hysteria, such as Abricossoff(l897-8), Ellenberger (1970, p.
Recommended publications
  • V O L N E Y P. G a Y R E a D I N G F R E U D
    VOLNEY P. GAY READING FREUD Psychology, Neurosis, and Religion READING FREUD READING FREUD %R American Academy of Religion Studies in Religion Charley Hardwick and James O. Duke, Editors Number 32 READING FREUD Psychology, Neurosis, and Religion by Volney P. Gay READING FREUD Psychology, Neurosis, and Religion VOLNEY P. GAY Scholars Press Chico, California READING FREUD Psychology, Neurosis, and Religion by Volney P. Gay ©1983 American Academy of Religion Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Gay, Volney Patrick. Reading Freud. (Studies in religion / American Academy of Religion ; no. 32) 1. Psychoanalysis and religion. 2. Freud, Sigmund, 1856-1939. 3. Religion—Controversial literature—History. I. Title. II. Series: Studies in Religion (American Academy of Religion) ; no. 32. BF175.G38 1983 200\1'9 83-2917 ISBN 0-89130-613-7 Printed in the United States of America for Barbara CONTENTS Acknowledgments viii Introduction ix Why Study Freud? Freud and the Love of Truth The Goals of This Book What This Book Will Not Do How to Use This Book References and Texts I Freud's Lectures on Psychoanalysis 1 Five Lectures on Psycho-analysis (SE 11) 1909 Introductory Lectures on Psycho-analysis (SE 15 & 16) 1915-16 II On the Reality of Psychic Pain: Three Case Histories 41 Fragment of an Analysis of a Case of Hysteria (SE 7) 1905 "Dora" Notes Upon a Case of Obsessional Neurosis (SE 10) 1909 "Rat Man" From the History of an Infantile Neurosis (SE 17) 1918 "Wolf Man" III The Critique of Religion 69 "The Uncanny" (SE 17) 1919 Totem and Taboo (SE 13) 1912-13 Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego (SE 18) 1921 The Future of an Illusion (SE 21) 1927 Moses and Monotheism (SE 23) 1939 References Ill Index 121 Acknowledgments I thank Charley Hardwick and an anonymous reviewer, Peter Homans (University of Chicago), Liston Mills (Vanderbilt), Sarah Gates Campbell (Peabody-Vanderbilt), Norman Rosenblood (McMaster), and Davis Perkins and his colleagues at Scholars Press for their individual efforts on behalf of this book.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Discussion of Representation
    International Visual Literacy Association, Cheyenne, 1996 A PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSION OF REPRESENTATION One of the most basic theoretical areas in the study of visual communication and visual literacy is the nature of representation. Much of the discussion of this topic comes from either philosophy or aesthetics. This paper reviews some of the more important writings in this area in an attempt to develop a model of representation. The primary works reviewed include: E. H. Gombrich, "The Visual Image;" "Representation and Misrepresentation" Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols, "Representation Re- presented" Paul Messaris, Visual Literacy: Image, Mind & Reality David Novitz, "Picturing" Marx Wartofsky, "Pictures, Representation, and Understanding;" "Visual Scenarios: The role of Representation in Visual Perception" Richard Wollheim, "Representation: The Philosophical Contribution to Psychology;" Pictures and Language;" and "Art, Interpretation, and Perception" In describing the requirements for a general theory of representation, Wollheim says it must answer two questions: What is it to represent? (what is the relationship between the representation and the something that it is of?) What, in the narrow sense of the term, is a representation? Using his two questions to guide our analysis, we find that the major theoretical issues that need to be investigated include: Is pictorial representation based on natural resemblance or convention? What is the relationship between pictures and reality? Finally, as part of this review, we are investigating if it is possible to develop an overriding theory of representation that accommodates the various issues and viewpoints. What is the relationship between pictures and reality? In beginning this discussion, let's first look at Wollheim's second question about what is a representation.
    [Show full text]
  • Paintings and Photographs, Introduction to "William Wegman" Curtis Carter Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2002 Paintings and Photographs, Introduction to "William Wegman" Curtis Carter Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. "Introduction," in William Wegman. Roman Zenner, 2002: 1-5. Permalink. © 2002 Roman Zenner. Used with permission. WILLIAM WEG MAN Roman Zenner 2002 PAINTINGS AND PHOTOGRAPHS When William Wegman began his career in the late 1960s, he like many young artists of his generation decided to abandon painting preferring instead to use pho­ tography and video to explore contemporary issues in art. Why abandon painting at this point? Painting, after all, had been under attack since the invention of photogra­ phy in the mid-nineteenth century. Still its output has continued for centuries virtu­ ally without interruption. Perhaps it was because painting in the 60s seemed less exciting or less flexible than the new media and unable to satisfy the needs of artists and the public in a technological post-modem society. Against the aesthetics of post­ modernism, painting as a medium affirms the values of originality and uniqueness. But these values had already been called into question decades earlier by Marcel Duchamp, Man Ray, and others. The decision to abandon painting overlooks certain facts about its resiliency. Painting has had a long history of success as an art form within a broad range of diverse cultures. As Richard Wollheim has argued," If artists over the centuries had not succeeded in putting across what they wished to convey, they would have turned to some other activity .... Or their public would have asked them to do SO."1 At the conclusion of a lengthy book on pain~ing, Wollheim's strongest argument for the continuation of painting is its survival as an art form.
