Nietzsche and the German Tradition

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nietzsche and the German Tradition Nietzsche and the German Tradition von Nicholas Martin 1. Auflage Nietzsche and the German Tradition – Martin schnell und portofrei erhältlich bei beck-shop.de DIE FACHBUCHHANDLUNG Peter Lang Bern 2003 Verlag C.H. Beck im Internet: www.beck.de ISBN 978 3 03910 060 6 Inhaltsverzeichnis: Nietzsche and the German Tradition – Martin Notes on Contributors CHRISTA DAVIS ACAMPORA is Assistant Professor of Phil- osophy at Hunter College of the City University of New York. She has published numerous articles on Nietzsche in a variety of publications, including Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Nietzsche- forschung, and International Studies in Philosophy. She is the co- editor, with Ralph Acampora, of A Nietzschean Bestiary: Animality Beyond Docial and Brutal, forthcoming from Rowman & Littlefield. THOMAS H. BROBJER lectures in the history of ideas at the Universities of Uppsala and Stockholm. He is the author of Nietzsche’s Ethics of Character (Uppsala 1995). He has published extensively on different aspects of Nietzsche’s reading and extant library, in the following journals and others: Journal of the History of Ideas, Journal of the History of Philosophy, Nietzsche-Studien, Journal of Nietzsche Studies, New Nietzsche Studies and Inter- national Studies in Philosophy. He has also contributed to a number of books on Nietzsche. DANIEL W. CONWAY is Professor of Philosophy and Director of Graduate Studies in Philosophy at The Pennsylvania State University. He has published widely on topics in political philosophy, contem- porary European philosophy, and nineteenth-century philosophy. He is the author of Nietzsche’s Dangerous Game (CUP 1997) and Nietzsche and the Political (Routledge 1997). He is also the editor of Nietzsche: Critical Assessments (Routledge 1998), and the co-editor of Nietzsche, Philosophy, and the Arts (CUP 1998). MALCOLM HUMBLE studied Modern Languages at Emmanuel College, Cambridge, and was a Research Fellow there from 1966 to 1969. He was Lecturer in German at the University of St Andrews xii from 1969 to 2001. His publications include articles on Anglo- German literary relations, the reception of Nietzsche and Brecht, exile literature (1933–45), GDR literature, and (with Raymond Furness) A Companion to Twentieth Century German Literature (Routledge 1991, 21997) and Introduction to German Literature 1871–1990 (Routledge 1994). CHRISTOPHER JANAWAY is Professor of Philosophy at Birkbeck College, University of London. He specializes in philosophical aesthetics and the philosophies of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. His publications include Self and World in Schopenhauer’s Philosophy (OUP 1989), Schopenhauer (OUP 1994), and Images of Excellence: Plato’s Critique of the Arts (OUP 1995). He is editor of the collections Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche’s Educator (OUP 1998) and The Cambridge Companion to Schopen- hauer (CUP 1999). DUNCAN LARGE is Senior Lecturer in German at University of Wales, Swansea, and Chairman of the Friedrich Nietzsche Society. He is the author of Nietzsche and Proust: A Comparative Study (OUP 2001), co-editor (with Keith Ansell-Pearson) of The Nietzsche Reader (Blackwell 2003), guest editor of ‘Nietzsche and German Literature’, Journal of Nietzsche Studies, 13 (Spring 1997), and has translated Sarah Kofman, Nietzsche and Metaphor (Athlone and Stanford UP 1993), as well as Nietzsche’s Twilight of the Idols (OUP 1998) and Ecce Homo (OUP 2003). He is currently completing a monograph on Nietzsche’s Renaissance Figures. NICHOLAS MARTIN is Lecturer in German at the University of St Andrews. He is the author of Nietzsche and Schiller: Untimely Aesthetics (OUP 1996) and the translator