Extensions of the Axiom of Determinacy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Extensions of the Axiom of Determinacy Extensions of the Axiom of Determinacy Paul B. Larson September 22, 2021 2 Contents 0.1 Introduction . 5 0.2 Notation . 7 0.3 Prerequisites . 9 0.4 Forms of Choice . 9 0.5 Partial orders . 9 I Preliminaries 11 1 The Axiom of Determinacy 13 1.1 Turing determinacy . 15 2 The Wadge hierarchy 19 2.1 Lipschitz determinacy . 19 2.2 Lipschitz degrees and Wadge degrees . 21 2.3 Pointclasses . 26 2.4 Universal sets . 28 2.5 The cardinal Θ . 33 3 Coding Lemmas 37 4 Properties of pointclasses 43 4.1 Separation and reduction . 43 4.2 The prewellordering property . 48 4.3 Prewellorderings and wellfounded relations . 52 4.4 Closure under wellordered unions . 54 5 Strong Partition Cardinals 57 5.1 The Martin Conditions . 59 6 Suslin sets and Uniformization 63 6.1 Uniformization ............................. 68 6.2 The Kunen-Martin property . 69 6.3 A pointclass fact . 69 6.4 The Solovay sequence . 70 3 4 CONTENTS II AD+ 73 7 <Θ-determinacy 75 8 Cone measures 81 8.1 Measurable cardinals from cone measures . 85 8.2 The degree order on sets of ordinals . 86 8.3 Pointed trees . 91 8.4 Coding ultrapowers . 92 8.5 Forcing with positive sets . 93 9 1-Borel sets 97 9.1 Local 1-Borel codes . 103 10 Vopˇenka algebras 107 10.1 Codes for projections, and Uniformization . 111 10.2 Vopˇenka algebras and 1-Borel sets . 116 10.3 1-Borel subsets of P(δ) . 120 11 Applications 125 11.1 Strong 1-Borel codes . 125 11.2 Producing strong 1-Borel codes . 127 11.3 1-Borel representations from Uniformization . 130 11.4 Closure of the Suslin cardinals . 132 12 Scales from Uniformization 137 12.1 Ordinal determinacy in the codes . 137 12.2 Boundedness for 1-Borel relations . 141 12.3 Becker's argument . 142 13 ADR 149 13.1 Weakly homogeneous trees . 150 13.2 Normal measures . 153 13.3 AD implies ADR if all sets are Suslin . 157 14 Questions 161 0.1. INTRODUCTION 5 This draft includes notes to myself, in footnotes. These should probably be ignored. Comments and corrections are more than welcome, although some parts are obviously very rough and these may not be worth commenting on, since they'll probably we rewritten. Chapters 1, 2 and 3 should be essentially in their final form, so please let me know when you see issues there. Ideally, I'll remember to post frequent updates. 0.1 Introduction The Axiom of Determinacy (AD) is the statement that all length-! integer games of perfect information are determined. The beginning of Chapter 1 contains a more precise definition, but we expect the reader to be familiar with the classical theory of determinacy, as found in [7, 9], for instance. The axiom AD+ is a generalization, due to W. Hugh Woodin, of the Axiom of Determinacy. We define it as the conjunction of three statements. 0.1.1 Definition. The axiom AD+ is the conjunction of the following three statements. 1. DCR 2. Every subset of !! is 1-Borel. 3. (<Θ-Determinacy) For all λ < Θ, every A ⊆ !! and every continuous function π : !λ ! !!, π−1(A) is determined (as a subset of !λ). The 1-Borel sets are defined in Definition 9.0.1 for subsets of 2!, and in Remark 9.0.8 for subsets of !!. The notion of continuity in <Θ-Determinacy refers to the discrete topology on λ, not the interval topology. The restriction of <Θ-Determinacy to the case where π is the identity function on !! is exactly AD. It is an open question whether AD implies any or all of the parts of AD+, and in fact whether AD plus any two parts of AD+ implies the third. It also + open whether ADR implies AD . The issue in this case is whether ADR implies <Θ-Determinacy, as DCR is easily seen to follow from ADR, and the second part + of AD follows from ADR (moreover, from AD + Uniformization) by Theorem 11.3.2. If M ⊆ N are models of AD with the same reals, and every set of reals in M is Suslin in N, then M j= AD+.1 In fact, this is the context which the axiom AD+ was designed to describe; its original name was \within scales". Here is a brief2 outline of what we aim to prove is this book (all due to Woodin): + • In L(R), AD implies AD . 