Human Uniqueness As a Guide to Resolving Conflicts Between Animal and Human Interests

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Human Uniqueness As a Guide to Resolving Conflicts Between Animal and Human Interests E8A 11/1 E8A 11/1 77� HumanHuman UniquenessUniqueness asas a a GuideGuide toto ResolvingResolving� ConflictsConflicts BetweenBetween AnimalAnimal andand HumanHuman In­In­� tereststerests11� WhileWhile itit isis byby nono meansmeans clearclear whetherwhether wewe shouldshould speakspeak ofof animalsanimals asas rights-bearers,rights-bearers, inin anyany literalliteral sense,sense, oror simplysimply asas creaturescreatures toto whomwhom wewe havehave certaincertain responsibilities,responsibilities, itit isis reasonablyreasonably clearclear thatthat animalsanimals areare properproper ob­ob­ 2 jectsjects ofof moralmoral concern.concern. 2 GrantingGranting animalsanimals moralmoral standing,standing, however,however, needneed notnot resultresult inin attemptsattempts toto promotepromote animalanimal welfare.welfare. ImagineImagine yourselfyourself inin thethe followingfollowing situation.situation. YouYou areare aa biochemist,biochemist, isolatedisolated onon aa desertdesert islandisland withwith youryour daughterdaughter Jill,Jill, youryour petpet dogdog PhiloPhilo andand aa smallsmall butbut well-equippedwell-equipped laboratory.laboratory. OneOne dayday youryour daughtdaught fallsfalls ill;ill; herher healthhealth failsfails rap­rap­ idlyidly andand itit seemsseems evidentevident sheshe willwill diedie unlessunless somethingsomething isis done.done. YouYou synthesizesynthesize whatwhat maymay bebe aa curecure butbut youyou areare notnot sure;sure; itit maymay alsoalso bebe aa poison.poison. WhatWhat shouldshould youyou do?do? TheThe ob­ob­ viousvious answeranswer isis thatthat youyou testtest thethe potionpotion onon Philo.Philo. ToTo dodo otherwiseotherwise wouldwould bebe morallymorally un­un­ justifiable.justifiable. 33 TheThe factfact thatthat youyou testtest thethe possible cure on Philo does not showshow thatthat you do not care about him or take him to be a proper object of moral concern. It is just that in this case Philo's interests are out­ weighed by Jill's. Conflicts like the above demonstrate that moral concern is not a sufficient guide for our treatment of animals. Donald VanDeVeer has ~osedppsed the problem well: The troublesometroublesome .and.and difficult question�question whichwhich arises,arises, onceonce oneone isis convincedconvinced that�that bothboth humanhuman beingsbeings (or(or many)many) andand animals�animals (or(or many)many) havehave atat leastleast somesome morally�morally relevantrelevant interests,interests, concernsconcerns howhow to�to wei~h~ theirtheir respectiverespective interestsinterests inin gen­�gen­ ~anderal and howhow toto adjudicateadjudicate conflictsconflicts of�of interestinterest whichwhich arisearise betweenbetween humanshumans and�and animals.animals.4�4 . WhatWhat needsneeds toto bebe shownshown isis howhow moralmoral concernconcern oughtought toto bebe manifestmanifest withwith respectrespect toto animals.animals. ~ot~ot eveneven thethe establishmentestablishment ofof animalanimal rights,rights, aa veryvery strongstrong conclusion,conclusion, wouldwould resolveresolve thisthis problem.problem. IfIf animalanimal interestsinterests areare protectedprotected byby rights,rights, wewe stillstill mustmust askask toto whatwhat extent,extent, ifif any,any, theythey areare protectedprotected againstagainst humanhuman interests.interests.5S AA justjust resolutionresolution ofof thethe aboveabove problemproblem willw~ll havehave toto taketake accountaccount ofof bothboth similaritiessimilarities andand differencesdifferences betW'eenbetween humanshumans andand animals.animals. RecentRecent studiesstudies ofof animalanimal behaviorbehaviorhavehave shownshown thatthat be­be­ haviorhavior toto bebe significantlysignificantly moremore complexcomplexand,and, consequently,consequently, moremore similarsimilar totohumanhumanbehaviorbehavior thanthanpreviouslypreviouslyassumed.assumed.66 AmongAmong otherotherthings,things, animalsanimalshavehavebeenbeenfoundfound toto useusecomplicatedcomplicated EaA 11/1�11/1 8 communication systems and to modify objects human nature. It is here that human unique­ ~or use as tools, two activities once deemed ness lends a hand to animal welfare. the exclusive property of human beings. Such I sophisticated behavior has led a number of sciencists to conclude that at least some ani­ What needs to be shown with respect to ani­ mals have a fairly substantial mental life.' mals is not only that their welfare i$ ~ Needless to say, this conclusion has marked matter of moral concern but equally important implications for the weighing of animal in­ how much weight animal interests ought to terests. An animal with a high level of carry whenever they conflict with human in­ awareness is vulnerable in more ways than one terests. One plausible approach to this wich a low level and, consequently, places