Cicero and the Epicureans

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Cicero and the Epicureans Among Friends: Cicero and the Epicureans by Nathan Gilbert A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Classics University of Toronto © Copyright by Nathan Gilbert 2015 ii Among Friends: Cicero and the Epicureans Nathan Gilbert Doctor of Philosophy Department of Classics University of Toronto 2015 In my dissertation I explain Cicero’s philosophical works through an analysis of his epistolary interactions and literary rivalries with Roman Epicureans. I argue that this historical and intellectual context reveals how Cicero’s overt and consistent anti-Epicurean polemics constitute a fundamental organizing principle of his philosophical works; Epicureanism is the philosophical Other against which the dialogues define themselves. The first two chapters of my thesis reconstruct Cicero’s social and friendship networks of Roman Epicureans and literary rivals; to that end I offer a series of prosopographical charts designed to replace the now dated Prosopography of Roman Epicureans by Catherine Castner. The second half of my thesis uses this background to explain the development and recurring polemical goals of Cicero’s philosophical works. More specifically, the third chapter begins to build my larger claim that his epistolary interactions with Epicureans over the course of twenty years offered him the opportunity to hone his argumentative technique and experiment with various translations into Latin of Greek philosophical ideas. In my final two chapters I offer the first comprehensive reading of Cicero’s exchange with Cassius in 46-45 BCE (Ad Fam. 15.16-19) and argue that these letters allow us to trace the development of individual arguments and polemical strategies in the dialogues of later that year, especially De Finibus I-II. My dissertation therefore stands at the intersection of literary, philosophical, and historical scholarship. I engage with and enrich recent work in Republican epistolary iii practice, the cultural politics of Ciceronian prefaces, the influence of Epicurean ideas on Latin poetry, and the renewed interest in Philodemus, Hellenistic philosophy, Roman Epicureanism, and Cicero as a philosopher. iv Acknowledgements The advice, kindness and time of many scholars and friends have made a positive and lasting impact on my dissertation; it is a great pleasure to finally acknowledge in writing their contributions. Above all I owe a debt a gratitude to my supervisor, Brad Inwood. Despite his many professional and scholarly obligations, he invariably found time to meet, read chapters, and offer criticism and support; his supervision went far beyond the requirements of his job. More generally, his ability to provide sharp criticism in a non-polemical spirit, his willingness to entertain disagreement, and his unique combination of training in Classics and philosophy represent an ideal of scholarship to which I can only aspire. I also owe hearty thanks to Rachel Barney, who stuck with me even as I crossed time and space to work on Cicero instead of the sophists. Her incisive writing feedback in the early years of my graduate studies and her later criticisms of my thesis chapters not only increased the quality of my dissertation but also made me a much better writer. I am grateful to the other members of my committee, Christer Bruun and John Magee, for making time to work with me while they were either on leave or serving as departmental chairs. I profited greatly from discussions with David Armstrong and Pamela Gordon; both were kind enough to share with me their unpublished work. Thanks also to Katharina Volk, who likewise shared her unpublished work. I am furthermore grateful to Adriana Brook, Marion Durand, John MacCormick, and Larkin Philpot—my brothers and sisters in graduate arms—for their detailed advice, editorial and otherwise. Finally, I would like to dedicate this thesis to my father, Jeff (1951-2005): while I am not sure he would have enjoyed reading it, I know without a doubt that he would have been very proud that I had written it. v Table of Contents Introduction: Cicero, Epicurus, and Roman Epicureanism………………………….. 1-12 Part I: Historical and Social Background Chapter I: “The Epicureans have taken over all of Italy”…………………… 13-77 Chapter II: Cicero’s Epicurean Friends, Teachers and Correspondents…….. 78-115 Part II: Epistolary Debates and Cicero’s Philosophical Works Chapter III: Anti-Epicurean Polemics in the Letters………………………... 116-163 Chapter IV: Epicureanism in Ad Familiares 15.16-19, Part I………………. 164-220 Chapter V: Epicureanism in Ad Familiares 15.16-19, Part II……………… 221-283 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………… 284-286 Bibliography…………………………………………………………………………. 287-305 Figure I: Roman Epicureans, 155-43 B.C…………………………………………… 112-114 Figure II: Cicero’s Epicurean Intellectual Network…………………………………. 