CV Marko Malink.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

CV Marko Malink.Pdf Curriculum Vitae Marko Malink New York University New York University Department of Philosophy Department of Classics 5 Washington Place 100 Washington Square East New York, NY 10003 New York, NY 10003 Email: [email protected] PERSONAL DATA born on February 2nd, 1980 in Bautzen (Germany) German citizen, US permanent resident RESEARCH INTERESTS AOS: Ancient Philosophy, especially Ancient Logic AOC: Leibniz, Philosophical Logic, History of Logic, Philosophy of Language EMPLOYMENT 2018– New York University, Professor of Philosophy and Classics 2014–18 New York University, Associate Professor of Philosophy and Classics 2013–14 University of Chicago, Associate Professor of Philosophy 2011–13 University of Chicago, Assistant Professor of Philosophy 2007–11 Humboldt University Berlin, Wissenschaftlicher Mitarbeiter 2004–07 University of Leipzig, Wissenschaftlicher Mitarbeiter, part-time EDUCATION 2008 Dr. Phil., Humboldt University Berlin (Philosophy) 2005–06 University of Oxford, Recognised Student (Philosophy) 2004 M. A., University of Leipzig (Logic and Theory of Science, Ancient Greek, Sorbian Studies) HONORS 2018 Philosopher’s Annual selection for ‘Aristotle on Principles as Elements’, chosen as one of the ten best philosophy papers published in 2017 2016 Philosopher’s Annual selection for ‘The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle’s Topics vs. Prior Analytics’, chosen as one of the ten best philosophy papers published in 2015 2015-16 Humboldt University Berlin, Visiting Fellow, summer 2015 and 2016 2013 Philosopher’s Annual selection for ‘A Method of Modal Proof in Aristotle’ (with Jacob Rosen), chosen as one of the ten best philosophy papers published in 2012 CV, Marko Malink, 5 November 2019 1 2008–09 Rutgers University, visiting scholar at Department of Philosophy 2005–07 doctoral fellowship, German National Academic Foundation 2000–04 fellowship, German National Academic Foundation PUBLICATIONS Book: 2013 Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic, Harvard University Press Reviews: Angelelli, I., Mathematical Reviews (2016), MR3185722 Beere, J., Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90 (2015), 742–747 Bronstein, D., Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90 (2015), 724–732 Crivelli, P., Phronesis 60 (2015), 129–132 Kirby, J., Journal of the History of Philosophy 52 (2014), 838–840 Leunissen, M., Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90 (2015), 733–741 Pakaluk, M., Bryn Mawr Classical Review 2014.03.04 Raymond, D., History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (2014), 209–211 Rosen, J., Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2014.08.33 Uckelman, S., Metascience 23 (2014), 573–579 Articles: forthc. ‘Aristotle on Direct and Indirect Demonstration’, in The Routledge Handbook of Metaphysical Ground, ed. M. Raven, New York: Routledge forthc. ‘Aristotle and Bolzano on Grounding’, in Priority Among Truths: Bernard Bolzano’s Philosophy of Grounding, ed. B. Schnieder and S. Roski, Oxford: Oxford University Press forthc. ‘Modalities and Modal Logic’, in The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Logic, ed. L. Castagnoli, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press forthc. ‘The Peripatetic Program in Categorical Logic: Leibniz on Propositional Terms’ (with Anubav Vasudevan), in Review of Symbolic Logic 2020 ‘Demonstration by reductio ad impossibile in Posterior Analytics 1.26’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 58 2020 ‘Hypothetical Syllogisms and Infinite Regress’, in Epistemology after Sextus Empiricus, ed. K. Vogt and J. Vlasits, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 129–151 2019 ‘Leibniz on the Logic of Conceptual Containment and Coincidence’ (with Anubav Vasudevan), in Leibniz and the Structure of Sciences: Modern Perspectives on the History