a problem has been labeled by VanDeVeer "two­ greater demand on our moral consideration. factor egalitarianism."a As its name sug­ gests, two-factor egalitarianism focuses on Excitement over these discoveries, however, two factors: these are. extent of interest should not lead us to forget the remaining, and psychological complexity. Once these are significant differences between animal and determined, various principles inform the human behavior. Recently discovered similar­ moral agent how much weight each deserves, i:ies, significant though they be, are not allowing in general that significance varies great enough to bridge that divide. Nor is directly with extent of interest and degree it likely that future research will do so. of psychological compleXity. Such a system Barring the discovery of presently unknown has intuitive appeal. 9 By focusing on the life-forms, human uniqueness appears a fact extent of interest involved two-factor egali­ to be lived with. To those concerned about tarianism allows us to take into account rela­ animal welfare such a conclusion may seem un­ tive cost and benefit. Underlying each de­ :ortunate and even distressing. Tradition­ cision will be a cost-benefit analysis. At ally, human uniqueness has been taken to the same time, two-factor egalitarianism as­ justify a rather cavalier attitude toward cribes greater weight to the interests of our animal welfare. Whether one spoke of souls, own kind, a position many persons find morally minds, intrinsic value, or divine commands, appealing. Moreover, it does so on the non­ the well-being of animals was felt to be in­ discriminatory, or, egalitarian grounds of significant compared to that of human beings. psychological complexity. All this is not to The result is well-known: the most trivial sav there are no problems regarding the of human interests allows the most thorough ac~eptability of two-factor egalitarianism as disregard for animal interests. It is no a guide to moral deliberation. 1Q For purposes wonder, then, that advocates of animal wel­ of this paper, however, I will ignore what­ fare have preferred to emphasize similari­ ever difficulties there may be and work with­ :1es while downplaying differences between in the framework provided by two-factor egal­ animal and human behavior. itarianism. My intention is to sketch a some­ In what follows, I want to re-examine the what plausible system in terms of which the role of human uniqueness in adjudicating con­ role of human uniqueness can be evaluated, flicts between animal and human interests. not to argue that two-factor egalitarianism ~~ conclusion will be that for the most part provides an adequate context for resolving t~is role has been misunderstood. Properly conflicts between animal and human interests. understood, human uniqueness is a vital com­ Let me begin with extent of interest. ponent in the case for animal welfare. My A continuum of interests is not difficult argument ~ill proceed in two stages. To be­ to envision. With respect to myself, I know oin I will sketch a system of moral princi­ o , . that some things count more for my well-being ples for adjudicating conflicts between an~- than others.. The extent of this counting is, mal and human interests. Iftlile grancing some of course, not a matter of my apprehension Doral consideration to animal interests, alone; it is a reflection of the world and my these principles both recognize human unique­ place therein. In many cases, I am aware of ness and grant high priority to human inter­ and correctly apprehend the relative impor­ ests. Having outlined this system, I will tance of my interests. In other cases, I do use it to address questions regarding the not. Unlike normal, adult humans, the knowl­ morality of animal experimentation. After edge animals have of their own L~terests will distinguishing two distinct ways in which be extremely vague or entirely intuitive. 11 [he systen can be applied to such questions, On our part, the determination and weighing I will argue that resolution of the debate of animal interests requires careful, pro­ over animal experimentation depends to a longed observation, with special care taken large extent on fundamental assumptions about to avoid anthropomorphic distortions. Recent E8A 11/1 9 9 studies of wolves, chimpanzees and gorillas reflective awareness. The value of such aware­ indicate that such distortions can be avoided ness, limited as it is~· is that it allows for and animal interests assessed from an objec­ greater adaptability: a painful course will be tive, scientific standpoint. 12 avoided, a pleasurable one pursued. In this Interests, both human and animal, can be di­ way bare awareness of pain and pleasure allows vided
Recommended publications
  • Works on Giambattista Vico in English from 1884 Through 2009