1Reference the relevant theorems. 2and incomplete 6 CONTENTS • If AD+ holds then every inner model containing the reals satisfies AD+. • If AD+ holds then the set of Suslin cardinals is closed below Θ. This follows from Theorem 11.4.1.3 • Assuming DCR and <Θ-Determinacy, ADR is equivalent to the assertion that the Solovay sequence has limit length. This is shown in Section ??.4 + 2 • AD implies Σ1 reflection into the Suslin, co-Suslin (i.e., hom) sets • AD+ implies that the ultrapower of V by the Turing measure is well- founded. ! • AD + DCR implies that for all ordinals χ, every subset of ! in L(P(χ)) is 1-Borel. Theorem 0.1.2 (Woodin). If <Θ-Determinacy and Uniformization hold, then every subset of !! is Suslin. Proof. By Theorem 11.3.2, the hypotheses give that every subset of !! is 1- Borel. The theorem then follows from Corollary 10.1.7 and Theorem 11.2.1. The first sentence of the following theorem is due to Woodin. The implication from (4) to (1) under DC combines results of Woodin and Becker (see Chapter 12) Theorem 0.1.3. Each of the following statements implies the ones below it, and the first two statements are equivalent. If DC holds, then all four statements are equivalent. 1. AD + \every subset of !! is Suslin" 2. AD+ + \every subset of !! is Suslin" 3. ADR 4. AD + Uniformization Proof. To see that (3) implies (4), note that ADR implies Uniformization, via a game in which each player plays once. That (2) implies (1) follows from applying Ordinal Determinacy in the case λ = !. As discussed in Chapter 6, Suslin sets can be uniformized, and Uniformization implies DCR. The implication from (1) to (2) then follows from Theorems 5.0.2 and 7.0.3, and Remark 6.0.9. Theorem 13.0.1 says that (1) implies (3). That (4) implies (1) under DC is Theorem 12.3.1 (the cofinality of Θ being uncountable is the relevant consequence of DC). 5 3Get closure below the supremum just from AD; comment on the reversal. 4 Does this need DCR? 5I should also introduce this theorem properly. 0.2. NOTATION 7 ! Theorem 0.1.4. Assume that AD + DCR holds. Let Γ be the set of A ⊆ ! for + which L(A; R) j= AD . Then + L(Γ; R) j= AD ; ! 6 and, if Γ 6= P(! ), then L(Γ; R) j= DC + ADR. Proof78 The following theorem follows from part (1) of Corollary 10.3.7. ! Theorem 0.1.5. Assuming AD+DCR, a subset of ! is 1-Borel if and only if there is a set of ordinals S such that A 2 L(S; R). The following is Theorem 11.4.8. + Theorem 0.1.6. If AD holds, then ADR fails if and only if there is a set of ordinals T such that L(P(R)) = L(T; R). + Theorem 0.1.7. Assume that V = L(P(R)) and that AD holds. Then for all A ⊆ !!, either V = L(A; R), or A# exists.9 Theorem 0.1.8. If AD and DCR hold, then for every ordinal χ, every subset of !! inL (P(χ)) is 1-Borel. Part I of the book collects various facts (primarily from the Cabal seminar) which will be needed in Part II. A natural way to read the book would be to start at the beginning of Part II and refer back to Part I as needed. This book has a great deal of overlap with many sources, notably [6, 18, 19]. 0.2 Notation We reserve the symbol R for the real line, which is never used directly. However, we use traditional notation such as ADR, DCR, L(R) and so on, as these terms ! are equivalent to more relevant forms such as AD!! , DC!! and L(! ). We informally use the word \real" to mean an element of the Baire space !!. We use the following notational conventions. • We write Ord for the class of ordinals. • We write XY to mean the set of functions from Y to X, and, when γ is <γ S α an ordinal X to mean α2γ X . 6 ! What is the proof? Let χB be the 1-Borel threshhold. Then P(! ) \ L(P(χB)) is the 1-Borel sets. Look at a limit of Suslin cardinals; all sets are < Borel, so also Suslin? 