When Science Became Western: Historiographical Reflections Author(S): by Marwa Elshakry Source: Isis, Vol

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

When Science Became Western: Historiographical Reflections Author(S): by Marwa Elshakry Source: Isis, Vol When Science Became Western: Historiographical Reflections Author(s): By Marwa Elshakry Source: Isis, Vol. 101, No. 1 (March 2010), pp. 98-109 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of The History of Science Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/652691 . Accessed: 01/04/2013 12:49 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press and The History of Science Society are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Isis. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 160.39.148.241 on Mon, 1 Apr 2013 12:49:23 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions When Science Became Western Historiographical Reflections By Marwa Elshakry* ABSTRACT While thinking about the notion of the “global” in the history of the history of science, this essay examines a related but equally basic concept: the idea of “Western science.” Tracing its rise in the nineteenth century, it shows how it developed as much outside the Western world as within it. Ironically, while the idea itself was crucial for the disciplinary formation of the history of science, the global history behind this story has not been much attended to. Drawing on examples from nineteenth-century Egypt and China, the essay begins by looking at how international vectors of knowledge production (viz., mission- aries and technocrats) created new global histories of science through the construction of novel genealogies and through a process of conceptual syncretism. Turning next to the work of early professional historians of science, it shows how Arabic and Chinese knowledge traditions were similarly reinterpreted in light of the modern sciences, now viewed as part of a diachronic and universalist teleology ending in “Western science.” It concludes by arguing that examining the global emergence of the idea of Western science in this way highlights key questions pertaining to the relation of the history of science to knowledge traditions across the world and the continuing search for global histories of science. HE CONTINGENCY OF THE TERM “SCIENCE”—shaped by different eras, geog- T raphies, and epistemological traditions—means that it is not always clear what histo- rians of science are or even should be studying. This is a point that medievalists and early modernists have long debated, and it has lent the discipline methodological depth by historicizing the very subject of its inquiry and by suggesting, in particular, what is modern about modern science.1 Yet some contingencies have mattered more than others. Imagine a map of the world as represented by the profession: it would be a largely Anglo-American and Eurasian one, with a severely truncated southern hemisphere and the Atlantic world predominating in the northern one. Ironically, this wasn’t the picture of the world that the discipline began with: indeed, * Department of History, Columbia University, 611 Fayerweather Hall, New York, New York 10027. 1 For the best example see Peter Dear, “What Is the History of Science the History Of? Early Modern Roots of the Ideology of Modern Science,” Isis, 2005, 96:390–406. Isis, 2010, 101:98–109 ©2010 by The History of Science Society. All rights reserved. 0021-1753/2010/10001-0005$10.00 98 This content downloaded from 160.39.148.241 on Mon, 1 Apr 2013 12:49:23 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions F O C FOCUS—ISIS, 101 : 1 (2010) 99 U S early professional historians of science often made much of the fact that they were taking the ecumenical view. But the price of such geographic capaciousness was a serious narrowing of the very idea of science itself. The “many rivers, one sea” of modern science analogy of the early historian of science Joseph Needham—who himself did much to introduce China to the wider world—meant that science was said to have a distinct coherence and flow after all.2 Nowhere is the problem of contingency and disciplinary cohesiveness more acute than across the entire range of studies often classed as “non-Western” science (or sometimes “extra-European” or “non-European” science). The division of the world into the West and the rest has a long history, of course—and the history of science has played a major part in that too. Indeed, in many ways the history of science itself started off by asking if science was the specific product of Western civilization or—in the language of a slightly later era—of the West. Early scholars argued that it was not, while current historians don’t bother to ask the question at all and would probably recoil at the antiquated Eurocentrism embedded in it. Some, though perhaps not as many today as a few decades ago, might even challenge the singularity of the term “science.” Once one begins to speak of a plurality of sciences the question has much less bite—though perhaps also less meaning. The specter of recurring “relativistic nightmares” meant that the postmodern turn never really caught on in the history of science—or, rather, that it did not ultimately impact our epistemological and disciplinary categories in the way that it has for other disciplines. This essay attempts to offer another way out of the twin predicaments of constructivism and relativism by asking how the very concept of “Western science” as the equivalent of “modern science” got established in the first place.3 Concomitantly, it asks how the “history of [this] science”—as opposed to