of Logic, Mathematics, Epistemology, ed. V. De Risi, Cham: Springer, 1–46 2017 ‘Leibniz’s Theory of Propositional Terms: A Reply to Massimo Mugnai’ (with Anubav Vasudevan), Leibniz Review 27, 139–155 2017 ‘Aristotle on Principles as Elements’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 53, 163– 213 2016 ‘The Logic of Leibniz’s Generales inquisitiones de analysi notionum et veritatum’ (with Anubav Vasudevan), Review of Symbolic Logic 9, 686–751 2016 ‘Aristotle on One-Sided Possibility’, in Logical Modalities from Aristotle to Carnap: The Story of Necessity, ed. M. Cresswell, E. Mares, and A. Rini, New York: Cambridge University Press, 29–49 CV, Marko Malink, 5 November 2019 2 2015 ‘The Beginnings of Formal Logic: Deduction in Aristotle’s Topics vs. Prior Analytics’, Phronesis 60, 267–309 2015 ‘Précis of Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic’ and ‘Replies to Beere, Bronstein, and Leunissen’, book symposium on Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90, 716–723 and 748–762 2014 ‘Deduction in Sophistici Elenchi 6’, in Strategies of Argument: Essays in Ancient Ethics, Epistemology, and Logic, ed. Mi-Kyoung Lee, New York: Oxford University Press, 149–174 2013 ‘Proof by Assumption of the Possible in Prior Analytics 1. 15’ (with Jacob Rosen), Mind 122, 953-986 2013 ‘Aristotle on Circular Proof’, Phronesis 58, 215–248 2013 ‘Essence and Being: A Discussion of Michail Peramatzis, Priority in Aristotle’s Metaphysics’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 45, 341–360 2012 ‘A Method of Modal Proof in Aristotle’ (with Jacob Rosen), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 42, 179–261 2012 ‘Figures of Prosleptic Syllogisms in Prior Analytics 2.7’, Classical Quarterly 62, 163– 178 2011 four handbook articles: ‘Organon’, ‘Modalitäten’, ‘Syllogismos’, ‘Wirkung: Logik’, in Aristoteles–Handbuch, ed. C. Rapp & K. Corcilius, Stuttgart: Metzler, 65–74, 275–80, 343–8, and 480–4 2009 ‘A Non-Extensional Notion of Conversion in the Organon’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 37, 105–141 2009 ‘Indeterminate Propositions in Prior Analytics 1.41’, Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 12, 165–189 2008 ‘ΤΩΙ vs ΤΩΝ in Prior Analytics 1.1–22’, Classical Quarterly 58, 519–536 2007 ‘Categories in Topics 1.9’, Rhizai. Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 4, 271– 294 2006 ‘A Reconstruction of Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic’, History and Philosophy of Logic 27, 95–141 Reviews and Translations: 2015 Translation into German of Prior Analytics II (with N. Strobach), in: Analytica Priora, Buch II, übersetzt von N. Strobach und M. Malink, erläutert von N. Strobach, de Gruyter: Berlin, 1–44 2012 Review of L. Castagnoli: Ancient Self-Refutation: The Logic and History of the Self- Refutation Argument from Democritus to Augustine (Cambridge UP), in: Classical Philology 107, 367–371 2009 Review of Th. Ebert & U. Nortmann: Aristoteles. Analytica priora, Buch I (Akademie Verlag Berlin); in: History and Philosophy of Logic 30, 389–396 2008 Review of J. Barnes: Truth, etc. Six Lectures in Ancient Logic (Oxford UP); in: Gnomon 80, 676–681 CV, Marko Malink, 5 November 2019 3 2006 Review of P. Crivelli: Aristotle on Truth (Cambridge UP); in: Philosophie Antique 6, 208–211 OTHER PUBLICATIONS In Linguistics: 2008 ‘Phase Structures and Quantification’, Event Structures in Linguistic Form and Interpretation, J. Dölling et al. (ed.), Berlin: de Gruyter, 413–434 2008 ‘Right Boundary Achievements under Conative Negation’, The Discourse Potential of Underspecified Structures, A. Steube (ed.), Berlin: de Gruyter, 145–162 See: C. Piñón, “Negating Right Boundary Achievements (Comments on Malink)”, ibid., 163–175 2008 ‘Russian, Czech and Upper Sorbian uže / už / hižo and Aspectual Relations’ (with T. Heyde-Zybatow), Formal Description of Slavic Languages: FDSL 5, G. Zybatow et al. (ed.), Frankfurt a. M.: Peter