7 ! Let χB be the universally Baire threshold. Then P(! ) \ L(P(χB)) = 1-Borel. 8Also : let λ be a limit of Suslin cardinals. All sets are < λ-Borel, so also Suslin (what did mean by this?? 9 Another statement to consider : The axiom ADR implies that the sharp of each subset of !! exists. 8 CONTENTS • For an ordinal α and a set of ordinals X,[X]α denotes the collection of subsets of X of ordertype α, and [X]<α denotes the collection of subsets of X of ordertype less than α. • Given a set X, we write 9X and 8X for existential and universal quantifi- cation over X, respectively. • A preorder on a set is a binary relation which is reflexive and transitive.
Recommended publications
  • Calibrating Determinacy Strength in Levels of the Borel Hierarchy
    CALIBRATING DETERMINACY STRENGTH IN LEVELS OF THE BOREL HIERARCHY SHERWOOD J. HACHTMAN Abstract. We analyze the set-theoretic strength of determinacy for levels of the Borel 0 hierarchy of the form Σ1+α+3, for α < !1. Well-known results of H. Friedman and D.A. Martin have shown this determinacy to require α+1 iterations of the Power Set Axiom, but we ask what additional ambient set theory is strictly necessary. To this end, we isolate a family of Π1-reflection principles, Π1-RAPα, whose consistency strength corresponds 0 CK exactly to that of Σ1+α+3-Determinacy, for α < !1 . This yields a characterization of the levels of L by or at which winning strategies in these games must be constructed. When α = 0, we have the following concise result: the least θ so that all winning strategies 0 in Σ4 games belong to Lθ+1 is the least so that Lθ j= \P(!) exists + all wellfounded trees are ranked". x1. Introduction. Given a set A ⊆ !! of sequences of natural numbers, consider a game, G(A), where two players, I and II, take turns picking elements of a sequence hx0; x1; x2;::: i of naturals. Player I wins the game if the sequence obtained belongs to A; otherwise, II wins. For a collection Γ of subsets of !!, Γ determinacy, which we abbreviate Γ-DET, is the statement that for every A 2 Γ, one of the players has a winning strategy in G(A). It is a much-studied phenomenon that Γ -DET has mathematical strength: the bigger the pointclass Γ, the stronger the theory required to prove Γ -DET.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics 144 Set Theory Fall 2012 Version
    MATHEMATICS 144 SET THEORY FALL 2012 VERSION Table of Contents I. General considerations.……………………………………………………………………………………………………….1 1. Overview of the course…………………………………………………………………………………………………1 2. Historical background and motivation………………………………………………………….………………4 3. Selected problems………………………………………………………………………………………………………13 I I. Basic concepts. ………………………………………………………………………………………………………………….15 1. Topics from logic…………………………………………………………………………………………………………16 2. Notation and first steps………………………………………………………………………………………………26 3. Simple examples…………………………………………………………………………………………………………30 I I I. Constructions in set theory.………………………………………………………………………………..……….34 1. Boolean algebra operations.……………………………………………………………………………………….34 2. Ordered pairs and Cartesian products……………………………………………………………………… ….40 3. Larger constructions………………………………………………………………………………………………..….42 4. A convenient assumption………………………………………………………………………………………… ….45 I V. Relations and functions ……………………………………………………………………………………………….49 1.Binary relations………………………………………………………………………………………………………… ….49 2. Partial and linear orderings……………………………..………………………………………………… ………… 56 3. Functions…………………………………………………………………………………………………………… ….…….. 61 4. Composite and inverse function.…………………………………………………………………………… …….. 70 5. Constructions involving functions ………………………………………………………………………… ……… 77 6. Order types……………………………………………………………………………………………………… …………… 80 i V. Number systems and set theory …………………………………………………………………………………. 84 1. The Natural Numbers and Integers…………………………………………………………………………….83 2. Finite induction