the “history of the sciences”—has shaped our disciplinary categories and range. In order to do this, it will consider the corollary: What did people outside Europe make of the idea of “Western” science? How did their understanding of this change ideas, practices, and disparate categories of knowledge—as well as belief—more broadly?4 I begin by examining nineteenth-century conceptions of modern European sciences in Egypt and China, as seen in particular by Western Christian missionaries and local technocrats. Both Ottoman Egyptian and Qing centers of learning underwent rapid transformations in their communities and institutions of knowledge. Both also had ven- erable traditions of learning of their own that would later come to occupy an important role in the disciplinary origins of the history of science itself. While playing an increasingly important role in official curricula, early discussions of modern sciences did not so much replace older disciplines or traditions of knowledge as redefine them. The very translation of the terms and concepts of these sciences, after all, involved a kind of conceptual syncreticism. Nevertheless, a new notion—and narra- tive—of Western science was also gradually emerging. 2 Joseph Needham, Science and Civilisation in China (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1954–), Vol. 1: Introductory Orientations, p. 16. See also Roger Hart, “Beyond Science and Civilization: A Post-Needham Critique,” East Asian Science, Technology, and Medicine, 1999, 16:88–114. 3 These points—and the reference to “relativistic nightmares”—are building on Peter Dear’s discussion; see Dear, “What Is the History of Science the History Of?” (cit. n. 1), pp. 392, 406. 4 For more on the distinction between knowledge and belief—and its relevance for the history of science, which I will here touch upon only briefly—see Mary Baine Campbell, Lorraine Daston, Arnold Davidson, John Forrester, and Simon Goldhill, “Enlightenment Now: Concluding Reflections on Knowledge and Belief,” Common Knowledge, 2007, 13:429–450. This content downloaded from 160.39.148.241 on Mon, 1 Apr 2013 12:49:23 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 100 FOCUS—ISIS, 101 : 1 (2010) By the interwar era, what was nascent would soon become more concrete: at the hands of early historians of science, the global reach of “science” was equally emphasized. But it was intended for the sake of a universal humanism that might bridge worlds, “East” and “West.” In the process, a much more specific and, in turn, a more universalizing notion of Western science was forged. This conception proved highly resilient, as the use of geographically dichotomous terms like “Western” and “non-Western” demonstrates. This division, moreover, goes well beyond mere expediency; rather, it has a very concrete history of its own, and it is one that may ultimately help us to define what has come to count as science and what has not. Only by setting the history of the sciences in a comparative perspective in this way can we come to appreciate how the concept of “science” gained its particular meaning and power around the world. Viewing the European sciences from outside Europe also allows us to learn something of the ways in which mutual claims on and engagements with the idea of science helped concepts to move across geographic and communal boundaries with astonishing rapidity and, at times, with unexpected synchronicity. After all, one of the main paradoxes in this story is that it was outside “the West” that the concept of “Western science” was itself first developed.5 SCIENCE GLOBALIZED How, then, was the idea of science as simultaneously “modern,” “universal,” and “West- ern” generated—and this despite the fact that there exist some seeming contradictions between these qualifiers? In the nineteenth century an entirely new global discourse around the idea of science emerged.
Recommended publications
  • Works on Giambattista Vico in English from 1884 Through 2009
    Works on Giambattista Vico in English from 1884 through 2009 COMPILED BY MOLLY BLA C K VERENE TABLE OF CON T EN T S PART I. Books A. Monographs . .84 B. Collected Volumes . 98 C. Dissertations and Theses . 111 D. Journals......................................116 PART II. Essays A. Articles, Chapters, et cetera . 120 B. Entries in Reference Works . 177 C. Reviews and Abstracts of Works in Other Languages ..180 PART III. Translations A. English Translations ............................186 B. Reviews of Translations in Other Languages.........192 PART IV. Citations...................................195 APPENDIX. Bibliographies . .302 83 84 NEW VICO STUDIE S 27 (2009) PART I. BOOKS A. Monographs Adams, Henry Packwood. The Life and Writings of Giambattista Vico. London: Allen and Unwin, 1935; reprinted New York: Russell and Russell, 1970. REV I EWS : Gianturco, Elio. Italica 13 (1936): 132. Jessop, T. E. Philosophy 11 (1936): 216–18. Albano, Maeve Edith. Vico and Providence. Emory Vico Studies no. 1. Series ed. D. P. Verene. New York: Peter Lang, 1986. REV I EWS : Daniel, Stephen H. The Eighteenth Century: A Current Bibliography, n.s. 12 (1986): 148–49. Munzel, G. F. New Vico Studies 5 (1987): 173–75. Simon, L. Canadian Philosophical Reviews 8 (1988): 335–37. Avis, Paul. The Foundations of Modern Historical Thought: From Machiavelli to Vico. Beckenham (London): Croom Helm, 1986. REV I EWS : Goldie, M. History 72 (1987): 84–85. Haddock, Bruce A. New Vico Studies 5 (1987): 185–86. Bedani, Gino L. C. Vico Revisited: Orthodoxy, Naturalism and Science in the ‘Scienza nuova.’ Oxford: Berg, 1989. REV I EWS : Costa, Gustavo. New Vico Studies 8 (1990): 90–92.