115 1 Introduction: Cicero, Epicurus, and Roman Epicureans Ante lucem cum scriberem contra Epicureos, de eodem oleo et opera exaravi nescio quid ad te et ante lucem dedi. Before dawn while I was writing against the Epicureans, by the same oil and effort I scribbled a note and sent it to you before dawn. (Ad Atticum 13.38 = SB 341, mid-August, 45 B.C.)1 That Cicero was consistently unsympathetic or even openly hostile to Epicurean philosophy is not a particularly surprising claim, nor is such a claim new.2 Philosophical authors before and after Cicero’s time routinely included in their works scathing passages of polemic against Epicureanism, whose scandalous account of the gods and shocking egoistic hedonism made the school a common enemy of Peripatetics, Platonists, and Stoics.3 That Cicero, a committed Academic Skeptic,4 took part in this polemical tradition and devoted 1 For the letters, I have followed the translations of Shackleton Bailey’s Cambridge editions, though with modifications, particularly on philosophical matters. I have also followed Smith and Rouse 1992 for Lucretius, and Brittain 2006 for the Academica, again sometimes with modifications. All other translations are my own unless otherwise noted. All dates are B.C. unless otherwise noted. 2 E.g. Reid 1885: 19; D’Anna 1965: 7-22; Gorman 2005: 97; Maso 2008; Brunt 2012: 181. A few scholars have seen a development in Cicero’s hostility (notably Howe 1951 and Maslowski 1985), but their views have failed to gain traction: see further Chapter I, section iii.B. 3 Early evidence is fragmentary; the best and most complete examples of this polemical tradition postdate Cicero. Arrian included two short anti-Epicurean lectures of the Stoic Epictetus in his Discourses (2.20, 3.7); Plutarch wrote three lengthier treatises with similar goals (It is impossible to live pleasantly according to Epicurus; Against Colotes; Is “live unknown” a wise precept?; cf. On Affection for Offspring); and while Seneca had nice things to say about Epicurus in the first thirty or so letters of the Epistulae Morales, the violence of his polemics in Book IV of De Beneficiis reveals a very different view (cf. Inwood 2005: 16). But this hostility was much older and predated Cicero. See e.g. SVF 1.553 and 3.709 (Cleanthes and Chrysippus, respectively); cf. all the lively Hellenistic slander documented in Epicurus’ vita in D.L. 10. Academic skeptics also took aim at Epicurus: e.g. Carneades’ thought experiment, reported by Cicero at Fin. 2.59, has an anti- Epicurean thrust; Arcesilaus pulled no punches when he compared Epicureans to eunuchs (D.L. 4.43). 4 This thesis works under the assumption that Cicero was a life-long and committed Academic skeptic. Some scholars (notably Glucker 1988 and Steinmetz 1989) have argued for a temporary lapse to the school of Antiochus of Ascalon. However, Görler 1995 has offered persuasive refutations of their arguments (the reservations of Dolganov 2008: 36 do not convince), and Schofield 2008 has shown how deeply Cicero’s Academic views structured and influenced almost all of his philosophical work (cf. Schofield 2013 and Fox 2007). See Brittain 2001 on Cicero’s teacher Philo and Academic skepticism more generally; and Brittain 2 energy to refuting Epicurus’ doctrines in his published5 philosophical works6 therefore seems only natural. This, of course, does not mean that Cicero’s disdain for the school is uninteresting, and as such scholars have been examining his arguments against various Epicurean positions in ethics and physics for some time now, both in order to better understand Cicero’s own ideas and to establish his value as a source for Epicurean doctrine,7 for which his treatises are especially important.8 This study approaches his opposition to Epicureanism from a very different perspective. I seek to explain the development of Cicero’s philosophica, including his translations of Greek technical language, his general strategies of philosophical and literary polemics, and even individual arguments in his treatises through an analysis of his epistolary interactions with his Roman Epicurean contemporaries and through his literary rivalries with early authors of Epicurean treatises in Latin. My approach, then, is sociological and consequently relies heavily on the ability of his letters to document his social networks of Epicurean acquaintences as well as his philosophical debates with them. This approach is an 2006: xi-xii for a brief, sensible reading of Cicero’s stance. A continued skeptical allegiance is now generally accepted. 5 By “publication” I mean to refer only to an author’s decision to have a work distributed, often informally, beyond a small circle of friends or a single addressee. For discussion of the dissemination of ancient literary works, see Starr 1987, Murphy 1998, Steel 2005: 10-13, and Johnson 2011: 52-6. 6 For simplicity I use the terms “philosophical works,” “philosophica,” and “dialogues” interchangeably; I intend these phrases to include all of Cicero’s published treatises with the exception of the rhetorical works (i.e. Inv., De Or., Brutus, Orator), speeches, poems, and translations. I readily admit that this is an artificial category (Cicero, for example, includes his rhetorical works in his philosophical catalogue in the preface to Div.
