The Senses Considered As Perceptual Systems·

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Senses Considered As Perceptual Systems· The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems· JAMES J. GIBSON Cornell University London GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN LTD RUSKIN HOUSE MUSEUM STREET Editor's Foreword How do animals, including human beings; secure the information from the world about them that is essential to their adaptation to it and their survival in it? Since ancient times this all-important question has been asked in many ways and a great variety of answers have been proposed. In this book the basic problem is analyzed anew and solutions are sug- gested which are both scientifically satisfying and almost startlingly novel. Dr. Gibson does not treat of the different senses as mere producers of visual, auditory, tactual, or other sensations. Rather, he regards them as active seeking mechanisms for looking, listening, touching, and the like. This means that the emphasis is on explanations of how we are able to have the constant perceptions that we need for effective action and avoidance of physical harm in our everyday lives. The author clearly supports his view that the perception of reality is not something as- sembled or computed by the brain from an ever-varying kaleidoscope of sensations. Dr. Gibson emphasizes the importance of regarding the different per- ceptual systems not only as active, but also interrelated. He points out that visual perception, for example, is frequently a seeking of informa- tion by head and eye movements coordinated in the so-called eye-head system. Similar active adjustments take place as the organism secures information with its ear-head system. The same can be said of the seek- ing and searching of the hand-body system. These out-reaching mech- anisms search out for the organism the required perceptual information about the world in which it exists. This dynamic perception is contrasted with the quite different sensory experience that results from the activation of essentially passive receptors. As the author notes, sensory experiences resulting from passive stimula- tion, that is, simple receptor activation, have been very widely studied in laboratories of physiology and psychology, with rigorous control of both the stimulus energies presented to the organism and the receptor cells that are acted upon. Dr. Gibson acknowledges these sensory experiences as facts, but he treats them as by-products of perception rather than building blocks. In other words, this book is not just another treatise on the anatomy and physiology of receptors. It is not a new report on quantitative experi- v vi / EDITOR'S FOREWORD mental findings of sensory thresholds. It is not an essay on psychophysics. It is even not directly concerned with the sensory projection areas of the brain or with the coding of impulses in afferent peripheral nerves. Rather, it has quite another mission, all too often neglected or forgotten. It ex- plains how our senses, as active interrelated systems, provide continuous, stable information that alone makes adaptive living possible. Successive chapters embrace the contribution made by each of the main receptor systems that are basic to the adjustment of the organism to its world. To me, the author's thesis seems most arresting in his daring, yet convincing new look at the psychological functions of the total visual mechanism. He introduces the concept of "ecological optics." This new treatment is not mentalistic; it is not traditionally physiological or physi- cal; but it is still rigorously scientific. In terms of this novel point of view, the book examines some fundamental questions in psychology: What is innate and what is acquired in perception? What is the role of learning in establishing adult perception? How is perceiving related to expec- tancy? What is the effect of language on perceiving? What are per- ceptual illusions? All in all, the editor considers this novel and challenging book a most important contribution to the assumptions underlying all scientific con- cern with living animals, especially human beings. In some respects it amplifies and develops ideas that were first presented in the author's earlier book, The Perception of the Visual World (Allen and Unwin, 1952). That book has received wide acceptance and has sparked many continuing fruitful experimental programs. An acquaintance of the editor, one of England's ablest psychologists, said of that earlier book that it seemed to him the most insightful volume to come from American psy- chology for decades. Certainly this new book merits similar praise. I have no doubt it will be forthcoming. It is refreshingly novel in the solutions it proposes for some of the oldest and most fundamental problems. Certainly not all professional students of mental life will agree with all the conclusions of this book. But it will be a brave psychologist indeed who feels he can afford to be ignorant of what is said in it. Leonard Carmichael Preface This book has had to be written twice - once in 1958-59 and again in 1963-64. The second draft is more explicit and coherent than the first, for a good deal of experimenting, teaching, arguing, reading, and re- formulating came in between. I needed to restudy the theories of per- ception handed down from the philosophers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries - theories that were only slightly modified by the experimental psychologists of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. I also had to survey the whole area of the anatomy and physiology of the senses. It was difficult to shake off the traditional explanations of the facts while keeping hold of the facts themselves. I am very grateful to the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton for taking me in and then leaving me alone while the first draft was being written. The Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences shel- tered me during the second draft, and that year was a real pleasure. These admirable establishments have made this book possible. And if the National Institutes of Health had not granted Cornell one of their career research awards on my behalf, the book would not be finished yet. A series of experiments lies behind the writing of this book. These studies, published and unpublished, have been supported for many years by the Physiological Psychology Branch of the Office of Naval Research under a contract with Cornell (Nonr 401-14). This agreement is for work on the perception of "motion" and of "space." The justification for such support has been that clarification of these ancient puzzles might contribute to aviation - and so it will someday. These chapters have been read in various versions and parts by a con- siderable number of knowledgeable persons, and to them I am indebted. The ones who gave the greatest help in revision were Leonard Car- michael, Wendell Gamer, Lloyd Kaufman, and T. A. Ryan. In formula- tion there are many others who helped, especially Julian Hochberg, who helped by arguing with me (or sometimes even agreeing) and thereby lessened the obscurity that the reader must face. The three experimental investigators in the field of perception who seem to be working closest to the vein of evidence that I am trying to mine are all from outside this country. They are Ivo Kohler of Innsbruck, Gunnar Johansson of Uppsala, and the late Albert Michotte of Louvain. vii viii / PREFACE Their discoveries are invaluable and, however the facts are interpreted, crucial for any theory of sense perception. Psychologists of the previous generation to whom lowe the greatest intellectual debt are E. B. Holt, Kurt Koffka, L. T. Troland, and E. G. Boring. This is a mixed group, but the fact is that I am attempting to reformulate stimulus-response theory, Gestalt phenomenology, and psy- chophysics so as to extract new theorems from these old theories. Above all, I am indebted to my students. A teacher depends on his students as much as they do on him. The young psychologists to whom lowe most are John Hay, Jacob Beck, Howard Flock, William Schiff, Horace Reynolds, Anne Danielson Pick, and Herbert Pick. This whole inquiry has been shared for years with Eleanor J. Gibson, my wife. In 1963, however, we divided the problems between us, and she has concentrated on perceptual learning and development while I concentrated on the senses. Her forthcoming book will take up the story where mine leaves off. Ithaca, New York J. J. G. April 1966 Contents Introduction I What are the senses? 1/ The Senses and the Sensory Nerves 4/ The Improvement of Perception with Learning 5/ The Facts to be Surveyed 6/ I The Environment as a Source of Stimulation 7 The Terrestrial Environment 8/ The Consequences of Rigidity 8/ The Consequences of Gravity 10/ The Conse- quences of Electromagnetic Radiation 11/ The Special Consequences of Light 12/ The Air as a Medium 14/ Ambient Information 15/ Perspective Projections of an Object 15/ Compression Waves from a Vibratory Event 15/ The Diffusion of Volatile Substances 17/ Chemical Contacts with the Environment 19/ Mechanical Contacts with the Environment 20/ The World of Physics and the Sources of Stimulation 21/ The Animate Environment 22/ Social Stimulation 23/ Social Interaction 24/ The Environment of Emerging Man 24/ The Cultural Environment 26/ The Meaning of the Term "Stimulus" 28/ Summary 29/ II The Obtaining of Stimulation 31 Two Ways of Obtaining Stimulation 32/ The Fallacy of Ascribing Proprioception to Proprioceptors 33/ The Lower Proprioceptive Systems: Posture and Equilibrium 35/ The Higher Proprioceptive Systems: Purposive Action 36/ Theories of Action Sensitivity 38/ The Characteristics of a Natural Stimulus 39/ Receptors,
Recommended publications
  • Emulating the Perceptual System of the Brain for the Purpose of Sensor Fusion
    HSI 2008 Krakow, Poland, May 25-27, 2008 Emulating the Perceptual System of the Brain for the Purpose of Sensor Fusion Rosemarie Velik, Member, IEEE, Roland Lang, Member, IEEE, Dietmar Bruckner, Member, IEEE, and Tobias Deutsch, Member, IEEE Abstract — This work presents a bionic model derived II. STATE OF THE ART from research findings about the perceptual system of the There have already been made various attempts to merge human brain to build next generation intelligent sensor fusion systems. Therefore, a new information processing information coming from various sensory sources. The principle called neuro-symbolic information processing is research area generally first mentioned when discussing introduced. According to this method, sensory data are such tasks is the area of sensor fusion. In literature, there processed by so-called neuro-symbolic networks. The basic cannot be found only one but various definitions of the processing units of neuro-symbolic networks are neuro- term sensor fusion. Principally, sensor fusion is concerned symbols. Correlations between neuro-symbols of a neuro- with the combination of sensor data or data derived from symbolic network can be learned from examples. Perception sensory data in order to produce enhanced data in form of is based on sensor data as well as on interaction with an internal representation of the process environment. The cognitive processes like focus of attention, memory, and achievements of sensor fusion are robustness, extended knowledge. Additionally, a mechanism for evaluating perception by emotions is suggested. spatial and temporal coverage, increased confidence, reduced ambiguity and uncertainty, and improved Keywords — Humanlike Perception, Sensor Fusion, resolution [8].