    [Show full text]
  • A Priori Rules: Wittgenstein on the Normativity of Logic
    A Priori Rules: Wittgenstein on the Normativity of Logic Peter Railton The University of Michigan Introduction Like many, I have long been uneasy with the category of the a priori. Perhaps I have simply misunderstood it. It has seemed to me, at any rate, that asserting a claim or principle as a priori is tantamount to claiming that we would be justified in ruling out alternatives in advance, no matter what the future course of experience might hold. Yet in my own case, I have felt it would be mere bluffing were I to lodge such a claim. I certainly could not discover in myself any sense of the requisite authority, nor even any clear idea of where to look for guidance in forming it. Contemplating widely-used examples of "propositions true a priori" did not remove my worry. For a start, there was the shadow of history. A claim like "logical truth is a priori" or "the attribution of rationality is a priori in intentional explanation" kept sounding, to my ears, as if they echoed "the Euclidean geometry of space is a priori" or "the principle of sufficient reason is a priori in physical explanation". And these echoes awakened just sort of the worry that had initially unsettled me: I would pronouce myself satisfied that certain claims, at least, were safe from the threat of contrary experience, just on the eve of developments in our on-going view of the world that would lead a sensible person to want to reopen the question. So I would emerge looking like the (perhaps apocryphal) fellow who claimed, in the wake of the great inventions of the nineteenth century, that the US Patent Office could now be closed, since all the really new ideas had been used up.
    [Show full text]
  • Atouch of 'Enlightenment'
    2006-2017 Kasturi & Sons Ltd. -Sukumar [email protected] - know saturday, march 17, 2018 BL 8 Ĩ STATES OF MATTER A touch of ‘Enlightenment’ At a time when most pundits are given to despair over the near-collapse of global order, psychologist and linguist Steven Pinker sees immense scope for human betterment masses under their benign sway. The American declaration of independence sukumar is an apt metaphor for what went wrong in the muralidharan Enlightenment project. Agreeing on its reson­ ant formulation that all men are “created equal” and endowed with “certain inalienable rights”, was the easy part. The waffling began the moment it came to making this principle operational in the citizenship law. The US “nat­ uralisation” law adopted in 1790 — a mere 14 years since the declaration of independence — restricted the right of citizenship to “free white persons” of good character. This was foretold in the doctrine pro­ nounced by Kant and its curious insistence that Enlightenment lies in the “free” submis­ sion of all to universal laws, leading to the civic state in which every man would be equal and autonomous and “compelled to be a good citizen”. Kant begins with a notion of “free” submission of all mankind to the universal laws — whatever be his moral attributes — and ends with a certain force of “compulsion” that makes him a good citizen. That force of com­ pulsion would be subtle in some instances, overt and explicit in others. Kant for instance, saw private individuals as meriting the status of citizenship only if they were free, ie, unconstrained by the need to dis­ pose of their labour power in the market to keep body and soul together.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: the Example of Cassirer’S Erkenntnisproblem", in from Hegel to Windelband, Eds
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2015 Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo- Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer’s Erkenntnisproblem Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. "Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer’s Erkenntnisproblem", in From Hegel to Windelband, Eds. Gerald Hartung and Valentin Pluder. Boston : De Gruyter, 2015: 181-205. Publisher Link. © 2015 Walter De Gruyter. Used with permission. Sebastian Luft Philosophical Historiography in Marburg Neo-Kantianism: The Example of Cassirer's Erkenntnisproblem Introduction: Philosophical Historiography as Problem-History. Windelband as Paradigm We can think that "problem-history"l is exclusively a name for one way of philo­ sophical historiography among others. As such it is a method that recounts the history of philosophy in terms of its problems, and not in terms of philosophical personalities or cultural epochs. In this understanding, problem-history proceeds with the naIve assumption that problems exist "in themselves", that they are merely repeated and manifested differently in different epochs. Plainly stated, this sounds both trivial and problematic. And if this reading is true then it is no wonder that problem-history is accorded little interest today, despite the fact that the classical authors of problem-history writing are still readily consulted. Apart from the fact that such writers are still being constantly exploited for re­ search purposes in the present, their works are granted no independent philo­ sophical value. This applies equally to the authors of these works: they are not considered as independent philosophers but "only" as historians.