Recommended publications
  • Cronache Ercolanesi Ercolanesi
    CRONACHE CRONACHE ERCOLANESI ERCOLANESI bollettino del centro internazionale per lo studio dei papiri ercolanesi fondato da Marcello Gigante 38/2008 direzione Graziano Arrighetti Knut Kleve Francesca Longo Auricchio redazione Giovanni Indelli Giuliana Leone 3 8 / 2 00 8 MACCHIAROLI EDITORE CRONACHE ERCOLANESI bollettino del centro internazionale per lo studio dei papiri ercolanesi fondato da Marcello Gigante 38/2008 direzione Graziano Arrighetti Knut Kleve Francesca Longo Auricchio redazione Giovanni Indelli Giuliana Leone MACCHIAROLI EDITORE CRONACHE ERCOLANESI - NUOVA SERIE QUESTA PUBBLICAZIONE REALIZZATA CON IL PATROCINIO DELLA PROVINCIA DI NAPOLI EDELCOMUNEDI ERCOLANO SI AVVALEDI UN CONTRIBUTO DEL MINISTERO PER I BENI E LE ATTIVITAÁ CULTURALI EDELLAREGIONECAMPANIA Questo «Bollettino» pubblica in volumi annuali Bando di concorso per tre borse di studio di ricerca sui Papiri Ercolanesi emanato articoli di papirologia e archeologia ercolanesi. dall'Istituto Banco di Napoli - Fondazione e dal CISPE Gli articoli vanno inviati in forma definitiva per Art. 1. EÁ indetto un concorso per titoli a tre perloStudiodeiPapiriErcolanesi`MarcelloGi- la stampa. borse di studio per l'anno 2008/2009. Possono gante'. Il tema di ricerca saraÁ stabilito in accordo Al testo va allegato un dischetto (sistema Macin- partecipare tutti coloro che siano in possesso di con l'Assemblea del Centro. I risultati della ricerca tosh, Word). Font: Times New Roman e Super- un diploma di laurea in discipline classiche pre saranno pubblicati nelle «Cronache Ercolanesi». Greek. D. M. 509/99 ovvero di laurea specialistica/ma- Art. 4. La domanda di ammissione al concorso, Si raccomanda di indicare l'indirizzo al quale gistrale in discipline classiche (D. M. 509/99 e D.
    [Show full text]
  • The Morals, Vol. 2 [1878]
    The Online Library of Liberty A Project Of Liberty Fund, Inc. Plutarch, The Morals, vol. 2 [1878] The Online Library Of Liberty This E-Book (PDF format) is published by Liberty Fund, Inc., a private, non-profit, educational foundation established in 1960 to encourage study of the ideal of a society of free and responsible individuals. 2010 was the 50th anniversary year of the founding of Liberty Fund. It is part of the Online Library of Liberty web site http://oll.libertyfund.org, which was established in 2004 in order to further the educational goals of Liberty Fund, Inc. To find out more about the author or title, to use the site's powerful search engine, to see other titles in other formats (HTML, facsimile PDF), or to make use of the hundreds of essays, educational aids, and study guides, please visit the OLL web site. This title is also part of the Portable Library of Liberty DVD which contains over 1,000 books and quotes about liberty and power, and is available free of charge upon request. The cuneiform inscription that appears in the logo and serves as a design element in all Liberty Fund books and web sites is the earliest-known written appearance of the word “freedom” (amagi), or “liberty.” It is taken from a clay document written about 2300 B.C. in the Sumerian city-state of Lagash, in present day Iraq. To find out more about Liberty Fund, Inc., or the Online Library of Liberty Project, please contact the Director at [email protected]. LIBERTY FUND, INC.