    [Show full text]
  • 1 What Do Models of Visual Perception Tell Us About Visual Phenomenology?
    What do models of visual perception tell us about visual phenomenology? Rachel N. Denison1, Ned Block2, Jason Samaha3 1 Department of Psychology and Center for Neural Science, New York University 2 Department of Philosophy, New York University 3 Department of Psychology, University of California, Santa Cruz 1 Abstract Computational models of visual processing aim to provide a compact, explanatory account of the complex neural processes that underlie visual perception and behavior. But what, if anything, do current modeling approaches say about how conscious visual experience arises from neural processing? Here, we introduce the reader to four commonly used models for understanding visual computations, neural activity, and behavior: signal detection theory, drift diffusion, probabilistic population codes, and sampling. In an attempt to bridge these modeling approaches with experimental and philosophical work on the neural basis of conscious visual perception, we lay out possible relationships between the components of the models and the contents of phenomenal visual experience. We find no unique relation between model components and phenomenal experience in any model; rather, there are multiple logically possible mappings from models to experience. Going forward, we suggest that there are scientific opportunities to develop models that predict and explain a variety of subjective reports and philosophical opportunities to consider what aspects of phenomenal experience are promising scientific targets. Keywords: vision, perception, consciousness, subjective report, computational model 2 1 Introduction The science of visual perception has a long history of developing quantitative, computational models to explain and predict visual performance on a variety of tasks. These models have typically been developed to account for objective visual performance—like observer’s accuracy, reaction time, or perceptual sensitivity in discriminating different visual stimuli.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 7 Information Theory and Sensory Perception
    Chapter 7 Information theory and sensory perception M.D. Plumbley & S.A. Abdallah Department of Electronic Engineering, Queen Mary University of London, London, UK. Abstract In this chapter, we explore Shannon’s information theory and what it may tell us about the biological processes of sensory perception. We begin by discussing some historical theories of sensory perception, including concepts of objects and invariances as well as principles from Gestalt psychology. We consider the ecological principle that perception should be useful for an organism, and introduce information theory as a possible way to measure this usefulness. After introducing some of the key concepts from information theory, such as entropy, information, redundancy and factorial coding, we draw parallels between communication in engineering systems and sensory perception. We discuss Attneave’s early proposal that perception should create an economical description of sensory inputs, as measured by information theory, and Barlow’s suggestion of lateral inhibition as a possible mechanism to achieve this. We discuss the important role played by noise in an information processing system, and its importance when determining how to optimise the communication of information. This leads to the concept of information-optimal filters which change their characteristics at different signal-to-noise levels, a feature exhibited by fly and human visual systems. For information processed across topographic maps, optimal information processing leads to a principle of uniform information density, whereby a larger area in the cortex allows higher information density, and hence higher accuracy or sensitivity, at the corresponding sensors. We also discuss some recent investigations of information theory applied to spiking neural systems, and the concept of economy of impulses.
    [Show full text]
  • Defining the Role of Attention in Hierarchical Auditory Processing
    Review Defining the Role of Attention in Hierarchical Auditory Processing Caitlin N. Price 1,2,* and Deborah Moncrieff 1,2 1 Institute for Intelligent Systems, University of Memphis, Memphis, TN 38152, USA; [email protected] 2 School of Communication Sciences & Disorders, University of Memphis, Memphis, TN 38152, USA * Correspondence: [email protected] Abstract: Communication in noise is a complex process requiring efficient neural encoding through- out the entire auditory pathway as well as contributions from higher-order cognitive processes (i.e., attention) to extract speech cues for perception. Thus, identifying effective clinical interventions for individuals with speech-in-noise deficits relies on the disentanglement of bottom-up (sensory) and top-down (cognitive) factors to appropriately determine the area of deficit; yet, how attention may interact with early encoding of sensory inputs remains unclear. For decades, attentional the- orists have attempted to address this question with cleverly designed behavioral studies, but the neural processes and interactions underlying attention’s role in speech perception remain unresolved. While anatomical and electrophysiological studies have investigated the neurological structures contributing to attentional processes and revealed relevant brain–behavior relationships, recent elec- trophysiological techniques (i.e., simultaneous recording of brainstem and cortical responses) may provide novel insight regarding the relationship between early sensory processing and top-down at- tentional influences. In this article, we review relevant theories that guide our present understanding of attentional processes, discuss current electrophysiological evidence of attentional involvement in auditory processing across subcortical and cortical levels, and propose areas for future study that will inform the development of more targeted and effective clinical interventions for individuals with speech-in-noise deficits.