    Works on Giambattista Vico in English from 1884 through 2009 COMPILED BY MOLLY BLA C K VERENE TABLE OF CON T EN T S PART I. Books A. Monographs . .84 B. Collected Volumes . 98 C. Dissertations and Theses . 111 D. Journals......................................116 PART II. Essays A. Articles, Chapters, et cetera . 120 B. Entries in Reference Works . 177 C. Reviews and Abstracts of Works in Other Languages ..180 PART III. Translations A. English Translations ............................186 B. Reviews of Translations in Other Languages.........192 PART IV. Citations...................................195 APPENDIX. Bibliographies . .302 83 84 NEW VICO STUDIE S 27 (2009) PART I. BOOKS A. Monographs Adams, Henry Packwood. The Life and Writings of Giambattista Vico. London: Allen and Unwin, 1935; reprinted New York: Russell and Russell, 1970. REV I EWS : Gianturco, Elio. Italica 13 (1936): 132. Jessop, T. E. Philosophy 11 (1936): 216–18. Albano, Maeve Edith. Vico and Providence. Emory Vico Studies no. 1. Series ed. D. P. Verene. New York: Peter Lang, 1986. REV I EWS : Daniel, Stephen H. The Eighteenth Century: A Current Bibliography, n.s. 12 (1986): 148–49. Munzel, G. F. New Vico Studies 5 (1987): 173–75. Simon, L. Canadian Philosophical Reviews 8 (1988): 335–37. Avis, Paul. The Foundations of Modern Historical Thought: From Machiavelli to Vico. Beckenham (London): Croom Helm, 1986. REV I EWS : Goldie, M. History 72 (1987): 84–85. Haddock, Bruce A. New Vico Studies 5 (1987): 185–86. Bedani, Gino L. C. Vico Revisited: Orthodoxy, Naturalism and Science in the ‘Scienza nuova.’ Oxford: Berg, 1989. REV I EWS : Costa, Gustavo. New Vico Studies 8 (1990): 90–92.
    [Show full text]
  • A Priori Rules: Wittgenstein on the Normativity of Logic
    A Priori Rules: Wittgenstein on the Normativity of Logic Peter Railton The University of Michigan Introduction Like many, I have long been uneasy with the category of the a priori. Perhaps I have simply misunderstood it. It has seemed to me, at any rate, that asserting a claim or principle as a priori is tantamount to claiming that we would be justified in ruling out alternatives in advance, no matter what the future course of experience might hold. Yet in my own case, I have felt it would be mere bluffing were I to lodge such a claim. I certainly could not discover in myself any sense of the requisite authority, nor even any clear idea of where to look for guidance in forming it. Contemplating widely-used examples of "propositions true a priori" did not remove my worry. For a start, there was the shadow of history. A claim like "logical truth is a priori" or "the attribution of rationality is a priori in intentional explanation" kept sounding, to my ears, as if they echoed "the Euclidean geometry of space is a priori" or "the principle of sufficient reason is a priori in physical explanation". And these echoes awakened just sort of the worry that had initially unsettled me: I would pronouce myself satisfied that certain claims, at least, were safe from the threat of contrary experience, just on the eve of developments in our on-going view of the world that would lead a sensible person to want to reopen the question. So I would emerge looking like the (perhaps apocryphal) fellow who claimed, in the wake of the great inventions of the nineteenth century, that the US Patent Office could now be closed, since all the really new ideas had been used up.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: the Example of Cassirer’S Erkenntnisproblem", in from Hegel to Windelband, Eds
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2015 Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo- Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer’s Erkenntnisproblem Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. "Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer’s Erkenntnisproblem", in From Hegel to Windelband, Eds. Gerald Hartung and Valentin Pluder. Boston : De Gruyter, 2015: 181-205. Publisher Link. © 2015 Walter De Gruyter. Used with permission. Sebastian Luft Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer's Erkenntnisproblem Introduction: Philosophical Historiography as Problem-History. Windelband as Paradigm We can think that "problem-history"l is exclusively a name for one way of philo­ sophical historiography among others. As such it is a method that recounts the history of philosophy in terms of its problems, and not in terms of philosophical personalities or cultural epochs. In this understanding, problem-history proceeds with the naIve assumption that problems exist "in themselves", that they are merely repeated and manifested differently in different epochs. Plainly stated, this sounds both trivial and problematic. And if this reading is true then it is no wonder that problem-history is accorded little interest today, despite the fact that the classical authors of problem-history writing are still readily consulted. Apart from the fact that such writers are still being constantly exploited for re­ search purposes in the present, their works are granted no independent philo­ sophical value. This applies equally to the authors of these works: they are not considered as independent philosophers but "only" as historians.