    [Show full text]
  • RICHARD WOLLHEIM Copyright © British Academy 2001
    RICHARD WOLLHEIM Copyright © British Academy 2001 – all rights reserved Richard Arthur Wollheim 1923–2003 RICHARD ARTHUR WOLLHEIM was born on 5 May 1923 in London, the younger son of Eric Wollheim, of a German Jewish family, and Constance Baker, whose family came from the West Country and for centuries were peasants. His father was a theatrical impresario, who from 1918 acted as the Diaghilev ballet’s London manager. His mother was a Gaiety show- girl, who performed as an actress playing to the troops during the First World War, but at her husband’s insistence left the stage when she married. In his posthumously published memoir of his childhood, Germs (2004), which begins with his tottering out through the front door into the light at the age of two, Richard traces the roots in childhood of a variety of emotions he experienced in later life—resentment against calm, quiet places, the lure of danger, shame at the unreliability of his body, certain fears of inundation—and paints vivid pictures of his parents’ opinions, routines, behaviour and character. His father was emancipated and although he embraced no religious faith—indeed, considered all religion to be folly, he insisted that Richard was brought up as a Christian, an encumbrance Richard freed himself from when he grew up, from then on regarding all religions as harmful illusions, and, like Hume and Nietzsche, believing that religions tend to be worse the further they stray from polytheism. At the age of 13 he went to Westminster School as a King’s Scholar. It was the first time that he had been away to boarding-school, something he had been looking forward to but which turned out to be very different from what he had expected.
    [Show full text]
  • A Bridge Between Psychoanalysis and Neuroscience: an Overview
    1 ISSN 2693-2490 A Bridge between Psychoanalysis and Neuroscience: An Overview of the Neurobiological Effects of Psychoanalytical Psychotherapy Journal of Psychology and Neuroscience Research Article Diego Cohen, MD. PhD *Correspondence author Diego Cohen, MD. PhD Professor of Psychiatry University of Buenos Aries Medical Collage Professor of Psychiatry University of Buenos Aries Medical Collage Submitted : 17 Jun 2021 ; Published : 1 Jul 2021 Abstract This study sets out to investigate the mechanisms by which psychoanalytical psychotherapy can induce neurobiological changes. From Neuroscience which, in accordance with his thinking at the time, Freud never disregarded, the concepts of neuronal plasticity, enriched environment and the neurobiological aspects of the attachment process. From Psychoanalysis, the theory of transference, M. Mahler’s psychological evolution model, the concept of the regulating function of the self-objects and Winnicott’s holding environment concept. Together these provide a useful bridge toward the understanding of the neurobiological changes resulting from psychoanalytical psychotherapy. One concludes that psychoanalytical psychotherapy, through transference, acts as a new model of object relation and learning which furthers the development of certain brain areas, specifically, the right hemisphere, and the prefrontal and limbic cortices, which have a regulating function on affects. Keywords : Transference, Neurobiology, Attachment, Neuroscience Informed Therapy. Introduction In this study my aim is to provide
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Perception As a Guide to Aesthetics
    OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Fri Jan 31 2014, NEWGEN 5 Philosophy of Perception as a Guide to Aesthetics Bence Nanay 5.1 The Provocative Claim The aim of this paper is to argue for a provocative claim: that many, maybe even most traditional problems in aesthetics are in fact about philosophy of perception and can, as a result, be fruitfully addressed with the help of the conceptual apparatus of the philosophy of perception. I will spend much of the paper clarifying and qualifying this claim, which after all the qualifications may not sound so provocative after all. I need to clarify the following aspects of this claim: (a) What is meant by aesthetics. (b) What is meant by philosophy of perception. (c) Why should we accept that it is a promising avenue of research to consider prob- lems in aesthetics to be really about the philosophy of perception. I will take these in turn. But before we begin, it needs to be emphasized that on the face of it, the claim I make does not sound crazy, at least if we consider the etymology of the term ‘aesthetics’. The Greek word ‘aesthemi’ means perception and when Alexander Baumgarten introduced the concept of ‘aesthetics’ in 1750, what he meant by it was precisely the philosophy of perception: the study of sense perception (scientia cogni- tionis sensitivae). My claim is that, regardless of etymology, this connection can also be made today. It is important that my aim is not to argue that aesthetics should be a subdiscipline of philosophy of perception or that any approach that does not consider aesthetics to be philosophy of perception is doomed or should be considered inferior.