    [Show full text]
  • Steven Pinker.Pdf
    ‘My20-year-old self wouldbesurprised I’mthrice-married and childless’ the little-known yetmomentous factthatviolence is in historical decline; defined apolitical goal (to identify the causesofour progressand intensify them); and challengedmetotell aparticularly complex story in a compelling way. What do youfind most irritating in otherpeople? Bickering.The costofconflict –in trust and long-term reciprocity –isalmost always greater than whatever’sbeing fought over. If your 20-year-old self could see younow,whatwouldhethink? He’dbesurprisedthatI’m thrice- marriedand childless, relievedthat Ilandedatenuredprofessorship, anddelighted that Icrossedover into writing forawideaudience. Which objectthatyou’velostdo youwish youstillhad? Effortlessmemory fordetails. What is thegreatest challengeofour time? The greatest practical challenge INVENTORY STEVEN PINKER,EXPERIMENTALPSYCHOLOGIST is avoiding catastrophicclimate change. The greatest moral and political challengeisdefending the Enlightenment idealsofreason, Steven Pinker,63, is Johnstone theory from Joan Bresnan,and beautiful in aboxyBauhaus science,humanismand progress. Family professor in the psycholinguistics(andprose style) way,and it makes photography Do youbelieve in anafterlife? departmentofpsychologyat from Roger Brown. But I’mnot asensuous experience. No.The mind depends entirelyon Harvard. He conducts research much of amentee:I’vealways What ambitionsdoyoustill have? thebrain,which is indisputably on language and cognition. gathered ideas and methods from Ialwayshaveseveral book mortal.
    [Show full text]
  • Better Than We Think
    Better than we think July 15, 2018 Unitarian-Universalist Fellowship of Athens Dan: ​ Good morning! Kate and I are excited to be asked to provide summer filler for UUFA. Today we hope to be uplifting and actually we think we have such a message! As is our custom, we will give our message IN STEREO. It has to do with health - and in particular our spiritual health. There are many aspects of our health that we have some control over and some we do not. Aspects we do have some control over are our eating, sleeping, exercising, meditating, singing and loving. Kate: ​ The aspects that we do not have control over include genes, parents, accidents, and state of the world. The first couple of ones we can imagine overcoming but the state of the world - how much poverty, war, violence, illness there is in the world can be a weight on our shoulders that makes it feel impossible to be truly happy when so much suffering is occuring. Dan: ​ But what if there is more good news than we realize in the world? Since most of us UUs do not put our trust in an afterlife that makes things all better nor believe the earth is just a loss leader, a backdrop to heavenly perfection, it matters to us what is happening here on earth. For our uplifting message, we are taking our inspiration from Steven Pinker and his recent book, Enlightenment Now. The information in this book for us was like standing under a waterfall of ​ refreshing news. We will be quoting extensively from his book since it is hard to word it better than he does.
    [Show full text]
  • The Enlightenment Is Working - WSJ
    4/24/2019 The Enlightenment Is Working - WSJ This copy is for your personal, non-commercial use only. To order presentation-ready copies for distribution to your colleagues, clients or customers visit https://www.djreprints.com. https://www.wsj.com/articles/the-enlightenment-is-working-1518191343 IDEAS | THE SATURDAY ESSAY The Enlightenment Is Working Don’t listen to the gloom-sayers. The world has improved by every measure of human flourishing over the past two centuries, and the progress continues, writes Steven Pinker. ILLUSTRATION: ROBERT NEUBECKER By Steven Pinker Feb. 9, 2018 1049 a.m. ET For all their disagreements, the left and the right concur on one thing: The world is getting worse. Whether the decline is visible in inequality, racism and pollution, or in terrorism, crime and moral decay, both sides see profound failings in modernity and a deepening crisis in the West. They look back to various golden ages when America was great, blue-collar workers thrived in unionized jobs, and people found meaning in religion, family, community and nature. Such gloominess is decidedly un-American. The U.S. was founded on the Enlightenment ideal that human ingenuity and benevolence could be channeled by institutions and result in progress. This concept may feel naive as we confront our biggest predicaments, but we can only understand where we are if we know how far we’ve come. You can always fool yourself into seeing a decline if you compare rose-tinted images of the past with bleeding headlines of the present. What do the trajectories of the nation and world look like when we measure human well-being over time with a constant yardstick? Let’s look at the numbers (most of which can be found on websites such as OurWorldinData, HumanProgress and Gapminder).