    [Show full text]
  • Pythagorean, Predecessor, and Hebrew: Philo of Alexandria and the Construction of Jewishness in Early Christian Writings
    Pythagorean, Predecessor, and Hebrew: Philo of Alexandria and the Construction of Jewishness in Early Christian Writings Jennifer Otto Faculty of Religious Studies McGill University, Montreal March, 2014 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy © Jennifer Otto, 2014 ii Table of Contents Abstracts v Acknowledgements vii Abbreviations viii Introduction 1 Method, Aims and Scope of the Thesis 10 Christians and Jews among the nations 12 Philo and the Wisdom of the Greeks 16 Christianity as Philosophy 19 Moving Forward 24 Part I Chapter 1: Philo in Modern Scholarship 25 Introducing Philo 25 Philo the Jew in modern research 27 Conclusions 48 Chapter 2: Sects and Texts: The Setting of the Christian Encounter with Philo 54 The Earliest Alexandrian Christians 55 The Trajanic Revolt 60 The “Catechetical School” of Alexandria— A Continuous 63 Jewish-Christian Institution? An Alternative Hypothesis: Reading Philo in the Philosophical Schools 65 Conclusions 70 Part II Chapter 3: The Pythagorean: Clement’s Philo 72 1. Introducing Clement 73 1.1 Clement’s Life 73 1.2 Clement’s Corpus 75 1.3 Clement’s Teaching 78 2. Israel, Hebrews, and Jews in Clement’s Writings 80 2.1 Israel 81 2.2 Hebrews 82 2.3 Jews 83 3. Clement’s Reception of Philo: Literature Review 88 4. Clement’s Testimonia to Philo 97 4.1 Situating the Philonic Borrowings in the context of Stromateis 1 97 4.2 Stromateis 1.5.31 102 4.3 Stromateis 1.15.72 106 4.4 Stromateis 1.23.153 109 iii 4.5 Situating the Philonic Borrowings in the context of Stromateis 2 111 4.6 Stromateis 2.19.100 113 5.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy
    CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy The Johns Hopkins University Citizen of U.K. Baltimore, MD 21218-2686 Permanent Resident of U.S. Phone: (410) 516-6863 Fax: (410) 516-6848 e-mail: <[email protected]> EDUCATION B.A. Oxford University, 1980, Literae Humaniores (Classics and Philosophy). First Class Honours, Final Examinations, 1980; First Class Honours, Honour Moderations in Greek & Latin Literature, 1978 Ph.D. University of California, Berkeley, 1986, Philosophy. Dissertation Title: “Moral Scepticism: Why Ask ‘Why Should I be Moral?’” CURRENT POSITION Professor and Chair of Philosophy, The Johns Hopkins University; secondary appointment in Classics PREVIOUS POSITIONS Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Texas at Arlington, 1986-1991 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, Jan.-June 1991 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1991-1994 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1994-2000; secondary appointment in Classics, 1996-2000 Acting Executive Director, The American Philosophical Association, Jan. 2000-June 2001 PUBLICATIONS a) Books Sextus Empiricus, Against the Ethicists (Adversus Mathematicos XI): Introduction, Translation and Commentary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997, paperback 2000). Pp. xxxiv + 302 Pyrrho, his Antecedents and his Legacy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000, paperback 2003). Pp. xi + 264 Sextus Empiricus, Against the Logicians (Adversus Mathematicos VII-VIII): Introduction, Translation and Notes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005). Pp. xliv
    [Show full text]
  • QUALIA: What It Is Like to Have an Experience
    QUALIA: What it is like to have an experience Qualia include the ways things look, sound and smell, the way it feels to have a pain, and more generally, what it's like to have experiential mental states. (‘Qualia’ is the plural of ‘quale’.) Qualia are experiential properties of sensations, feelings, perceptions and, more controversially, thoughts and desires as well. But, so defined, who could deny that qualia exist? Although the existence of subjective experience is not (or anyway should not be) controversial, ‘quale’—which is more clearly a technical term than ‘subjective experience’ is more often used by those who are inclined to reject the common-sense conception of subjective experience. Here is a first approximation to a statement of what is controversial: whether the phenomenology of experience can be exhaustively analyzed in intentional, functional or purely cognitive terms. Opponents of qualia think that the phenomenology of an experience can be exhaustively analyzed in terms of its representational or intentional content (“representationism”); or that the phenomenology of experience can be exhaustively analyzed in terms of its causal role (“functionalism”), or that having a subjective experiential state can be exhaustively analyzed in terms of having a state that is cognitively monitored in a certain way or accompanied by a thought to the effect that I have that state. If we include in the definition of ‘qualia’ the idea that the phenomenology of experience outruns such intentional, functional and cognitive analyses, then it is controversial whether there are qualia. This definition of `qualia' is controversial in a respect that is familiar in philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Editorial: Reflections on the Hypatia Controversy: Philosophical Methods and Social Justice