of Gianni Vattimo, Nietzsche: An Introduction (Athlone and Stanford UP 2002). He has published articles on Nietzsche in German Life and Letters, Nietzscheforschung, Journal of Nietzsche Studies, History of Euro- pean Ideas, and the Times Literary Supplement. His most recent xiii publication on Nietzsche is ‘“Fighting a Philosophy”: The Figure of Nietzsche in British Propaganda of the First World War’, Modern Language Review, 98 (2003). BEN MORGAN is a Fellow of Worcester College, Oxford, and Lecturer in German at the University of Oxford. His research interests include German intellectual history, German cinema and twentieth-century German philosophy. He has published widely on medieval mysticism, psychoanalysis, the Frankfurt School, and the films of Fritz Lang and Leni Riefenstahl. GERD SCHANK studied linguistics, and German and Romance philology at Freiburg. Since 1977 he has been a lecturer at the University of Nijmegen (since 1988 in the Department of Philosophy, where he is a member of the Nietzsche Dictionary Project). His publications include: ‘Rasse’ und ‘Züchtung’ bei Nietzsche (de Gruyter 2000); Dionysos gegen den Gekreuzigten: Eine philologische und philosophische Studie zu Nietzsches ‘Ecce homo’ (Lang 1993); and ‘Dionysos und Ariadne im Gespräch: Subjektauflösung und Mehrstimmigkeit in Nietzsches Philosophie’, Tijdschrift voor Filo- sofie, 53 (1991). HANS-GERD von SEGGERN studied German literature, philosophy, and history in Berlin (Freie Universität) and Vienna from 1989–97. He held a Ph.D. scholarship from the Friedrich Ebert Foundation (1999–2001) and is completing a thesis on Nietzsche and Weimar classicism. Publications: Nietzsches Philosophie des Scheins (VDG 1999); ‘Allen Tinten-Fischen feind: Metaphern der Melancholie in Nietzsches Also sprach Zarathustra’, Nietzscheforschung, 9 (2002); ‘Die Aura im Zeitalter ihrer theoretischen Beliebigkeit: Überlegungen zu einer untoten ästhetischen Kategorie’, in Renate Reschke (ed.), Ästhetik. Ephemeres und Historisches (Kovač 2002). xiv PAUL J. M. van TONGEREN is Professor of Philosophical Ethics at the University of Nijmegen and Extraordinary Professor of Ethics at the Catholic University of Louvain. He is Director of the Nietzsche Research Group at Nijmegen, which is preparing a Nietzsche Dictionary (Nietzsche-Wörterbuch). He has recently published Re- interpreting Modern Culture. An Introduction to Nietzsche’s Phil- osophy (Purdue UP 2000). JIM URPETH is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Greenwich, London. His research interests include Kant, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Bataille, Foucault, Deleuze, aesthetics, and the philosophy of religion. He is currently completing two books: From Kant to Deleuze: The Renaturalisation of Aesthetics; and Nietzsche and French Religious Atheism. He was co-editor (with John Lippitt) of Nietzsche and the Divine (Clinamen 2000) and guest editor of ‘Nietzsche and Religion’, Journal of Nietzsche Studies, 19 (Spring 2000). His other publications include ‘“Noble” Ascesis: Between Nietzsche and Foucault’, New Nietzsche Studies, 2 (1998), and ‘A “Sacred” Thrill: Presentation and Affectivity in the Analytic of the Sublime’, in Rehberg and Jones (eds), The Matter of Critique: Readings in Kant’s Philosophy (Clinamen 2000). Preface Nietzsche and the German Tradition. To those persuaded that Nietzsche is the anti-German, antitraditional thinker par excellence, this title may well appear contradictory. Just how potentially contradictory (but also fruitful) it is, can be gauged by recasting it as a series of questions, emphasising each word in turn: Nietzsche and the German Tradition? Nietzsche and the German Tradition? Nietzsche and the German Tradition? Nietzsche and the German Tradition? Nietzsche and the German Tradition? Even without perplexed exclamation marks, each