    [Show full text]
  • The Function of Perception
    The Function of Perception Peter J. Graham 1 Fitness, Functions, and Functional Analysis I believe human perceptual systems—especially visual systems—have producing reliably accurate perceptual representations as a biological function (Graham 2010 , 2012 , 2014 ). I defend this against an argument from Tyler Burge. Burge argues that perceptual states cannot have representing accurately as a biological function, for there is a “root mismatch” between representational success and failure, on the one hand, and biological success and failure, on the other. Truth and accuracy are seman- tical, not practical, matters, and biology only cares about practical matters. Representational success and failure thus cannot be biological functions of any psy- chological state or system. Burge is not alone, as many have argued that truth and accuracy cannot be biological functions. 1 I shall argue this isn’t necessarily so. In the fi rst Sect. 1 say a few words about biological functions before saying why, in the second, I think human perception has accurately representing the environment as a biological function. In the third and fourth I state Burge’s case for thinking this isn’t so. In the fi fth I explain why Burge’s grounds do not make his case and then in the sixth I critically examine an example Burge offers to buttress his case. In the seventh I say why the issue matters to Burge and why, even though I reject his argument, we are not at cross-purposes. 2 There is an everyday sense of ‘fi tness’ and a technical sense. I trust we would all like to stay fi t—to stay in shape.
    [Show full text]
  • The Color of Smell
    The Color of Smell A cross-modal interactive installation for individual expression Hannah Weiser Interaction Design Master’s Program One-year master 15 Credits Spring semester 2016 Supervisor: Simon Niedenthal [Main field of study – See the programme syllabus for the main field of study] [Level, specify Bachelor, One-year master or Two-year master] [Specify the number of credits for this thesis] [Semester/Year when this thesis is submitted] Supervisor: [First name Surname] “The Color of Smell” A cross-modal interactive installation for individual expression Table of Content 1. Abstract 5 2. Introduction 5-6 3. Research Questions 6 4. Theory 7-16 4.1 The potential of smell: Psychological and physiological properties 4.2 Olfactory communication in HCI 4.3 The olfactory medium 4.4 Smell in a cross-modal context 4.5 Synesthetic Design - A cross-sensory approach 4.5.1 Synesthetic perception 4.5.2 Embodied Cognition in the context of synesthetic perception 4.6 Cross-sensory connections for the creation of Synesthetic Design 4.6.1 Cross-modal analogy 4.6.2 Concrete association - iconic conncetion 4.6.3 Symbolic connection 4.7 The benefits of Synesthetic Design 5. Related work - relevant examples 17-20 5.1 Lexus - A Journey Through the Senses 5.2 Odor Emoticons, Olfacticons: An olfactory application that conveys emotion 5.3 The Sound of Touch 5.4 The I/O Brush: Drawing with Everyday Objects 6. Methods 21-23 6.1 Research Through Design 6.2 Co-Design 6.3 Prototyping 6.3.1 The Wizard of Oz 6.3.2 Rapid video prototyping 7.