    [Show full text]
  • Syllabus Enlightenment S21 Course Schedule
    Class Schedule This is just to give you a sense of what readings I have planned, but given the pandemic, I must ask you to be flexible because these dates might have to change. Please always defer to the schedule on Blackboard. Weeks 1 and 2 February 8: What was the Enlightenment, and why do so many people fight about it? • Introductory lecture • In-class primary source workshop February 10: Who were the philosophes? • Andrew Curran lecture on Diderot • Dumarsais, “Philosophe” • Discuss biography paper (read prompt before class) February 15: Sensing the Enlightenment • Purnell, Sensational Past, 11-23, 46-86 • Voltaire, “Prejudice,” Philosophical Dictionary February 17: The body and society • Purnell, Sensational Past, 87-143, 236-241 • Purnell class visit – this class meets at 11:00AM Weeks 3 and 4 February 22: #BHATM • Live chat of Mademoiselle Paradis on Slack • Send me proposal, bibliography for your biography paper February 24: Making and breaking social bonds • Rousseau, Julie • Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals • On Adam Smith and inequality March 1: Human Rights • Cesare Beccaria, An Essay on Crimes and Punishments • Lynn Hunt, Inventing Human Rights, pp. 70-112 March 3: #BHATM • Live-chat of Belle on Slack • Read this review afterwards (or before, if you don’t mind spoilers) • Biography paper due Weeks 5 and 6 March 8: Science, Race, and Gender • Farren Yero, “An Eradication: Empire, Enslaved Children, and the Whitewashing of Vaccine History” • Rebecca Messbarger, The Lady Anatomist: The Life and Work of Anna Morandi Manzolini, 99-118. • Encyclopédie, “Nègre” • Summary of Andrew Curran, Anatomy of Blackness March 10: Education • Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Emile • Catherine Macaulay, Letters on Education March 15: #BHATM • Podcast on genius – heads up c.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Political Theory As an Anti-Enlightenment Project
    Dennis C. Rasmussen Brown University Contemporary Political Theory as an Anti-Enlightenment Project [NB: I am aware that the argument of this paper – that the majority of contemporary political theorists seek to dissociate themselves from the Enlightenment – isn’t actually much of an argument. I am currently beginning a book project that will seek to defend the Enlightenment (to some extent or another) from the attacks of its contemporary critics; the material gathered here includes part of the introduction and the introductions to each of the five substantive chapters, along with a few underdeveloped remarks at the beginning and end that seek to tie things together. In other words, this material wasn’t written as a stand-alone paper, so I apologize if it seems incomplete – it is! I also apologize for the length; for those who don’t have the time or desire to read it all, the main line of argument comes in the first 18 pages, with the rest fleshing out some details. I will, however, be eager to hear your thoughts about the charges I have outlined, and especially if I have missed any major critics or criticisms of the Enlightenment.] Like it or not, we are all children of the Enlightenment, utterly incapable of escaping the clutches of ideals and arguments put forth over two centuries ago. Or so, at least, many critics of the Enlightenment seem to believe. Michel Foucault claims, for instance, that the Enlightenment has largely determined “what we are, what we think, and what we do today,”1 and John Gray insists that “all schools of contemporary political thought are variations on the Enlightenment project.”2 There is, of course, something to such claims: given the number of values, practices, and institutions that we have inherited from the eighteenth century, it is difficult to imagine what our world would look like without its Enlightenment heritage.