    [Show full text]
  • Monism and Pluralism: the History of Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Architecture - Part I Paul Guyer
    Monism and Pluralism: The History of Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Architecture - Part I Paul Guyer I. Monism and Pluralism in the Early History of Aesthetics One way to think about the history of aesthetics since its inception as a properly named subdiscipline of philosophy in the early eighteenth century is to think of it as a debate about the right way to understand the relations among the terms of the Neo-Platonist triad comprised by the true, the good, and the beautiful: do these terms designate three separate domains of human interest, the theoretical, the practical and moral, and the aesthetic, the boundaries between which must be sharply defined and maintained, or do they designate three aspects of human experience that can and should be fused in practice, indeed do they suggest that the distinctive function of art among human activities is precisely to fuse our natural love of beauty with our theoretical and moral concerns, to provide a kind of unity in human experience that we otherwise do not find?1 Immanuel Kant might be thought to be the foremost of separatists rather than synthesizers in the modern history of aesthetics: his definition in the “Analytic of the Beautiful” in the Critique of the Power of Judgment of the “judgment of taste” as “aesthetic,” where that means that it is neither cognitive nor practical, that on the one hand “In order to decide whether or not something is beautiful, we do not relate the representation by means of understanding to the object for cognition”2 and that on the other hand “The agreeable,
    [Show full text]
  • Sigmund Freud Papers
    Sigmund Freud Papers A Finding Aid to the Papers in the Sigmund Freud Collection in the Library of Congress Digitization made possible by The Polonsky Foundation Manuscript Division, Library of Congress Washington, D.C. 2015 Revised 2016 December Contact information: http://hdl.loc.gov/loc.mss/mss.contact Additional search options available at: http://hdl.loc.gov/loc.mss/eadmss.ms004017 LC Online Catalog record: http://lccn.loc.gov/mm80039990 Prepared by Allan Teichroew and Fred Bauman with the assistance of Patrick Holyfield and Brian McGuire Revised and expanded by Margaret McAleer, Tracey Barton, Thomas Bigley, Kimberly Owens, and Tammi Taylor Collection Summary Title: Sigmund Freud Papers Span Dates: circa 6th century B.C.E.-1998 Bulk Dates: (bulk 1871-1939) ID No.: MSS39990 Creator: Freud, Sigmund, 1856-1939 Extent: 48,600 items ; 141 containers plus 20 oversize and 3 artifacts ; 70.4 linear feet ; 23 microfilm reels Language: Collection material in German, with English and French Location: Manuscript Division, Library of Congress, Washington, D.C. Summary: Founder of psychoanalysis. Correspondence, holograph and typewritten drafts of writings by Freud and others, family papers, patient case files, legal documents, estate records, receipts, military and school records, certificates, notebooks, a pocket watch, a Greek statue, an oil portrait painting, genealogical data, interviews, research files, exhibit material, bibliographies, lists, photographs and drawings, newspaper and magazine clippings, and other printed matter. The collection documents many facets of Freud's life and writings; his associations with family, friends, mentors, colleagues, students, and patients; and the evolution of psychoanalytic theory and technique. Selected Search Terms The following terms have been used to index the description of this collection in the Library's online catalog.
    [Show full text]
  • Significant Landmarks in the History of Aphasia and Its Therapy
    © Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC © Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION CHAPTER© Jones & Bartlett2 Learning, LLC © Jones & Bartlett© Involved Channel/Shutterstock Learning, LLC NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION Significant© Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC Landmarks© Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC inNOT FOR the SALE OR DISTRIBUTIONHistory ofNOT AphasiaFOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION © Jones & Bartlettand Learning, Its LLC Therapy© Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC NOT FOR SALEChris OR Code DISTRIBUTION NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION OBJECTIVES© Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC © Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION The reader will be able to: 1. Understand the origins of different classifications of aphasia. 2. Compare models of aphasia that have emerged in the history of aphasia. 3.© JonesAppreciate & thatBartlett the history Learning, of aphasia LLC is influenced by social and ©political Jones developments & Bartlett in Learning,different countries. LLC 4. Name the main protagonists in the history of aphasia. 5.NOT Identify FOR the SALE main events OR DISTRIBUTION in the history of aphasia. NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION 6. Identify the main shifts in approach to the treatment of aphasia throughout the history of aphasia. 7. Understand where ideas about the nature of aphasia originated. © Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC © Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION “History doesn’t repeat itself. At best it sometimes Plato’s view, that the mind was located in the head rhymes.” contrasted with Aristotle’s idea that it was located in the heart.