    [Show full text]
  • Vestal Virgins and Their Families
    Vestal Virgins and Their Families Andrew B. Gallia* I. INTRODUCTION There is perhaps no more shining example of the extent to which the field of Roman studies has been enriched by a renewed engagement with anthropology and other cognate disciplines than the efflorescence of interest in the Vestal virgins that has followed Mary Beard’s path-breaking article regarding these priestesses’ “sexual status.”1 No longer content to treat the privileges and ritual obligations of this priesthood as the vestiges of some original position (whether as wives or daughters) in the household of the early Roman kings, scholars now interrogate these features as part of the broader frameworks of social and cultural meaning through which Roman concepts of family, * Published in Classical Antiquity 34.1 (2015). Early versions of this article were inflicted upon audiences in Berkeley and Minneapolis. I wish to thank the participants of those colloquia for helpful and judicious feedback, especially Ruth Karras, Darcy Krasne, Carlos Noreña, J. B. Shank, and Barbara Welke. I am also indebted to George Sheets, who read a penultimate draft, and to Alain Gowing and the anonymous readers for CA, who prompted additional improvements. None of the above should be held accountable for the views expressed or any errors that remain. 1 Beard 1980, cited approvingly by, e.g., Hopkins 1983: 18, Hallett 1984: x, Brown 1988: 8, Schultz 2012: 122. Critiques: Gardner 1986: 24-25, Beard 1995. 1 gender, and religion were produced.2 This shift, from a quasi-diachronic perspective, which seeks explanations for recorded phenomena in the conditions of an imagined past, to a more synchronic approach, in which contemporary contexts are emphasized, represents a welcome methodological advance.
    [Show full text]
  • Pliny the Elder and the Problem of Regnum Hereditarium*
    Pliny the Elder and the Problem of Regnum Hereditarium* MELINDA SZEKELY Pliny the Elder writes the following about the king of Taprobane1 in the sixth book of his Natural History: "eligi regem a populo senecta clementiaque, liberos non ha- bentem, et, si postea gignat, abdicari, ne fiat hereditarium regnum."2 This account es- caped the attention of the majority of scholars who studied Pliny in spite of the fact that this sentence raises three interesting and debated questions: the election of the king, deposal of the king and the heredity of the monarchy. The issue con- cerning the account of Taprobane is that Pliny here - unlike other reports on the East - does not only use the works of former Greek and Roman authors, but he also makes a note of the account of the envoys from Ceylon arriving in Rome in the first century A. D. in his work.3 We cannot exclude the possibility that Pliny himself met the envoys though this assumption is not verifiable.4 First let us consider whether the form of rule described by Pliny really existed in Taprobane. We have several sources dealing with India indicating that the idea of that old and gentle king depicted in Pliny's sentence seems to be just the oppo- * The study was supported by OTKA grant No. T13034550. 1 Ancient name of Sri Lanka (until 1972, Ceylon). 2 Plin. N. H. 6, 24, 89. Pliny, Natural History, Cambridge-London 1989, [19421], with an English translation by H. Rackham. 3 Plin. N. H. 6, 24, 85-91. Concerning the Singhalese envoys cf.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Date of the Trial of Anaxagoras
    The Classical Quarterly http://journals.cambridge.org/CAQ Additional services for The Classical Quarterly: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here On the Date of the Trial of Anaxagoras A. E. Taylor The Classical Quarterly / Volume 11 / Issue 02 / April 1917, pp 81 - 87 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838800013094, Published online: 11 February 2009 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0009838800013094 How to cite this article: A. E. Taylor (1917). On the Date of the Trial of Anaxagoras. The Classical Quarterly, 11, pp 81-87 doi:10.1017/S0009838800013094 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/CAQ, IP address: 128.122.253.212 on 28 Apr 2015 ON THE DATE OF THE TRIAL OF ANAXAGORAS. IT is a point of some interest to the historian of the social and intellectual development of Athens to determine, if possible, the exact dates between which the philosopher Anaxagoras made that city his home. As everyone knows, the tradition of the third and later centuries was not uniform. The dates from which the Alexandrian chronologists had to arrive at their results may be conveniently summed up under three headings, (a) date of Anaxagoras' arrival at Athens, (6) date of his prosecution and escape to Lampsacus, (c) length of his residence at Athens, (a) The received account (Diogenes Laertius ii. 7),1 was that Anaxagoras was twenty years old at the date of the invasion of Xerxes and lived to be seventy-two. This was apparently why Apollodorus (ib.) placed his birth in Olympiad 70 and his death in Ol.