    [Show full text]
  • Biography Paper – Georg Cantor
    Mike Garkie Math 4010 – History of Math UCD Denver 4/1/08 Biography Paper – Georg Cantor Few mathematicians are house-hold names; perhaps only Newton and Euclid would qualify. But there is a second tier of mathematicians, those whose names might not be familiar, but whose discoveries are part of everyday math. Examples here are Napier with logarithms, Cauchy with limits and Georg Cantor (1845 – 1918) with sets. In fact, those who superficially familier with Georg Cantor probably have two impressions of the man: First, as a consequence of thinking about sets, Cantor developed a theory of the actual infinite. And second, that Cantor was a troubled genius, crippled by Freudian conflict and mental illness. The first impression is fundamentally true. Cantor almost single-handedly overturned the Aristotle’s concept of the potential infinite by developing the concept of transfinite numbers. And, even though Bolzano and Frege made significant contributions, “Set theory … is the creation of one person, Georg Cantor.” [4] The second impression is mostly false. Cantor certainly did suffer from mental illness later in his life, but the other emotional baggage assigned to him is mostly due his early biographers, particularly the infamous E.T. Bell in Men Of Mathematics [7]. In the racially charged atmosphere of 1930’s Europe, the sensational story mathematician who turned the idea of infinity on its head and went crazy in the process, probably make for good reading. The drama of the controversy over Cantor’s ideas only added spice. 1 Fortunately, modern scholars have corrected the errors and biases in older biographies.
    [Show full text]
  • Algebra I Chapter 1. Basic Facts from Set Theory 1.1 Glossary of Abbreviations
    Notes: c F.P. Greenleaf, 2000-2014 v43-s14sets.tex (version 1/1/2014) Algebra I Chapter 1. Basic Facts from Set Theory 1.1 Glossary of abbreviations. Below we list some standard math symbols that will be used as shorthand abbreviations throughout this course. means “for all; for every” • ∀ means “there exists (at least one)” • ∃ ! means “there exists exactly one” • ∃ s.t. means “such that” • = means “implies” • ⇒ means “if and only if” • ⇐⇒ x A means “the point x belongs to a set A;” x / A means “x is not in A” • ∈ ∈ N denotes the set of natural numbers (counting numbers) 1, 2, 3, • · · · Z denotes the set of all integers (positive, negative or zero) • Q denotes the set of rational numbers • R denotes the set of real numbers • C denotes the set of complex numbers • x A : P (x) If A is a set, this denotes the subset of elements x in A such that •statement { ∈ P (x)} is true. As examples of the last notation for specifying subsets: x R : x2 +1 2 = ( , 1] [1, ) { ∈ ≥ } −∞ − ∪ ∞ x R : x2 +1=0 = { ∈ } ∅ z C : z2 +1=0 = +i, i where i = √ 1 { ∈ } { − } − 1.2 Basic facts from set theory. Next we review the basic definitions and notations of set theory, which will be used throughout our discussions of algebra. denotes the empty set, the set with nothing in it • ∅ x A means that the point x belongs to a set A, or that x is an element of A. • ∈ A B means A is a subset of B – i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • MATH 361 Homework 9
    MATH 361 Homework 9 Royden 3.3.9 First, we show that for any subset E of the real numbers, Ec + y = (E + y)c (translating the complement is equivalent to the complement of the translated set). Without loss of generality, assume E can be written as c an open interval (e1; e2), so that E + y is represented by the set fxjx 2 (−∞; e1 + y) [ (e2 + y; +1)g. This c is equal to the set fxjx2 = (e1 + y; e2 + y)g, which is equivalent to the set (E + y) . Second, Let B = A − y. From Homework 8, we know that outer measure is invariant under translations. Using this along with the fact that E is measurable: m∗(A) = m∗(B) = m∗(B \ E) + m∗(B \ Ec) = m∗((B \ E) + y) + m∗((B \ Ec) + y) = m∗(((A − y) \ E) + y) + m∗(((A − y) \ Ec) + y) = m∗(A \ (E + y)) + m∗(A \ (Ec + y)) = m∗(A \ (E + y)) + m∗(A \ (E + y)c) The last line follows from Ec + y = (E + y)c. Royden 3.3.10 First, since E1;E2 2 M and M is a σ-algebra, E1 [ E2;E1 \ E2 2 M. By the measurability of E1 and E2: ∗ ∗ ∗ c m (E1) = m (E1 \ E2) + m (E1 \ E2) ∗ ∗ ∗ c m (E2) = m (E2 \ E1) + m (E2 \ E1) ∗ ∗ ∗ ∗ c ∗ c m (E1) + m (E2) = 2m (E1 \ E2) + m (E1 \ E2) + m (E1 \ E2) ∗ ∗ ∗ c ∗ c = m (E1 \ E2) + [m (E1 \ E2) + m (E1 \ E2) + m (E1 \ E2)] c c Second, E1 \ E2, E1 \ E2, and E1 \ E2 are disjoint sets whose union is equal to E1 [ E2.
    [Show full text]
  • UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS and GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON Introduction Generic Absoluteness Principles Assert That Certai
    UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON Abstract. We prove several equivalences and relative consistency re- 2 uBλ sults involving notions of generic absoluteness beyond Woodin's (Σ1) generic absoluteness for a limit of Woodin cardinals λ. In particular,e we R 2 uBλ prove that two-step 9 (Π1) generic absoluteness below a measur- able cardinal that is a limite of Woodin cardinals has high consistency 2 uBλ strength, and that it is equivalent with the existence of trees for (Π1) formulas. The construction of these trees uses a general method for building an absolute complement for a given tree T assuming many \failures of covering" for the models L(T;Vα) below a measurable car- dinal. Introduction Generic absoluteness principles assert that certain properties of the set- theoretic universe cannot be changed by the method of forcing. Some pro- perties, such as the truth or falsity of the Continuum Hypothesis, can always be changed by forcing. Accordingly, one approach to formulating generic ab- soluteness principles is to consider properties of a limited complexity such 1 1 as those corresponding to pointclasses in descriptive set theory: Σ2, Σ3, projective, and so on. (Another approach is to limit the class ofe allowede forcing notions. For a survey of results in this area, see [1].) Shoenfield’s 1 absoluteness theorem implies that Σ2 statements are always generically ab- solute. Generic absoluteness principlese for larger pointclasses tend to be equiconsistent with strong axioms of infinity, and they may also relate to the extent of the universally Baire sets. 1 For example, one-step Σ3 generic absoluteness is shown in [3] to be equiconsistent with the existencee of a Σ2-reflecting cardinal and to be equiv- 1 alent with the statement that every ∆2 set of reals is universally Baire.
    [Show full text]
  • SRB MEASURES for ALMOST AXIOM a DIFFEOMORPHISMS José Alves, Renaud Leplaideur
    SRB MEASURES FOR ALMOST AXIOM A DIFFEOMORPHISMS José Alves, Renaud Leplaideur To cite this version: José Alves, Renaud Leplaideur. SRB MEASURES FOR ALMOST AXIOM A DIFFEOMORPHISMS. 2013. hal-00778407 HAL Id: hal-00778407 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-00778407 Preprint submitted on 20 Jan 2013 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. SRB MEASURES FOR ALMOST AXIOM A DIFFEOMORPHISMS JOSE´ F. ALVES AND RENAUD LEPLAIDEUR Abstract. We consider a diffeomorphism f of a compact manifold M which is Almost Axiom A, i.e. f is hyperbolic in a neighborhood of some compact f-invariant set, except in some singular set of neutral points. We prove that if there exists some f-invariant set of hyperbolic points with positive unstable-Lebesgue measure such that for every point in this set the stable and unstable leaves are \long enough", then f admits a probability SRB measure. Contents 1. Introduction 2 1.1. Background 2 1.2. Statement of results 2 1.3. Overview 4 2. Markov rectangles 5 2.1. Neighborhood of critical zone 5 2.2. First generation of rectangles 6 2.3. Second generation rectangles 7 2.4.