    Document generated on 09/28/2021 3:25 p.m. Atlantis Critical Studies in Gender, Culture & Social Justice Études critiques sur le genre, la culture, et la justice Editorial Reflections on the Hypatia Controversy: Philosophical Methods and Social Justice Alison Suen and Chloë Taylor Volume 39, Number 2, 2018 URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1064072ar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/1064072ar See table of contents Publisher(s) Mount Saint Vincent University ISSN 1715-0698 (digital) Explore this journal Cite this document Suen, A. & Taylor, C. (2018). Editorial: Reflections on the Hypatia Controversy: Philosophical Methods and Social Justice. Atlantis, 39(2), 57–60. https://doi.org/10.7202/1064072ar All Rights Reserved © Mount Saint Vincent University, 2018 This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal. Its mission is to promote and disseminate research. https://www.erudit.org/en/ Special Section: Editorial Reflections on the Hypatia Controversy: Philosophical Methods and Social Justice Alison Suen is an assistant professor of philosophy at his cluster of articles proceeds from a symposium Iona College, New York. She received her BA in Tfunded by both the Social Sciences and Human- Philosophy from the University of Northern Iowa in ities Research Council of Canada and Kule Institute 2006, and her PhD in Philosophy from Vanderbilt for Advanced Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected]
    Digital Commons @ George Fox University George Fox Evangelical Seminary 2013 Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes Part of the Christianity Commons, and the Church History Commons Recommended Citation Kerns, Loren, "Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria" (2013). George Fox Evangelical Seminary. Paper 6. http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes/6 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ George Fox University. It has been accepted for inclusion in George Fox Evangelical Seminary by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ George Fox University. Kings College London Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria A Dissertation submitted to The School of Arts and Humanities In Candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Theology and Religious Studies By Loren Kerns London, United Kingdom July 2013 Copyright by Loren Kerns, 2013 All rights reserved. Abstract Philo of Alexandria forged his theory of the soul and its passions while expositing the meaning of Torah. Though writing as a Jewish teacher and disciple of Moses, his biblical reflections display a strong orientation toward Middle-Platonic philosophy. On the topic of the soul and its passions, however, Philo also exhibits significant Stoic influence. The introduction notes Philo’s apparent incompatible use of both the complex Platonic and the monistic Stoic psychological models. After assessing the degree to which Philo understood 'passion' to be a type of Stoic impulse or opinion (chapter one), chapter two demonstrates that Philo consistently drew upon the Stoics’ depiction of all passions as irrational, excessive, and unnatural.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Cicero's Eclectic Probabilism
    Revista Archai ISSN: 1984-249X Universidade de Brasília Skvirsky, Alexandre Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Revista Archai, no. 27, e02705, 2019 Universidade de Brasília DOI: https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=586161659005 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System Redalyc More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America and the Caribbean, Spain and Journal's webpage in redalyc.org Portugal Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative AS ORIGENS DO PENSAMENTO OCIDENTAL THE ORIGINS OF WESTERN THOUGHT ARTIGO I ARTICLE Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Alexandre Skvirsky i https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9508-1023 [email protected] i Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio de Janeiro – Rio de Janeiro – RJ – Brasil SKVIRSKY, A. (2019). Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica. Archai 27, e02705. Abstract: The objective is to show the peculiar way in which Cicero’s philosophical thinking is original and distances itself from the main representatives of the New Academy: the Roman thinker does not practice epoche, nor does he assign any special role to it in his thought. Instead, Cicero introduces the concept of doubt to characterize his own way of thinking. Keywords: Cicero, epoche, doubt, skepticism, probabilism. https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 [1] 2 Rev. Archai, n. 27, Brasília, 2019, e02705. Cicero’s philosophical contributions have often been downplayed, even by himself. His importance as a translator and divulger of philosophy among the Romans frequently overshadows his originality as a philosopher.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophia Ancilla Theologiae Allegory and Ascension in Philo’S on Mating with the Preliminary Studies (De Congressu Quaerendae Eruditionis Gratia)