Lang, 201–212 2008 ‘Clitic Climbing and Theta-Roles in Upper Sorbian and Czech’ (with Š. Lešnerová), Formal Description of Slavic Languages: FDSL 5, G. Zybatow et al. (ed.), Frankfurt a. M.: Peter Lang, 396–407 2003 ‘Phasenpartikeln und Verbklassen’ (with T. Zybatow), Proceedings of the Conference sub7 – Sinn und Bedeutung, Arbeitspapier 114 des FB Sprachwissenschaft der Universität Konstanz, M. Weisgerber (ed.), 337–351 2001 ‘Zur dreidimensionalen Modellierung der Phasenpartikeln um schon’ (with I. Max), Linguistische Arbeitsberichte 76, Institut für Linguistik der Universität Leipzig, J. Dölling and G. Zybatov (ed.), 89–120 In Sorbian Studies: 2014 ‘Friedrich Nietzsches Slawische Vorfahren’, in Europa Erlesen: Lausitz /Łužica, ed. by M. Retschke, Klagenfurt: Wieser Verlag, 102–109 2008 ‘Słowjanski pochad Friedricha W. Nietzscheho’, Rozhlad, 43–48 2006 (ed.) Serbska Poezija 52: Matej Urban, Bautzen: Domowina 2005 ‘Arno Schmidt a Łužicy’, Rozhlad, 127–133 2004 ‘Besprechung, Heilung und Musik – M. A. Pohles Dissertation von 1706’, Beiträge zur slawischen Musik in Mitteldeutschland, B. Greiner and K. Rebling (ed.), Frankfurt a. M.: Peter Lang, 25–38 PRESENTATIONS 08/2020 ‘Aristotle’s Categories 7, 6a36–7b14’, 22nd Symposium Aristotelicum, University of Oslo 07/2020 TBA, Seminar on the Logic of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Fernuniversität Hagen, Campus Leipzig 07/2020 TBA, Birkbeck College London, Aristotle Workshop 05/2020 TBA, Workshop Induction from Aristotle to Galileo, Stockholm 04/2020 ‘Aristotle on demonstration by reductio ad impossibile’, Session on the History of Logic, APA Pacific Meeting, San Francisco CV, Marko Malink, 5 November 2019 4 02/2020 TBA, Conference Pragmatic Argumentation in the History of Philosophy, Swedish Institute at Rome 11/2019 ‘Peripatetic Connexive Logic’ (with Anubav Vasudevan), 5th Workshop on Connexive Logics, Ruhr-Universität Bochum 11/2019 ‘Introducing Posterior Analytics 1.26’, Workshop on Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics, Paris 10/2019 ‘Signification and Essence in Metaphysics Γ 4’, Conference on Aristotle’s Metaphysics
Recommended publications
  • The Place of Ethics in Aristotle's Philosophy
    Offprint from OXFORDSTUDIES INANCIENT PHILOSOPHY EDITOR:BRADINWOOD VOLUMEXL Essays in Memory of Michael Frede JAMESALLEN EYJÓLFURKJALAREMILSSON WOLFGANG-RAINERMANN BENJAMINMORISON 3 THEPLACEOFETHICSIN ARISTOTLE’SPHILOSOPHY GEORGEKARAMANOLIS . The issue D the wealth of studies on Aristotle’s ethics, there has been almost nothing, as far as I know, dedicated to considering the place that ethics occupies in Aristotle’s philosophy. This issue does not seem to be interesting to modern students of Aristotle. There was, however, a debate and indeed a controversy about this issue in late antiquity, as I shall show in this paper. There are two questions in- volved here, which are interrelated, and the debate was about both of them. The first concerns the order in which ethics or practical philosophy, more generally, must be studied by the student of Aris- totle’s philosophy. The second concerns the relative significance of this part of philosophy within the framework of Aristotle’s philoso- phical work. Both questions arise from remarks that Aristotle himself makes. The second in particular, some might argue, is addressed by Aris- totle in various parts of his work. In Metaphysics Ε –, for instance, he famously discusses the relative value of theoretical, practical, and productive sciences. Aristotle there argues explicitly that the the- oretical sciences are preferable (hairetōterai) to all others, practical © George Karamanolis It is a pleasure to offer this contribution in honour of Michael Frede, who taught me so much. Drafts of this paper were presented at Princeton, Oxford, and the Department of Theory and Philosophy of Science, University of Athens. I have benefited from the comments of all these audiences.