of these questions highlights different aspects of a central problem discussed in this collection of essays. This problem is the tension between Nietzsche’s desire for a new beginning, a clean slate for (hu)mankind and his keen awareness that nineteenth-century humans are not a tabula rasa. Nietzsche himself is, of course, no different to his contemporaries. As he constantly reminds us, he carries an accumulated weight of psychological, cultural, political, religious and academic baggage. Much of Nietzsche’s intellectual effort involves sorting through this ‘traditional’ baggage, attempting both to discard items likely to impede the journey and to repack those with the potential to enhance it. A difficulty for his interpreters is that Nietzsche’s criteria for sorting, discarding and repacking tradition(s) undergo significant, though not constant, mutations. This problem and its near-neighbour, the question of the extent to which Nietzsche and his legacies – and the study of them – have themselves become a ‘tradition’, are illuminated from a variety of perspectives in this volume. The contributors represent a wide range of disciplines (philosophy, cultural studies, the history of ideas, linguistics, history, and German studies), and they bring a refreshing diversity of methodological approaches to bear on the theme of Nietzsche and the German tradition. xvi The essays collected here, with the exception of the editor’s, were first presented at the 7th Annual Conference of the Friedrich Nietzsche Society, which was held at the University of St Andrews in September 1997. All have since been revised and updated to take account of subsequent developments in Nietzsche studies and other relevant areas of scholarship. The conference itself attracted some sixty delegates, including nine from Scotland, eighteen from other parts of the UK, ten from other EU countries, and eleven from North America, as well as participants from South Africa, Australia and Switzerland.1 Three distinct, yet often overlapping, lines of inquiry emerged at the conference and are, quite
Recommended publications
  • Works on Giambattista Vico in English from 1884 Through 2009
    Works on Giambattista Vico in English from 1884 through 2009 COMPILED BY MOLLY BLA C K VERENE TABLE OF CON T EN T S PART I. Books A. Monographs . .84 B. Collected Volumes . 98 C. Dissertations and Theses . 111 D. Journals......................................116 PART II. Essays A. Articles, Chapters, et cetera . 120 B. Entries in Reference Works . 177 C. Reviews and Abstracts of Works in Other Languages ..180 PART III. Translations A. English Translations ............................186 B. Reviews of Translations in Other Languages.........192 PART IV. Citations...................................195 APPENDIX. Bibliographies . .302 83 84 NEW VICO STUDIE S 27 (2009) PART I. BOOKS A. Monographs Adams, Henry Packwood. The Life and Writings of Giambattista Vico. London: Allen and Unwin, 1935; reprinted New York: Russell and Russell, 1970. REV I EWS : Gianturco, Elio. Italica 13 (1936): 132. Jessop, T. E. Philosophy 11 (1936): 216–18. Albano, Maeve Edith. Vico and Providence. Emory Vico Studies no. 1. Series ed. D. P. Verene. New York: Peter Lang, 1986. REV I EWS : Daniel, Stephen H. The Eighteenth Century: A Current Bibliography, n.s. 12 (1986): 148–49. Munzel, G. F. New Vico Studies 5 (1987): 173–75. Simon, L. Canadian Philosophical Reviews 8 (1988): 335–37. Avis, Paul. The Foundations of Modern Historical Thought: From Machiavelli to Vico. Beckenham (London): Croom Helm, 1986. REV I EWS : Goldie, M. History 72 (1987): 84–85. Haddock, Bruce A. New Vico Studies 5 (1987): 185–86. Bedani, Gino L. C. Vico Revisited: Orthodoxy, Naturalism and Science in the ‘Scienza nuova.’ Oxford: Berg, 1989. REV I EWS : Costa, Gustavo. New Vico Studies 8 (1990): 90–92.