    [Show full text]
  • As Guest, Some Pages Are Restricted
    RELIG IONS ' ANCIENT AND MODERN B EDWARD GLODD au h o The Stor o Crea t o i n . Animism . y , t r of y f P B 'AMES ALLANSON PI CTON au h o f The li ion o the anth eism. y , t or Re g f Th li fAn en China . B P s G ILES LL . D . P s e Re g ions o ci t y rofes or , rofe sor f h e iv am d o Ch inese in t U n ersit o f C bri ge. B ' E H R R ISO u at Th e l i n f An i n . L Re ig o o c e t reece y AN A N , ect rer Ne vnha m C ll Camb d a u h o of Prole omm a. t o Stud o Greek v o ege, ri ge, t r g y f Rel igion . h e R H on. AMBER AL I SYED f h ud l m f His I B t t . o t e ' a C m e o slam. y , ici o itt e ’ s C un l au h o of The S it o slam and E hics o Isla m. Maje ty s Privy o ci , t r pir f I t f M i and Fe i hism . B Dr. A. C . H ADDON L u o n ag e t s y , ect rer hnolo a Ca m d e n s gt gy t bri g U iver ity .
    [Show full text]
  • Iamblichus and Julian''s ''Third Demiurge'': a Proposition
    Iamblichus and Julian”s ”Third Demiurge”: A Proposition Adrien Lecerf To cite this version: Adrien Lecerf. Iamblichus and Julian”s ”Third Demiurge”: A Proposition . Eugene Afonasin; John M. Dillon; John F. Finamore. Iamblichus and the Foundations of Late Platonism, 13, BRILL, p. 177-201, 2012, Ancient Mediterranean and Medieval Texts and Contexts. Studies in Platonism, Neoplatonism, and the Platonic Tradition, 10.1163/9789004230118_012. hal-02931399 HAL Id: hal-02931399 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02931399 Submitted on 6 Sep 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Iamblichus and Julian‟s “Third Demiurge”: A Proposition Adrien Lecerf Ecole Normale Supérieure, Paris, France [email protected] ABSTRACT. In the Emperor Julian's Oration To the Mother of the Gods, a philosophical interpretation of the myth of Cybele and Attis, reference is made to an enigmatic "third Demiurge". Contrary to a common opinion identifying him to the visible Helios (the Sun), or to tempting identifications to Amelius' and Theodorus of Asine's three Demiurges, I suggest that a better idea would be to compare Julian's text to Proclus' system of Demiurges (as exposed and explained in a Jan Opsomer article, "La démiurgie des jeunes dieux selon Proclus", Les Etudes Classiques, 71, 2003, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Proquest Dissertations
    Justice ou amitie ? Les fondements aristoteliciens et epicuriens de la communaute Jean-Philippe Ranger These soumise a la Faculte des etudes superieures et postdoctorales de I'Universite d'Ottawa et a l'£cole Doctorale 5 : Concepts et langages de I'Universite Paris IV (Sorbonne) dans le cadre des exigences du programme de doctorat en cotutelle de these Sous la codirection de Catherine Collobert (Ottawa) et Jonathan Barnes (Paris IV) Departement de Philosophie Faculte des arts Universite d'Ottawa UFR Philosophie Universite Paris IV © Jean-Philippe Ranger, Ottawa, Canada, 2007 Library and Bibliotheque et 1*1 Archives Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de I'edition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington Ottawa ON K1A0N4 Ottawa ON K1A0N4 Canada Canada Your file Votre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-49393-9 Our file Notre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-49393-9 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accorde une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library permettant a la Bibliotheque et Archives and Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par telecommunication ou par Plntemet, prefer, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des theses partout dans loan, distribute and sell theses le monde, a des fins commerciales ou autres, worldwide, for commercial or non­ sur support microforme, papier, electronique commercial purposes, in microform, et/ou autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriete du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in et des droits moraux qui protege cette these.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cappadocian Milieu 14:00 - 16:00 Tuesday, 20Th August, 2019 East School Presentation Type Short Communications Ilaria
    The Cappadocian Milieu 14:00 - 16:00 Tuesday, 20th August, 2019 East School Presentation type Short Communications Ilaria 518 Basil and Amelius Arnaud PERROT Ecole normale supérieure, Paris, France Abstract Basil’s Homily on the word: ‘In the beginning was the Word (John 1:1)’ alludes to the admiration of the pagans for the prologue of the Gospel of John and to how the pagans are supposed to have made use of this text in their own writings. Behind these words, one can easily recognize an allusion to the Neoplatonist Amelius, Plotinus’ senior disciple. Basil’s Neoplatonism has been the subject of much debate, especially as far as his direct knowledge of Plotinus is concerned. In this paper, I will show that Basil has certainly not read Amelius, but, exactly like the other Christian writers who referred to Amelius’ testimony, is dependent here on Eusebius’ Evangelical Preparation and the way the Palestinian bishop had more or less coined Amelius’ testimony on the value of John’s Prologue. 896 Sympatheia and the Body of Christ in Basil of Caesarea Thomas Tatterfield Boston College, Chestnut Hill, USA Abstract It is no secret that Basil of Caesarea utilizes the Stoic philosophical concept of sympatheia in his cosmology. This article's point of departure is an article on the subject by N. Joseph Torchia in which various Plotinian parallels are discussed. Once sympatheia is understood in its broader usage, Basil's unique treatment of it is revealed. This paper argues that Basil's use of sympatheia is integrated in to his treatment of the unity of the Church.