    [Show full text]
  • Aspasian Infidelities. on Aspasius' Philosophical Background (EN I)
    apeiron 2016; 49(2): 229–259 António Pedro Mesquita* Aspasian Infidelities. On Aspasius’ Philosophical Background (EN I) DOI 10.1515/apeiron-2015-0028 Abstract: The discussion on Aspasius’ philosophical background has benefited in recent years from a wide consensus. According to this consensus, Aspasius should be regarded as a Peripatetic, or even as an “orthodox Peripatetic” (Barnes’ phrase). It is true that Aspasius’ commentary is generally in tune with Aristotle. It is true that he shows an extensive knowledge of Aristotelian research pertinent for the discussions and that he uses Aristotelian concepts, principles, and doctrines with ease as if they were his own, thus denoting an old assimila- tion of those materials and a long accommodation to them. In a word, it is true that Aspasius is an Aristotelian. He is, however, as I will try to show in this paper, an Aristotelian strongly influenced by Stoicism. I will do so by selecting those points from Aspasius’ commentary on book I of the Nicomachean Ethics where the Stoic influence is most flagrantly evident, namely in his interpretation of art (τέχνη), his conception of continence and incontinence and, especially, his interpretation of the relation between happiness, virtue, and external goods in Aristotle. Keywords: Aspasius, Aristotelianism, Stoicism, happiness, virtue, external goods The Consensus The discussion on Aspasius’ philosophical background has benefited in recent years from a wide consensus. A good example of this consensus is the position Barnes sustains on the matter in his excellent “Introduction to Aspasius”, where he states the following1: Next, Aspasius’ philosophical position. Galen calls him a Peripatetic, and it is plain that his pupil taught Galen Peripatetic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelianism in the First Century BC
    CHAPTER 5 Aristotelianism in the First Century BC Andrea Falcon 1 A New Generation of Peripatetic Philosophers The division of the Peripatetic tradition into a Hellenistic and a post- Hellenistic period is not a modern invention. It is already accepted in antiquity. Aspasius speaks of an old and a new generation of Peripatetic philosophers. Among the philosophers who belong to the new generation, he singles out Andronicus of Rhodes and Boethus of Sidon.1 Strabo adopts a similar division. He too distinguishes between the older Peripatetics, who came immediately after Theophrastus, and their successors.2 He collectively describes the latter as better able to do philosophy in the manner of Aristotle (φιλοσοφεῖν καὶ ἀριστοτελίζειν). It remains unclear what Strabo means by doing philosophy in the manner of Aristotle.3 But he certainly thinks that the philosophers who belong to the new generation, and not those who belong to the old one, deserve the title of true Aristotelians. For Strabo, the event separating the old from the new Peripatos is the rediscovery and publication of Aristotle’s writings. We may want to resist Strabo’s negative characterization of the earlier Peripatetics. For Strabo, they were not able to engage in philosophy in any seri- ous way but were content to declaim general theses.4 This may be an unfair judgment, ultimately based on the anachronistic assumption that any serious philosophy requires engagement with an authoritative text.5 Still, the empha- sis that Strabo places on the rediscovery of Aristotle’s writings suggests that the latter were at the center of the critical engagement with Aristotle in the 1 Aspasius, On Aristotle’s Ethics 44.20–45.16.