    [Show full text]
  • A Priori Rules: Wittgenstein on the Normativity of Logic
    A Priori Rules: Wittgenstein on the Normativity of Logic Peter Railton The University of Michigan Introduction Like many, I have long been uneasy with the category of the a priori. Perhaps I have simply misunderstood it. It has seemed to me, at any rate, that asserting a claim or principle as a priori is tantamount to claiming that we would be justified in ruling out alternatives in advance, no matter what the future course of experience might hold. Yet in my own case, I have felt it would be mere bluffing were I to lodge such a claim. I certainly could not discover in myself any sense of the requisite authority, nor even any clear idea of where to look for guidance in forming it. Contemplating widely-used examples of "propositions true a priori" did not remove my worry. For a start, there was the shadow of history. A claim like "logical truth is a priori" or "the attribution of rationality is a priori in intentional explanation" kept sounding, to my ears, as if they echoed "the Euclidean geometry of space is a priori" or "the principle of sufficient reason is a priori in physical explanation". And these echoes awakened just sort of the worry that had initially unsettled me: I would pronouce myself satisfied that certain claims, at least, were safe from the threat of contrary experience, just on the eve of developments in our on-going view of the world that would lead a sensible person to want to reopen the question. So I would emerge looking like the (perhaps apocryphal) fellow who claimed, in the wake of the great inventions of the nineteenth century, that the US Patent Office could now be closed, since all the really new ideas had been used up.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: the Example of Cassirer’S Erkenntnisproblem", in from Hegel to Windelband, Eds
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2015 Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo- Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer’s Erkenntnisproblem Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. "Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer’s Erkenntnisproblem", in From Hegel to Windelband, Eds. Gerald Hartung and Valentin Pluder. Boston : De Gruyter, 2015: 181-205. Publisher Link. © 2015 Walter De Gruyter. Used with permission. Sebastian Luft Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer's Erkenntnisproblem Introduction: Philosophical Historiography as Problem-History. Windelband as Paradigm We can think that "problem-history"l is exclusively a name for one way of philo­ sophical historiography among others. As such it is a method that recounts the history of philosophy in terms of its problems, and not in terms of philosophical personalities or cultural epochs. In this understanding, problem-history proceeds with the naIve assumption that problems exist "in themselves", that they are merely repeated and manifested differently in different epochs. Plainly stated, this sounds both trivial and problematic. And if this reading is true then it is no wonder that problem-history is accorded little interest today, despite the fact that the classical authors of problem-history writing are still readily consulted. Apart from the fact that such writers are still being constantly exploited for re­ search purposes in the present, their works are granted no independent philo­ sophical value. This applies equally to the authors of these works: they are not considered as independent philosophers but "only" as historians.
    [Show full text]
  • The 'New' Heidegger
    Fordham University Masthead Logo DigitalResearch@Fordham Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Philosophy Collections 1-2015 The ‘New’ Heidegger Babette Babich [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_babich Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Digital Humanities Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Other German Language and Literature Commons, Physical Sciences and Mathematics Commons, Radio Commons, and the Reading and Language Commons Recommended Citation Babich, Babette, "The ‘New’ Heidegger" (2015). Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Collections. 65. https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_babich/65 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at DigitalResearch@Fordham. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles and Chapters in Academic Book Collections by an authorized administrator of DigitalResearch@Fordham. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Chapter 10 The ‘New’ Heidegger Babette Babich 10.1 Calculating Heidegger: From the Old to the New The ‘new’ Heidegger corresponds less to what would or could be the Heidegger of the moment on some imagined ‘cutting edge’ than it corresponds to what some wish they had in Heidegger and above all in philosophical discussions of Heidegger’s thought. We have moved, we suppose, beyond grappling with the Heidegger of Being and Time . And we also tend to suppose a fairly regular recurrence of scandal—the current instantiation infl amed by the recent publication of Heidegger’s private, philosophical, Tagebücher, invokes what the editor of these recently published ‘black notebooks’ attempts to distinguish as Heidegger’s ‘historial antisemitism’ — ‘historial’ here serving to identify Heidegger’s references to World Jewry in one of the volumes.