    [Show full text]
  • Freud, S. (1923). the Ego and the Id. the Standard Edition Of
    Freud, S. (1923). The Ego and the Id. The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Volume XIX (1923- 1925): The Ego and the Id and Other Works, 1-66 The Ego and the Id Sigmund Freud This Page Left Intentionally Blank - 1 - Copyrighted Material. For use only by UPENN. Reproduction prohibited. Usage subject to PEP terms & conditions (see terms.pep-web.org). Editor's Introduction to "The Ego and the Id" James Strachey (a) German Editions: 1923 Das Ich Und Das Es Leipzig, Vienna and Zurich: Internationaler Psycho-analytischer Verlag. Pp. 77. 1925 Das Ich Und Das Es G.S., 6, 351-405. 1931 Das Ich Und Das Es Theoretische Schriften, 338-91. 1940 Das Ich Und Das Es G.W., 13, 237-289. (b) English Translation:: The Ego and the Id 1927 London: Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho- Analysis. Pp. 88. (Tr. Joan Riviere.) The present is a very considerably modified version of the one published in 1927. This book appeared in the third week of April, 1923, though it had been in Freud's mind since at least the previous July (Jones, 1957, 104). On September 26, 1922, at the Seventh International Psycho-Analytical Congress, which was held in Berlin and was the last he ever attended, he read a short paper with the title ‘Etwas vom Unbewussten [Some Remarks on the Unconscious]’, in which he foreshadowed the contents of the book. An abstract of this paper (which was never itself published) appeared that autumn in the Int. Zeitschrift Psychoanal., 5 (4), 486,1 and, although there is no certainty that it was written by Freud himself, it is worth while recording it: ‘Some Remarks on the Unconscious’ ‘The speaker repeated the familiar history of the development of the concept “‘unconscious” in psycho-analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • The Language of Boundaries
    Session 1: The Language of Boundaries There are 20 films, 40 ideas, and 4 architectures to cover in this survey of how boundaries are used in human life and expression, and there is no logical order that sets out plainly an obvious starting point of “basics” on to which more complicated issues can be later added. Rather, we have to “start in the middle” wherever we start, because everyplace is a center, out from which thought can move towards the horizon, which keeps receding the closer we get to it. With this in mind, it’s always a good idea to start with something that is both familiar and mysterious at the same time (this is, one should also note, Freud’s formula for the uncanny). We work within a physical field that is mostly spatial, involving the visual arts, landscape, architecture, film, travel, etc. But, this is not a simplification. In themental field of our project — defined primarily by a few key philosophers (Vico, Hegel, Cassirer) and psychoanalysts (Freud, La- can) — spatiality and temporality are intrinsic to thought and human being as such. We could say that “dimensional- ity” is something that humans construct once anxiety, the fuel for that construction, is given certain qualities; and that because they have some latitude over how it is constructed, personalities and cultures turn out to be quite unique, with the only common factor being the construction process rather than the end result. Zeno. Everyone knows the famous paradoxes of this ancient Greek philosopher. A fast runner (Achil- BASIC DIAGRAMS les) cannot beat out the tortoise; an arrow cannot reach the target; etc.
    [Show full text]
  • 19Chronology of Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy Of
    Chronology of 19 Works in Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art Darren Hudson Hick Notes on Selection This chronology, as with this Companion as a whole, focuses on those works that contribute to the Western tradition of aesthetics, and, beginning in the twentieth century, in the analytic current of thought within that tradition (as opposed to the Continental one). As with the history of Western philosophy in general, the study of philosophical problems in art and beauty dates back to the ancient period, and is infl uenced by the major philosophical and cultural move- ments through the centuries. Much of what survives from the ancient to the post-Hellenistic period does so in fragments or references. In cases where only fragments or references exist, and where dating these is especially problematic, the author or attributed author and (where available) his dates of birth and death are listed. Where works have not survived even as fragments, these are not listed. As well, much of what sur- vives up to the medieval period is diffi cult to date, and is at times of disputable attribution. In these cases, whatever information is available is listed. Aesthetics in the period between the ancients and the medievals tends to be dominated by adherence to Platonic, Aristotelian, and other theories rooted in the ancient period, and as such tends to be generally lacking in substantive the- oretical advancements. And while still heavily infl uenced by ancient thinking, works from the medieval period tend also to be heavily infl uenced by religious thinking, and so many issues pertaining to art and aesthetics are intertwined with issues of religion as “theological aesthetics.” Movements in art theory and aes- thetics in the Renaissance, meanwhile, were largely advanced by working artists, and so tend to be couched in observational or pedagogical approaches, rather than strictly theoretical ones.
    [Show full text]