    [Show full text]
  • Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-48147-2 — Scale, Space and Canon in Ancient Literary Culture Reviel Netz Index More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-108-48147-2 — Scale, Space and Canon in Ancient Literary Culture Reviel Netz Index More Information Index Aaker, Jennifer, 110, 111 competition, 173 Abdera, 242, 310, 314, 315, 317 longevity, 179 Abel, N. H., 185 Oresteia, 197, 200, 201 Academos, 189, 323, 324, 325, 337 papyri, 15 Academy, 322, 325, 326, 329, 337, 343, 385, 391, Persians, 183 399, 404, 427, 434, 448, 476, 477–8, 512 portraits, 64 Achilles Tatius, 53, 116, 137, 551 Ptolemaic era, 39 papyri, 16, 23 Aeschylus (astronomer), 249 Acta Alexandrinorum, 87, 604 Aesop, 52, 68, 100, 116, 165 adespota, 55, 79, 81–5, 86, 88, 91, 99, 125, 192, 194, in education, 42 196, 206, 411, 413, 542, 574 papyri, 16, 23 Adkin, Neil, 782 Aethiopia, 354 Adrastus, 483 Aetia, 277 Adrastus (mathematician), 249 Africa, 266 Adrianople, 798 Agatharchides, 471 Aedesius (martyr), 734, 736 Agathocles (historian), 243 Aegae, 479, 520 Agathocles (peripatetic), 483 Aegean, 338–43 Agathon, 280 Aegina, 265 Agias (historian), 373 Aelianus (Platonist), 484 agrimensores, 675 Aelius Aristides, 133, 657, 709 Ai Khanoum, 411 papyri, 16 Akhmatova, Anna, 186 Aelius Herodian (grammarian), 713 Albertus Magnus, 407 Aelius Promotus, 583 Albinus, 484 Aenesidemus, 478–9, 519, 520 Alcaeus, 49, 59, 61–2, 70, 116, 150, 162, 214, 246, Aeolia, 479 see also Aeolian Aeolian, 246 papyri, 15, 23 Aeschines, 39, 59, 60, 64, 93, 94, 123, 161, 166, 174, portraits, 65, 67 184, 211, 213, 216, 230, 232, 331 Alcidamas, 549 commentaries, 75 papyri, 16 Ctesiphon, 21 Alcinous, 484 False Legation, 22 Alcmaeon, 310
    [Show full text]
  • The Phenomenon of Chance in Ancient Greek Thought
    THE PHENOMENON OF CHANCE IN ANCIENT GREEK THOUGHT by MELISSA M. SHEW A DISSERTATION Presented to the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate School ofthe University ofOregon in partial fulfillment ofthe requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy September 2008 11 University of Oregon Graduate School Confirmation of Approval and Acceptance of Dissertation prepared by: Melissa Shew Title: "The Phenomenon of Chance in Ancient Greek Thought" This dissertation has been accepted and approved in partial fulfillment ofthe requirements for the degree in the Department ofPhilosophy by: Peter Warnek, Chairperson, Philosophy John Lysaker, Member, Philosophy Ted Toadvine, Member, Philosophy James Crosswhite, Outside Member, English and Richard Linton, Vice President for Research and Graduate Studies/Dean ofthe Graduate School for the University of Oregon. September 6, 2008 Original approval signatures are on file with the Graduate School and the University of Oregon Libraries. 111 An Abstract of the Dissertation of Melissa M. Shew for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy to be taken September 2008 Title: THE PHENOMENON OF CHANCE IN ANCIENT GREEK THOUGHT Approved: Dr. Peter Warnek This dissertation engages three facets of Greek philosophy: 1) the phenomenon of tyche (chance, fortune, happening, or luck) in Aristotle's Physics, Nicomachean Ethics, and Poetics; 2) how tyche infonns Socrates' own philosophical practice in the Platonic dialogues; and 3) how engaging tyche in these Greek texts challenges established interpretations of Greek thought in contemporary scholarship and discussion. I argue that the complex status of tyche in Aristotle's texts, when combined with its appearance in the Platonic dialogues and the framework of Greek myth and poetry (poiesis), underscores the seriousness with which the Greeks consider the role of chance in human life.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 INSTRUMENTS and IMPEDIMENTS Α Senecan