    [Show full text]
  • Dec. 2016 CURRICULUM VITAE RUTH ABBEY Educational Background Phd in Political Science, Mcgill University, 1995. Di
    Updated – Dec. 2016 CURRICULUM VITAE RUTH ABBEY Educational Background PhD in Political Science, McGill University, 1995. Dissertation: Descent & Dissent: Nietzsche's Reading of Two French Moralists. Supervisor: Charles Taylor. MA in Political Science, McGill University, 1989 Research paper: John Dewey: A Fresh Look BA, Monash University, 1984. First class honours in Political Science and a Major in English. Thesis title: The Liberation of the senses in Karl Marx’s Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844 Career Current Position Professor, Dept. of Political Science, University of Notre Dame Previous Positions 2005-2013 Associate Professor, Dept. of Political Science, University of Notre Dame 2008-2009 Faculty Fellow Murphy Institute for Ethics and Public Affairs Tulane University, New Orleans 2002-2005 Senior Lecturer Department of Politics & International Relations University of Kent at Canterbury 2000-2002 Lecturer in Political Theory, Department of Politics and International Relations, UKC 2000 Senior Lecturer in Philosophy, University of Notre Dame, Australia 1999-2000 Member of the School of Social Science, Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton, New Jersey 2 1999 Acting Director, Politics & Law Program, College of Law, University of Notre Dame, Australia Honorary Research Fellow, Department of Political Science, University of Western Australia. 1997 Visiting Scholar, Faculty of Social & Political Sciences, Cambridge University (Michaelmas Term) 1996-1997 Postdoctoral Fellow in Political Science, University of Western Australia
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School November 2019 Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism Megan Flocken University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Flocken, Megan, "Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism" (2019). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/8098 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Heidegger's Will to Power and the Problem of Nietzsche's Nihilism by Megan Flocken A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Lee Braver, Ph.D. Charles Guignon, Ph.D. Ofelia Schutte, Ph.D. Iain Thomson, Ph.D. Stephen Turner, Ph.D. Date of Approval: November 12, 2019 Keywords: continental philosophy, ontology, comparative philosophy, Kehre Copyright © 2019, Megan Flocken TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT .................................................................................................................................... ii CHAPTER ONE: HEIDEGGER’S WILL TO POWER AND THE PROBLEM OF NIETZSCHE’S
    [Show full text]
  • Pythagorean, Predecessor, and Hebrew: Philo of Alexandria and the Construction of Jewishness in Early Christian Writings
    Pythagorean, Predecessor, and Hebrew: Philo of Alexandria and the Construction of Jewishness in Early Christian Writings Jennifer Otto Faculty of Religious Studies McGill University, Montreal March, 2014 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy © Jennifer Otto, 2014 ii Table of Contents Abstracts v Acknowledgements vii Abbreviations viii Introduction 1 Method, Aims and Scope of the Thesis 10 Christians and Jews among the nations 12 Philo and the Wisdom of the Greeks 16 Christianity as Philosophy 19 Moving Forward 24 Part I Chapter 1: Philo in Modern Scholarship 25 Introducing Philo 25 Philo the Jew in modern research 27 Conclusions 48 Chapter 2: Sects and Texts: The Setting of the Christian Encounter with Philo 54 The Earliest Alexandrian Christians 55 The Trajanic Revolt 60 The “Catechetical School” of Alexandria— A Continuous 63 Jewish-Christian Institution? An Alternative Hypothesis: Reading Philo in the Philosophical Schools 65 Conclusions 70 Part II Chapter 3: The Pythagorean: Clement’s Philo 72 1. Introducing Clement 73 1.1 Clement’s Life 73 1.2 Clement’s Corpus 75 1.3 Clement’s Teaching 78 2. Israel, Hebrews, and Jews in Clement’s Writings 80 2.1 Israel 81 2.2 Hebrews 82 2.3 Jews 83 3. Clement’s Reception of Philo: Literature Review 88 4. Clement’s Testimonia to Philo 97 4.1 Situating the Philonic Borrowings in the context of Stromateis 1 97 4.2 Stromateis 1.5.31 102 4.3 Stromateis 1.15.72 106 4.4 Stromateis 1.23.153 109 iii 4.5 Situating the Philonic Borrowings in the context of Stromateis 2 111 4.6 Stromateis 2.19.100 113 5.