    [Show full text]
  • Infinite Sets
    “mcs-ftl” — 2010/9/8 — 0:40 — page 379 — #385 13 Infinite Sets So you might be wondering how much is there to say about an infinite set other than, well, it has an infinite number of elements. Of course, an infinite set does have an infinite number of elements, but it turns out that not all infinite sets have the same size—some are bigger than others! And, understanding infinity is not as easy as you might think. Some of the toughest questions in mathematics involve infinite sets. Why should you care? Indeed, isn’t computer science only about finite sets? Not exactly. For example, we deal with the set of natural numbers N all the time and it is an infinite set. In fact, that is why we have induction: to reason about predicates over N. Infinite sets are also important in Part IV of the text when we talk about random variables over potentially infinite sample spaces. So sit back and open your mind for a few moments while we take a very brief look at infinity. 13.1 Injections, Surjections, and Bijections We know from Theorem 7.2.1 that if there is an injection or surjection between two finite sets, then we can say something about the relative sizes of the two sets. The same is true for infinite sets. In fact, relations are the primary tool for determining the relative size of infinite sets. Definition 13.1.1. Given any two sets A and B, we say that A surj B iff there is a surjection from A to B, A inj B iff there is an injection from A to B, A bij B iff there is a bijection between A and B, and A strict B iff there is a surjection from A to B but there is no bijection from B to A.
    [Show full text]
  • A Linear Order on All Finite Groups
    Preprints (www.preprints.org) | NOT PEER-REVIEWED | Posted: 5 July 2020 doi:10.20944/preprints202006.0098.v3 CANONICAL DESCRIPTION OF GROUP THEORY: A LINEAR ORDER ON ALL FINITE GROUPS Juan Pablo Ram´ırez [email protected]; June 6, 2020 Guadalajara, Jal., Mexico´ Abstract We provide an axiomatic base for the set of natural numbers, that has been proposed as a canonical construction, and use this definition of N to find several results on finite group theory. Every finite group G, is well represented with a natural number NG; if NG = NH then H; G are in the same isomorphism class. We have a linear order, on the quotient space of isomorphism classes of finite groups, that is well behaved with respect to cardinality. If H; G are two finite groups such that j j j j ≤ ≤ n1 ⊕ n2 ⊕ · · · ⊕ nk n1 n2 ··· nk H = m < n = G , then H < Zn G Zp1 Zp2 Zpk where n = p1 p2 pk is the prime factorization of n. We find a canonical order for the objects of G and define equivalent objects of G, thus finding the automorphisms of G. The Cayley table of G takes canonical block form, and we are provided with a minimal set of independent equations that define the group. We show how to find all groups of order n, and order them. We give examples using all groups with order smaller than 10, and we find the canonical block form of the symmetry group ∆4. In the next section, we extend our results to the infinite case, which defines a real number as an infinite set of natural numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch
    Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch. August 16, 2020 Contents Page 1 Axioms and Formal Systems 1 1.1 Introduction 1 1.2 Preliminaries: axioms and formal systems. 3 1.2.1 The formal language of ZF set theory; terms 4 1.2.2 The Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms 7 1.3 Transfinite Recursion 9 1.4 Relativisation of terms and formulae 11 2 Initial segments of the Universe 17 2.1 Singular ordinals: cofinality 17 2.1.1 Cofinality 17 2.1.2 Normal Functions and closed and unbounded classes 19 2.1.3 Stationary Sets 22 2.2 Some further cardinal arithmetic 24 2.3 Transitive Models 25 2.4 The H sets 27 2.4.1 H - the hereditarily finite sets 28 2.4.2 H - the hereditarily countable sets 29 2.5 The Montague-Levy Reflection theorem 30 2.5.1 Absoluteness 30 2.5.2 Reflection Theorems 32 2.6 Inaccessible Cardinals 34 2.6.1 Inaccessible cardinals 35 2.6.2 A menagerie of other large cardinals 36 3 Formalising semantics within ZF 39 3.1 Definite terms and formulae 39 3.1.1 The non-finite axiomatisability of ZF 44 3.2 Formalising syntax 45 3.3 Formalising the satisfaction relation 46 3.4 Formalising definability: the function Def. 47 3.5 More on correctness and consistency 48 ii iii 3.5.1 Incompleteness and Consistency Arguments 50 4 The Constructible Hierarchy 53 4.1 The L -hierarchy 53 4.2 The Axiom of Choice in L 56 4.3 The Axiom of Constructibility 57 4.4 The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis in L.