    vendredi 25 mars 14h-16h Comments welcome: [email protected] 1 Maison de la Recherche D116 INSTRUMENTS AND IMPEDIMENTS Α Senecan-Aristotelian debate on the activation of the virtues My starting point is a notoriously ambiguous chapter in Aristotle. It’s well known that in Nicomachean Ethics 1.10, Aristotle rejects the view that virtuous activity is sufficient all by itself for happiness. Instead he asserts that while eudaimonia does consist in a life of virtuous activity, certain external goods, things like health, wealth, and freedom from pain, are also necessary in some sense. But in what sense? The text leaves room for interpretation: whether Aristotle means that such things are components of the best human life, such that happiness is incomplete without them, or whether they are instrumentally necessary for the best life – what we need to use to perform virtuous activities in the best way; and there are further questions about each of these possibilities. In this paper I am not seeking to provide an answer to what Aristotle meant. My interest is rather in the interpretive space defined by that ambiguity, and in what happened next in ancient philosophy within that interpretive space. I explore a series of texts in which the so- called Peripatetic philosophers, responding to Aristotle, give their accounts of the relation between happiness and external goods – and the Stoics, represented by Seneca, give their version, responding to the Peripatetics. The star player is what I call the activation argument. Some Peripatetics hold, picking up on certain things in Aristotle, that virtue is not sufficient for happiness because virtue can’t be activated—can’t give rise to any virtuous activities—without having some external goods.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Synopsis of the Aristotelian Commentary Tradition (In Less Than Sixty Minutes)
    HISTORICAL SYNOPSIS OF THE ARISTOTELIAN COMMENTARY TRADITION (IN LESS THAN SIXTY MINUTES) Fred D. Miller, Jr. CHAPTER 1 PERIPATETIC SCHOLARS Aristotle of Stagira (384–322 BCE) Exoteric works: Protrepticus, On Philosophy, Eudemus, etc. Esoteric works: Categories, Physics, De Caelo, Metaphysics, De Anima, etc. The legend of Aristotle’s misappropriated works Andronicus of Rhodes: first edition of Aristotle’s works (40 BCE) Early Peripatetic commentators Boethus of Sidon (c. 75—c. 10 BCE) comm. on Categories Alexander of Aegae (1st century CE)comm. on Categories and De Caelo Adrastus of Aphrodisias (early 1st century) comm. on Categories Aspasius (c. 131) comm. on Nicomachean Ethics Emperor Marcus Aurelius establishes four chairs of philosophy in Athens: Platonic, Peripatetic, Stoic, Epicurean (c. 170) Alexander of Aphrodisias (late 2nd —early 3rd century) Extant commentaries on Prior Analytics, De Sensu, etc. Lost comm. on Physics, De Caelo, etc. Exemplar for all subsequent commentators. Comm. on Aristotle’s Metaphysics Only books 1—5 of Alexander’s comm. are genuine; books 6—14 are by ps.-Alexander . whodunit? Themistius (c. 317—c. 388) Paraphrases of Physics, De Anima, etc. Paraphrase of Metaphysics Λ (Hebrew translation) Last of the Peripatetics CHAPTER 2 NEOPLATONIC SCHOLARS Origins of Neoplatonism Ammonius Saccas (c. 175—242) forefather of Neoplatonism Plotinus (c. 205—260) the Enneads Reality explained in terms of hypostases: THE ONE—> THE INTELLECT—>WORLD SOUL—>PERCEPTIBLE WORLD Porphyry of Tyre (232–309) Life of Plotinus On the School of Plato and Aristotle Being One On the Difference Between Plato and Aristotle Isagoge (Introduction to Aristotle’s Categories) What is Neoplatonism? A broad intellectual movement based on the philosophy of Plotinus that sought to incorporate and reconcile the doctrines of Plato, Pythagoras, and Aristotle with each other and with the universal beliefs and practices of popular religion (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Theophrastus of Eresus Commentary Volume 6.1