    [Show full text]
  • Patrick A. Heelan, S.J.: Bibliography
    PATRICK A. HEELAN, S.J.: BIBLIOGRAPHY 2001 Book review of: Science Unfettered, by James E. McGuire and Barbara Tuchanska. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press, 2000. Review ofMetaphysics, 55 (200 I). Theological and Philosophical Foundations of Modem Science, in Science and Faith: The Problem of the Human Being in Science and Theology. Ed. by Natalia Pecherskaya. St. Petersburg, Russia: St. Petersburg School of Religion and Philosophy, 2001. Pp. 80-86. Lifeworld and Scientific Interpretation, published on www.georgetown. edulheelan (to be included in the Handbook ofPhenomenology and Medicine, ed. by Kay Toombs). Faith and Reason in the University: Commentary on John Paul Il's Encyclical Fides et Ratio 1998, published on www.georgetown.edu/heelan (to be included in a volume to honor Jean Ladriere, ed. by Jean-Franyois Malherbe). 2000 Bernard J. F. Lonergan as a Contemporary Christian Philosopher: Lonergan and the Measures of God, in The Questions of Christian Philosophy Today. Ed. by Francis Ambrosio. New York: Fordham University Press, 2000. Pp. 165-188. Visual Space as Variable and Task-Oriented: A Study ofVan Gogh's 'Modem; Use of Scientific Perspective, published on www.georgetown.edu/heelan. 1999 Nietzsche's Perspectivalism and the Philosophy of Science, in Nietzsche, Epistemology, and the Philosophy ofScience, Vol. II. Ed. by Babette E. Babich and RobertS. Cohen. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 204. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer, 1999. Pp. 193-209. Hermeneutics and Natural Science, in Continental Philosophers in America. Ed. by James R. Watson. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press 1999. Pp. 64-73. 1998 Scope of Hermeneutics in the Philosophy of Natural Science, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 29 (1998), 273-298.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy
    CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy The Johns Hopkins University Citizen of U.K. Baltimore, MD 21218-2686 Permanent Resident of U.S. Phone: (410) 516-6863 Fax: (410) 516-6848 e-mail: <[email protected]> EDUCATION B.A. Oxford University, 1980, Literae Humaniores (Classics and Philosophy). First Class Honours, Final Examinations, 1980; First Class Honours, Honour Moderations in Greek & Latin Literature, 1978 Ph.D. University of California, Berkeley, 1986, Philosophy. Dissertation Title: “Moral Scepticism: Why Ask ‘Why Should I be Moral?’” CURRENT POSITION Professor and Chair of Philosophy, The Johns Hopkins University; secondary appointment in Classics PREVIOUS POSITIONS Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Texas at Arlington, 1986-1991 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, Jan.-June 1991 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1991-1994 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1994-2000; secondary appointment in Classics, 1996-2000 Acting Executive Director, The American Philosophical Association, Jan. 2000-June 2001 PUBLICATIONS a) Books Sextus Empiricus, Against the Ethicists (Adversus Mathematicos XI): Introduction, Translation and Commentary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997, paperback 2000). Pp. xxxiv + 302 Pyrrho, his Antecedents and his Legacy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000, paperback 2003). Pp. xi + 264 Sextus Empiricus, Against the Logicians (Adversus Mathematicos VII-VIII): Introduction, Translation and Notes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005). Pp. xliv
    [Show full text]
  • QUALIA: What It Is Like to Have an Experience
    QUALIA: What it is like to have an experience Qualia include the ways things look, sound and smell, the way it feels to have a pain, and more generally, what it's like to have experiential mental states. (‘Qualia’ is the plural of ‘quale’.) Qualia are experiential properties of sensations, feelings, perceptions and, more controversially, thoughts and desires as well. But, so defined, who could deny that qualia exist? Although the existence of subjective experience is not (or anyway should not be) controversial, ‘quale’—which is more clearly a technical term than ‘subjective experience’ is more often used by those who are inclined to reject the common-sense conception of subjective experience. Here is a