    [Show full text]
  • Pythagorean, Predecessor, and Hebrew: Philo of Alexandria and the Construction of Jewishness in Early Christian Writings
    Pythagorean, Predecessor, and Hebrew: Philo of Alexandria and the Construction of Jewishness in Early Christian Writings Jennifer Otto Faculty of Religious Studies McGill University, Montreal March, 2014 A thesis submitted to McGill University in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy © Jennifer Otto, 2014 ii Table of Contents Abstracts v Acknowledgements vii Abbreviations viii Introduction 1 Method, Aims and Scope of the Thesis 10 Christians and Jews among the nations 12 Philo and the Wisdom of the Greeks 16 Christianity as Philosophy 19 Moving Forward 24 Part I Chapter 1: Philo in Modern Scholarship 25 Introducing Philo 25 Philo the Jew in modern research 27 Conclusions 48 Chapter 2: Sects and Texts: The Setting of the Christian Encounter with Philo 54 The Earliest Alexandrian Christians 55 The Trajanic Revolt 60 The “Catechetical School” of Alexandria— A Continuous 63 Jewish-Christian Institution? An Alternative Hypothesis: Reading Philo in the Philosophical Schools 65 Conclusions 70 Part II Chapter 3: The Pythagorean: Clement’s Philo 72 1. Introducing Clement 73 1.1 Clement’s Life 73 1.2 Clement’s Corpus 75 1.3 Clement’s Teaching 78 2. Israel, Hebrews, and Jews in Clement’s Writings 80 2.1 Israel 81 2.2 Hebrews 82 2.3 Jews 83 3. Clement’s Reception of Philo: Literature Review 88 4. Clement’s Testimonia to Philo 97 4.1 Situating the Philonic Borrowings in the context of Stromateis 1 97 4.2 Stromateis 1.5.31 102 4.3 Stromateis 1.15.72 106 4.4 Stromateis 1.23.153 109 iii 4.5 Situating the Philonic Borrowings in the context of Stromateis 2 111 4.6 Stromateis 2.19.100 113 5.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy
    CURRICULUM VITAE RICHARD BETT Department of Philosophy The Johns Hopkins University Citizen of U.K. Baltimore, MD 21218-2686 Permanent Resident of U.S. Phone: (410) 516-6863 Fax: (410) 516-6848 e-mail: <[email protected]> EDUCATION B.A. Oxford University, 1980, Literae Humaniores (Classics and Philosophy). First Class Honours, Final Examinations, 1980; First Class Honours, Honour Moderations in Greek & Latin Literature, 1978 Ph.D. University of California, Berkeley, 1986, Philosophy. Dissertation Title: “Moral Scepticism: Why Ask ‘Why Should I be Moral?’” CURRENT POSITION Professor and Chair of Philosophy, The Johns Hopkins University; secondary appointment in Classics PREVIOUS POSITIONS Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Texas at Arlington, 1986-1991 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, Jan.-June 1991 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1991-1994 Associate Professor of Philosophy, Johns Hopkins, 1994-2000; secondary appointment in Classics, 1996-2000 Acting Executive Director, The American Philosophical Association, Jan. 2000-June 2001 PUBLICATIONS a) Books Sextus Empiricus, Against the Ethicists (Adversus Mathematicos XI): Introduction, Translation and Commentary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997, paperback 2000). Pp. xxxiv + 302 Pyrrho, his Antecedents and his Legacy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000, paperback 2003). Pp. xi + 264 Sextus Empiricus, Against the Logicians (Adversus Mathematicos VII-VIII): Introduction, Translation and Notes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005). Pp. xliv
    [Show full text]
  • QUALIA: What It Is Like to Have an Experience
    QUALIA: What it is like to have an experience Qualia include the ways things look, sound and smell, the way it feels to have a pain, and more generally, what it's like to have experiential mental states. (‘Qualia’ is the plural of ‘quale’.) Qualia are experiential properties of sensations, feelings, perceptions and, more controversially, thoughts and desires as well. But, so defined, who could deny that qualia exist? Although the existence of subjective experience is not (or anyway should not be) controversial, ‘quale’—which is more clearly a technical term than ‘subjective experience’ is more often used by those who are inclined to reject the common-sense conception of subjective experience. Here is a first approximation to a statement of what is controversial: whether the phenomenology of experience can be exhaustively analyzed in intentional, functional or purely cognitive terms. Opponents of qualia think that the phenomenology of an experience can be exhaustively analyzed in terms of its representational or intentional content (“representationism”); or that the phenomenology of experience can be exhaustively analyzed in terms of its causal role (“functionalism”), or that having a subjective experiential state can be exhaustively analyzed in terms of having a state that is cognitively monitored in a certain way or accompanied by a thought to the effect that I have that state. If we include in the definition of ‘qualia’ the idea that the phenomenology of experience outruns such intentional, functional and cognitive analyses, then it is controversial whether there are qualia. This definition of `qualia' is controversial in a respect that is familiar in philosophy.
    [Show full text]