    TheophrastusofEresusCommentaryVolume6.1 Philosophia Antiqua A Series of Studies on Ancient Philosophy Previous Editors J.H. Waszink † W. J. Ve r d e n i u s † J.C.M. Van Winden Edited by K.A. Algra F.A.J. De Haas J. Mansfeld C.J. Rowe D.T. Runia Ch. Wildberg VOLUME 123 Theophrastus of Eresus Sources for His Life, Writings, Thought and Influence Commentary Volume 6.1 Sources on Ethics Theophrastus of Eresus Commentary Volume 6.1 Sources on Ethics by William W. Fortenbaugh, with Contributions on the Arabic Material by Dimitri Gutas LEIDEN • BOSTON 2011 Thisbookisprintedonacid-freepaper. Library of Congress Control Number: 2007295680 ISSN: 0079-1687 ISBN: 978 90 04 19422 9 Copyright 2011 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Hotei Publishing, IDC Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Koninklijke Brill NV provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910, Danvers, MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change. for Herwig Görgemanns Scholar, Betreuer, Friend CONTENTS Preface ................................................................. ix I.Introduction........................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Him the Aristotle Referred to As Alexander's Teacher in Several Texts and Renders the Emendation of This Name to Aristocles Un­ Necessary
    I2 INTRODUCTION him the Aristotle referred to as Alexander's teacher in several texts and renders the emendation of this name to Aristocles un­ necessary. If this is correct his philosophical views are represented by a passage of the de intellectu dealing with the doctrine of "the external intellect" (voui; 6upa.6e:v).54 II. THE ALEXANDRIAN CORPUS 55 The purpose of this description of the Peripatetic school in the generation before Alexander has been to place his own contribution in perspective. It is clear now that a strong tradition of scholarly exegesis was established before him, and that he was linked to it through his teachers Herminus and Sosigines. There are also some indications of a less rigorous tradition represented by Alexan­ der of Damascus and Aristocles of Messenia in which philosophical eclecticism was combined with an affiliation to the culture of the Second Sophistic. Alexander's contribution was to be entirely the continuation of the former tradition 56 and its elevation to new heights, primarily through the composition of a series of com­ mentaries on Aristotelian works. The Commentaries The precise form of pre-Alexandrian philosophical commentaries is not known to us,57 the only extant example being the somewhat 54 Mant. no. 4-n2. 5 Bruns; cf. n. 44. 66 See Pt. II of the bibliography for additional literature on the works and subjects discussed in this section. 69 This is another reason, quite apart from those adduced by Moraux, why Alexander might not have been the pupil of Aristocles of Messenia. Nothing however is known of the contribution of Aristotle of Mitylene to the specifically scholarly tradition, and therefore his influence on Alexander as against that of the known scholars, Herminus and Sosigines, might have been slight.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected]
    Digital Commons @ George Fox University George Fox Evangelical Seminary 2013 Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes Part of the Christianity Commons, and the Church History Commons Recommended Citation Kerns, Loren, "Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria" (2013). George Fox Evangelical Seminary. Paper 6. http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes/6 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ George Fox University. It has been accepted for inclusion in George Fox Evangelical Seminary by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ George Fox University. Kings College London Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria A Dissertation submitted to The School of Arts and Humanities In Candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Theology and Religious Studies By Loren Kerns London, United Kingdom July 2013 Copyright by Loren Kerns, 2013 All rights reserved. Abstract Philo of Alexandria forged his theory of the soul and its passions while expositing the meaning of Torah. Though writing as a Jewish teacher and disciple of Moses, his biblical reflections display a strong orientation toward Middle-Platonic philosophy. On the topic of the soul and its passions, however, Philo also exhibits significant Stoic influence. The introduction notes Philo’s apparent incompatible use of both the complex Platonic and the monistic Stoic psychological models. After assessing the degree to which Philo understood 'passion' to be a type of Stoic impulse or opinion (chapter one), chapter two demonstrates that Philo consistently drew upon the Stoics’ depiction of all passions as irrational, excessive, and unnatural.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Emotion, London: Duckworth and New York: Barnes and Noble (Hard and Soft Cover) 1975, Reprinted with Epilogue 2002