    [Show full text]
  • Introductory Psychology Chapter 4: Sensation & Perception Winter 2014
    Van Selst Introductory Psychology Chapter 4: Sensation & Perception Winter 2014 Sensation and Perception Chapter 4 of Feist & Rosenberg Psychology: Perspectives & Connections Chapter 4: Sensation & Perception Sensation: receiving physical stimulation, encoding the input into the nervous system; The processes by which our sensory organs receive information from the environment. Perception: the process by which people select, organize, and interpret (recognize) the sensory information, the act of understanding what the sensation represents Transduction: Physical energy neural impulses Chapter 4: Sensation & Perception Absolute threshold: the minimum amount of stimulus required for a percept (note: “sub-liminal” perception is perception below the threshold of consciousness); the amount of stimulation required for a stimulus to be detected 50% of the time. Jnd: just noticeable difference: smallest difference between stimuli that people can detect 50% of the time. Weber’s law: physical intensity vs perceptual (psychological) experience; the idea that the jnd of a stimulus is a constant proportion despite variations in intensity. (2% change for weight; 10% change for loudness; 20% for taste of salt) Sensory adaption: a decline in senstitivity to a stimulus that occurs as a result of constant exposure. e.g., the perceived loudness of a nightclub or a plane Chapter 4: Sensation & Perception Signal-Detection Theory: statistical model of decision making (Sensitivity & Bias) Chapter 4: Sensation & Perception The five classic senses: • Vision (day,
    [Show full text]
  • Object Apprehension Using Vision and Touch
    Object Apprehension Using Vision and Touch R. Bajcsy and S.A. Stansfield ._ University of Pennsylvania [ i) " ;'_ Philadelphia, PA 19104 [ ....... 1. Abstract ._._ ..... We define object apprehension as the determination of the properties of an object and the rela;t|bnships among these properties. W_t contrast tla!s_with recognition, which goes a step further to attach a label to/the object as a whole. Apprehension_ls_rfi_d_ental ,to manipulation. This is true whether the manipulation is t:161ngcarried out by an autonomous ro,.Ipo_s"thi3 result of teleoperatlon involving sensory feedback. W6 present an apprehension paradigm using both vision and touch. In this model, we define a representation for object apprehension in terms of aset of primitives and features, along with their relationships. This representation is the mechanism by which the data from the two modallties is combined. It Is also the mechanism which drives the apprehension process. 2. Introduction It h_s been suggested by both psychologists and perceptual roboticists that objects are defined In terms of their Parts and features. It has also been suggested that these features determine not only our recognition of objects, 10ut also our interactions with them. It seems reasonable to say that these features (along with their relationships] are the outputs of the perceptual system. Ore '!rst task, then, in building a robotic perceptual system is to determine what this fixed set of features will be. This is also vital to our representation pardigm, since these features r_ust form the building blocks of objects wh!ch are to be manipulated by the system. We have chosen a hierarchical representation for objects which consists, at the lowest level, of a set of modality dependent primitives.
    [Show full text]
  • Psychology of Auditory Perception Andrew Lotto1∗ and Lori Holt2
    Overview Psychology of auditory perception Andrew Lotto1∗ and Lori Holt2 Audition is often treated as a ‘secondary’ sensory system behind vision in the study of cognitive science. In this review, we focus on three seemingly simple perceptual tasks to demonstrate the complexity of perceptual–cognitive processing involved in everyday audition. After providing a short overview of the characteristics of sound and their neural encoding, we present a description of the perceptual task of segregating multiple sound events that are mixed together in the signal reaching the ears. Then, we discuss the ability to localize the sound source in the environment. Finally, we provide some data and theory on how listeners categorize complex sounds, such as speech. In particular, we present research on how listeners weigh multiple acoustic cues in making a categorization decision. One conclusion of this review is that it is time for auditory cognitive science to be developed to match what has been done in vision in order for us to better understand how humans communicate with speech and music. 2010 John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. WIREs Cogn Sci 2010 DOI: 10.1002/wcs.123 INTRODUCTION a person spoke and a dog barked and asked you to name the number, location, and identity of these magine sitting on a pier with a friend over a sound sources—you would find the challenge much Iswimming beach where the swimmers are out of less intimidating (though you may still question your your direct view. Your friend offers you this challenge: quality of friend). The ability of the auditory system from the movement of the water waves that you see to segregate, locate, and categorize events in the below, can you tell how many swimmers there are? environment is a remarkable accomplishment given Where are these swimmers relative to each other? the complexity and transient nature of sound waves.