first approximation to a statement of what is controversial: whether the phenomenology of experience can be exhaustively analyzed in intentional, functional or purely cognitive terms. Opponents of qualia think that the phenomenology of an experience can be exhaustively analyzed in terms of its representational or intentional content (“representationism”); or that the phenomenology of experience can be exhaustively analyzed in terms of its causal role (“functionalism”), or that having a subjective experiential state can be exhaustively analyzed in terms of having a state that is cognitively monitored in a certain way or accompanied by a thought to the effect that I have that state. If we include in the definition of ‘qualia’ the idea that the phenomenology of experience outruns such intentional, functional and cognitive analyses, then it is controversial whether there are qualia. This definition of `qualia' is controversial in a respect that is familiar in philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Editorial: Reflections on the Hypatia Controversy: Philosophical Methods and Social Justice
    Document generated on 09/28/2021 3:25 p.m. Atlantis Critical Studies in Gender, Culture & Social Justice Études critiques sur le genre, la culture, et la justice Editorial Reflections on the Hypatia Controversy: Philosophical Methods and Social Justice Alison Suen and Chloë Taylor Volume 39, Number 2, 2018 URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1064072ar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/1064072ar See table of contents Publisher(s) Mount Saint Vincent University ISSN 1715-0698 (digital) Explore this journal Cite this document Suen, A. & Taylor, C. (2018). Editorial: Reflections on the Hypatia Controversy: Philosophical Methods and Social Justice. Atlantis, 39(2), 57–60. https://doi.org/10.7202/1064072ar All Rights Reserved © Mount Saint Vincent University, 2018 This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal. Its mission is to promote and disseminate research. https://www.erudit.org/en/ Special Section: Editorial Reflections on the Hypatia Controversy: Philosophical Methods and Social Justice Alison Suen is an assistant professor of philosophy at his cluster of articles proceeds from a symposium Iona College, New York. She received her BA in Tfunded by both the Social Sciences and Human- Philosophy from the University of Northern Iowa in ities Research Council of Canada and Kule Institute 2006, and her PhD in Philosophy from Vanderbilt for Advanced Studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected]
    Digital Commons @ George Fox University George Fox Evangelical Seminary 2013 Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria Loren Kerns George Fox University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes Part of the Christianity Commons, and the Church History Commons Recommended Citation Kerns, Loren, "Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria" (2013). George Fox Evangelical Seminary. Paper 6. http://digitalcommons.georgefox.edu/gfes/6 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ George Fox University. It has been accepted for inclusion in George Fox Evangelical Seminary by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ George Fox University. Kings College London Platonic and Stoic Passions in Philo of Alexandria A Dissertation submitted to The School of Arts and Humanities In Candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Theology and Religious Studies By Loren Kerns London, United Kingdom July 2013 Copyright by Loren Kerns, 2013 All rights reserved. Abstract Philo of Alexandria forged his theory of the soul and its passions while expositing the meaning of Torah. Though writing as a Jewish teacher and disciple of Moses, his biblical reflections display a strong orientation toward Middle-Platonic philosophy. On the topic of the soul and its passions, however, Philo also exhibits significant Stoic influence. The introduction notes Philo’s apparent incompatible use of both the complex Platonic and the monistic Stoic psychological models. After assessing the degree to which Philo understood 'passion' to be a type of Stoic impulse or opinion (chapter one), chapter two demonstrates that Philo consistently drew upon the Stoics’ depiction of all passions as irrational, excessive, and unnatural.
    [Show full text]