    PUBLICATIONS Monograph: Aristotle on Emotion, London: Duckworth and New York: Barnes and Noble (hard and soft cover) 1975, reprinted with epilogue 2002 Text and Commentary: Quellen zur Ethik Theophrasts, Amsterdam: B. R. Gruener Verlag 1984 Text and Translation: Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for his Life, Writings, Thought & Influence, 2 vols. ed. and transl. with P. Huby, R. Sharples & D. Gutas, Leiden: E.J. Brill 1992 reprinted with corrections 1993 Commentary: Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for his Life, Writings, Thought & Influence, Commentary Volume 8: Sources on Rhetoric and Poetics, Leiden Brill 2005 Theophrastus of Eresus: Sources for his Life, Writings, Thought & Influence, Commentary Volume 6a: Sources on Ethics, Leiden Brill, 2010 Text, Translation and Commentary: Theophrastus, On Sweat, in Theophrastus, On Sweat, On Dizziness and On Fatigue, ed. with R. Sharples and M. Sollenberger (Leiden 2003) 1-167 Collected Essays Theophrastean Studies, Stuttgart: Franz Schneider 2003 Aristotle’s Practical Side: on his psychology, ethics, politics and rhetoric, Leiden: Brill 2006 Edited Books: On Stoic and Peripatetic Ethics: The Work of Arius Didymus, New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1983 = RUSCH Vol. I Theophrastus of Eresus: On His Life and Works (ed. with A.A. Long and P.M. Huby), New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1985 = RUSCH Vol. II Theophrastean Studies: On Natural Science, Physics and Metaphysics, Ethics, Religion and Rhetoric (ed. with R.W. Sharples), New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1987 = RUSCH Vol. III Cicero's Knowledge of the Peripatos (ed. with P. Steinmetz), New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1989 = RUSCH Vol. IV Theophrastus: His Psychological, Doxographical and Scientific Writings (ed. with D. Gutas), New Brunswick: Transaction Books 1992 = RUSCH Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • The History of a Greek Proverb , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 29:2 (1988:Summer) P.153
    WHEELER, EVERETT L., "Polla kena tou polemou" [Greek]: The History of a Greek Proverb , Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 29:2 (1988:Summer) p.153 IToAAa KEVa TOt) 7ToAEP.OV: The History of a Greek Proverb Everett L. Wheeler N THE SPRING of 427 B.C. a Peloponnesian fleet under the nauarch I Alcidas lumbered across the Aegean to raise the Athenian siege of Mytilene. i At Embaton in the Erythraea the fleet received confir­ mation of the report that Mytilene had already fallen; the Spartan mission had failed. 2 But the Elean Teutiaplus, a figure otherwise unknown, proposed to salvage the situation through stratagem: a sur­ prise attack by night would catch the Athenians unprepared, dis­ persed, and negligent in victory (Thuc. 3.30.1-3). Teutiaplus justifies his plan by reference to TO KEVOV TOt) 7TOA€P.OV (3.30.4), an obscure phrase, which then appears (always in the plural and always in a military context) in other authors down to Cicero, before eventually entering the collection of proverbs attributed to Diogenianus. 3 Metaphorical use of the phrase (i.e., in a non-military context) is first seen in Philo of Alexandria (Ebr. 76) and Plutarch (Mor. 41B). Neither Thucydides nor Aristotle, however, recognized the phrase as a proverb, of which Polybius gives the first explicit attestation. The history of the phrase KEV'ovl KEVil. TOl! 7ToAEP.OV provides a rare glimpse of how a Greek proverb originated, and allows us to probe its relationship to ancient military thought and psychological theory. Although proverbs are often regarded as colloquial aphorisms of 'folk wisdom' originating at indeterminable points in the past, some I The following will be cited by author's name: C.
    [Show full text]