    [Show full text]
  • The Use of Illusory Visual Information in Perception and Action
    I Medische E;t:JliDtheek !2oo.)" E.U.R. ~~ ~ The Use of Illusory Visual Information in Perception and Action Het gebruik van illusoire visuele informatie in perceptie en actie Proefschrift ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor aan de Erasmus Universiteit Rotterdam op gezag van de rector magnificus Prof.dr. S.W.J. Lamberts en volgens besluit van het College voor Promoties. De openbare verdediging zal plaatsvinden op donderdag 19 mei 2005 om 13.30 uur door Denise Desiree J osefina de Grave geboren te Winterswijk Promotiecommissie Promotor: Prof.dr. J.G.G. Borst Overige leden: Dr. M.A. Frens Prof.dr. C.J. Erkelens Prof.dr. C.I. de Zeeuw Copromotoren: Dr. E. Brenner Dr. J.B.J. Smeets Dit proefschrift werd mede mogelijk gemaakt door financiele steun van de Nederlandse Organisatie voor Wetenschappelijk Onderzoek (NWO), gebied Maatschappij- en Gedragswetenschappen (MaGW), dossiemummer 490-22-lSOb. Contents Contents Chapter 1 5 General Introduction Chapter 2 17 Are the original and the induced Roelofs effect caused by the same shift in straight ahead? Chapter3 31 Effects ofthe Ebbinghaus figure on grasping are not only due to misjudged size Chapter4 45 The coding of pointing movements ChapterS 61 The coding of saccades Chapter 6 75 Summary and conclusions Hoofdstuk6 87 Samenvatting en conclusies References 95 Dankwoord 107 Curriculum Vitae 109 Publications Ill Chapter 1 General introduction Chapter 1 Humans constantly interact with objects in the environment (e.g. grasp a pencil for writing or pick up a cup of tea) without making many mistakes in these performed actions. To guide these actions, visual information is used.
    [Show full text]
  • Perceptual Co-Reference
    Perceptual Co-Reference Michael Rescorla Abstract: The perceptual system estimates distal conditions based upon proximal sensory input. It typically exploits information from multiple cues across and within modalities: it estimates shape based upon visual and haptic cues; it estimates depth based upon convergence, binocular disparity, motion parallax, and other visual cues; and so on. Bayesian models illuminate the computations through which the perceptual system combines sensory cues. I review key aspects of these models. Based on my review, I argue that we should posit co-referring perceptual representations corresponding to distinct sensory cues. For example, the perceptual system represents a distal size using a representation canonically linked with vision and a distinct representation canonically linked with touch. Distinct co-referring perceptual representations represent the same denotation, but they do so under different modes of presentation. Bayesian cue combination models demonstrate that psychological explanation of perception should attend to mode of presentation and not simply to denotation. §1. Sensory cue combination A familiar picture holds that mental activity involves computation over mental representations (Fodor, 1975, 2008; Gallistel and King, 2009; Pylyshyn, 1984). This paper will discuss representations that figure in computations executed by the perceptual system. My focus is sensory cue combination. The perceptual system estimates distal conditions (e.g. shapes, sizes, colors, and locations of distal objects) based upon proximal sensory input 2 (e.g. retinal stimulations, or vibrations in the inner ear, or muscle spindle activity). When estimating distal conditions, the perceptual system typically exploits relevant information from multiple sensory modalities. If you see a barking dog across the park, then you receive both visual and auditory information relevant to the dog’s location.
    [Show full text]
  • Bayesian Natural Selection and the Evolution of Perceptual Systems
    Received 13 September 2001 Accepted 13 November 2001 Published online 22 April 2002 Bayesian natural selection and the evolution of perceptual systems Wilson S. Geisler* and Randy L. Diehl Department of Psychology and Center for Perceptual Systems, University of Texas at Austin TX 78712, Austin, USA In recent years, there has been much interest in characterizing statistical properties of natural stimuli in order to better understand the design of perceptual systems. A fruitful approach has been to compare the processing of natural stimuli in real perceptual systems with that of ideal observers derived within the framework of Bayesian statistical decision theory. While this form of optimization theory has provided a deeper understanding of the information contained in natural stimuli as well as of the computational principles employed in perceptual systems, it does not directly consider the process of natural selection, which is ultimately responsible for design. Here we propose a formal framework for analysing how the statistics of natural stimuli and the process of natural selection interact to determine the design of percep- tual systems. The framework consists of two complementary components. The rst is a maximum tness ideal observer, a standard Bayesian ideal observer with a utility function appropriate for natural selection. The second component is a formal version of natural selection based upon Bayesian statistical decision theory. Maximum tness ideal observers and Bayesian natural selection are demonstrated in several examples. We suggest that the Bayesian approach is appropriate not only for the study of perceptual systems but also for the study of many other systems in biology. 1.
    [Show full text]