    [Show full text]
  • Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive?
    Are Large Cardinal Axioms Restrictive? Neil Barton∗ 24 June 2020y Abstract The independence phenomenon in set theory, while perva- sive, can be partially addressed through the use of large cardinal axioms. A commonly assumed idea is that large cardinal axioms are species of maximality principles. In this paper, I argue that whether or not large cardinal axioms count as maximality prin- ciples depends on prior commitments concerning the richness of the subset forming operation. In particular I argue that there is a conception of maximality through absoluteness, on which large cardinal axioms are restrictive. I argue, however, that large cardi- nals are still important axioms of set theory and can play many of their usual foundational roles. Introduction Large cardinal axioms are widely viewed as some of the best candi- dates for new axioms of set theory. They are (apparently) linearly ordered by consistency strength, have substantial mathematical con- sequences for questions independent from ZFC (such as consistency statements and Projective Determinacy1), and appear natural to the ∗Fachbereich Philosophie, University of Konstanz. E-mail: neil.barton@uni- konstanz.de. yI would like to thank David Aspero,´ David Fernandez-Bret´ on,´ Monroe Eskew, Sy-David Friedman, Victoria Gitman, Luca Incurvati, Michael Potter, Chris Scam- bler, Giorgio Venturi, Matteo Viale, Kameryn Williams and audiences in Cambridge, New York, Konstanz, and Sao˜ Paulo for helpful discussion. Two anonymous ref- erees also provided helpful comments, and I am grateful for their input. I am also very grateful for the generous support of the FWF (Austrian Science Fund) through Project P 28420 (The Hyperuniverse Programme) and the VolkswagenStiftung through the project Forcing: Conceptual Change in the Foundations of Mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • 17 Axiom of Choice
    Math 361 Axiom of Choice 17 Axiom of Choice De¯nition 17.1. Let be a nonempty set of nonempty sets. Then a choice function for is a function f sucFh that f(S) S for all S . F 2 2 F Example 17.2. Let = (N)r . Then we can de¯ne a choice function f by F P f;g f(S) = the least element of S: Example 17.3. Let = (Z)r . Then we can de¯ne a choice function f by F P f;g f(S) = ²n where n = min z z S and, if n = 0, ² = min z= z z = n; z S . fj j j 2 g 6 f j j j j j 2 g Example 17.4. Let = (Q)r . Then we can de¯ne a choice function f as follows. F P f;g Let g : Q N be an injection. Then ! f(S) = q where g(q) = min g(r) r S . f j 2 g Example 17.5. Let = (R)r . Then it is impossible to explicitly de¯ne a choice function for . F P f;g F Axiom 17.6 (Axiom of Choice (AC)). For every set of nonempty sets, there exists a function f such that f(S) S for all S . F 2 2 F We say that f is a choice function for . F Theorem 17.7 (AC). If A; B are non-empty sets, then the following are equivalent: (a) A B ¹ (b) There exists a surjection g : B A. ! Proof. (a) (b) Suppose that A B.
    [Show full text]