    ARTICLES PHILOSOPHIA ANCILLA THEOLOGIAE ALLEGORY AND ASCENSION IN PHILO’S ON MATING WITH THE PRELIMINARY STUDIES (DE CONGRESSU QUAERENDAE ERUDITIONIS GRATIA) Hent de Vries, Johns Hopkins University Baltimore Translated by Jack Ben-Levi This essay takes Philo of Alexandria's allegorical reading in ‘De congressu quaerendae eruditionis gratia’ of Genesis 16: 1–6, which recounts Abraham's temporary relationship with Hagar, as anticipation of the philosophia ancilla theologiae motif that has informed much of Western Christian and philosophical thought. In so doing, it explores the ways in which Philo's view in ‘On Mating with the Preliminary Studies’ gives new meaning to the ancient Greek curriculum of the enkyklios paideia that would remain decisive for the idea of the artes liberales and the humaniora, from early modernity up until Gadamer's philosophical her- meneutics. I. INTRODUCTION Since its beginnings, Christian theology has considered it necessary to defend, in the court of contemporary opinion, the claim made by religious faith for its own universal truth. Yet at the same time, if this theology did not want simply to identify the God of faith with that of the philosophers, it had to keep alive a sense of the discrepancy between its doctrine and secular knowledge. A resolution of the resulting dilemma is to be found in one Platonic tradition that did indeed grant a certain importance to formal knowledge (epistēmē, scientia) and to philosophy (philosophia, philosophia), while in the end nonetheless subordinating them to Christian doctrine, considered to be the source of wisdom (sophia, sapientia).1 This position, familiar to us from the medieval dictum ‘philosophia ancilla theologiae’ (philosophy is the handmaiden of theology), was established much earlier.
    [Show full text]
  • When Science Became Western: Historiographical Reflections Author(S): by Marwa Elshakry Source: Isis, Vol
    When Science Became Western: Historiographical Reflections Author(s): By Marwa Elshakry Source: Isis, Vol. 101, No. 1 (March 2010), pp. 98-109 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of The History of Science Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/652691 . Accessed: 01/04/2013 12:49 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press and The History of Science Society are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Isis. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 160.39.148.241 on Mon, 1 Apr 2013 12:49:23 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions When Science Became Western Historiographical Reflections By Marwa Elshakry* ABSTRACT While thinking about the notion of the “global” in the history of the history of science, this essay examines a related but equally basic concept: the idea of “Western science.” Tracing its rise in the nineteenth century, it shows how it developed as much outside the Western world as within it. Ironically, while the idea itself was crucial for the disciplinary formation of the history of science, the global history behind this story has not been much attended to.
    [Show full text]
  • Online Access to Essential Research in the Humanities!
    Online access to essential research in the humanities! Browse dozens of scholarly journals, series, and conference proceedings in applied ethics, philosophy, and religious studies. Enjoy online research in huge selections of material dating back to 1890. All articles are fulltext searchable and OpenURL ready. Many titles in the following categories: and free page previews are available to non- subscribers. Open access provided for • Analytic Philosophy select titles. Content is displayed in either • Ancient Philosophy HTML or PDF format. Institutions may order • Applied Philosophy single titles, bundles, or the entire collection. • Business and Professional Ethics Pricing is modest, and multi-campus and • Catholic Tradition consortia pricing is available. • Conference Proceedings • Contemporary Philosophy • Continental Philosophy • General Interest • History of Philosophy • Major Philosophers • Philosophy and Religion • Semiotics • Social and Political Philosophy • Teaching Philosophy Fulltext E-Collection – hosted by the Philosophy Documentation Center Since 1966 the Philosophy Documentation Center (PDC) has earned a reputation for excellence with the non-profit publication of scholarly journals, series, and conference proceedings, and reference works. We also provide membership and publishing services for learned societies in philosophy and related Coverage expands as new issues are fields. Our goal is to increase access to published. Subscribers have access to current humanities scholarship in a fair and issues and complete archives. Free search sustainable manner. Philosophy Documentation Center, P.O. Box 7147, Charlottesville, Virginia 22906-7147 USA, www.pdcnet.org Over 200 titles in English and other languages. 200 ,000+ articles, reviews, and other documents! Most titles available exclusively through PDC. www.pdcnet.org /ecollection •The Acorn (Vol. 1, 1986, to present) •The New Scholasticism (Vol.
    [Show full text]