    [Show full text]
  • Phoenix from the Ashes Kleve.Pdf (826.1Kb)
    PHOENIX FROM THE ASHES: LUCRETIUS AND ENNIUS IN HERCULANEUM Knut Kleve Otto Skutsch in memoriam The Library in Herculaneum When the king of Naples dug for art treasures under the lava in Herculaneum in the 1750's, he also came upon a library consisting of two thousand heavily carbonized and petrified papyrus scrolls. By means of a glue method invented by A. Piaggio eight hundred scrolls were unrolled in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. The remaining one thousand and eight hundred scrolls were regarded as hopeless.1 In the 1980's, however, Piaggio's method was refined by the Norwegian Brynjulf Fosse and the opening of the scrolls has now started again in the National Library of Naples, where they are housed.2 The papyri aroused great expectations when they were found. One looked forward to new tragedies of Euripides, the Annals of Ennius, and unknown books of Tacitus. The disappointment was great when what came to light were dry, philosophical works in Greek. The so-called Papyrus Villa, where the library was found, turned out to be an Epicurean school on Roman soil with Philodemus of Gadara, a contemporary of Cicero, as head master. Scores of treatises under his name were unrolled: "On Rhetoric", "On Signs", "On Death", "On Music", "On Economy", "On Piety", "On the Gods", etc.3 When Fosse resumed the opening, Professor M. Gigante, who is the director of the international papyrus centre in Naples, prayed:"no more Philodemus!" There was, of course, more Philodemus, but also something different and interesting which indicates that the old expectations had not been all that unrealistic.
    [Show full text]
  • The Polemical Practice in Ancient Epicureanism* M
    UDK 101.1;141.5 Вестник СПбГУ. Философия и конфликтология. 2019. Т. 35. Вып. 3 The polemical practice in ancient Epicureanism* M. M. Shakhnovich St. Petersburg State University, 7–9, Universitetskaya nab., St. Petersburg, 199034, Russian Federation For citation: Shakhnovich M. M. The polemical practice in ancient Epicureanism. Vestnik of Saint Petersburg University. Philosophy and Conflict Studies, 2019, vol. 35, issue 3, pp. 461–471. https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu17.2019.306 The article explores the presentation methods of a philosophical doctrine in Greek and Ro- man Epicureanism; it is shown that for the ancient, middle, and Roman Epicureans a con- troversy with representatives of other philosophical schools was a typical way of present- ing their own views. The polemical practice, in which the basic principles of Epicureanism were expounded through the criticism of other philosophical systems, first of all, Academics and Stoics, was considered not only as the preferred way of presenting the own doctrine, but also as the most convenient rhetorical device, which had, among other things, didac- tic significance. The founder of the school, Epicurus, often included in his texts the terms used in other philosophical schools, giving them a different, often opposite, content. While presenting his teaching in the treatise “On Nature” or in letters to his followers, Epicurus pushed off the opinions of Democritus, Plato, and the Stoics, but resorted mainly to implicit criticism of his opponents, often without naming them by name. His closest students and later followers — Metrodorus, Hermarchus, Colotes, Philodemus, Lucretius, Diogenes of Oenoanda — continuing the controversy with the Academics and the Stoics, more frank- ly expressed their indignation about the “falsely understood Epicureanism” or erroneous opinions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Sophistic Roman: Education and Status in Quintilian, Tacitus and Pliny Brandon F. Jones a Dissertation Submitted in Partial
    The Sophistic Roman: Education and Status in Quintilian, Tacitus and Pliny Brandon F. Jones A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2015 Reading Committee: Alain Gowing, Chair Catherine Connors Alexander Hollmann Deborah Kamen Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics ©Copyright 2015 Brandon F. Jones University of Washington Abstract The Sophistic Roman: Education and Status in Quintilian, Tacitus and Pliny Brandon F. Jones Chair of Supervisory Commitee: Professor Alain Gowing Department of Classics This study is about the construction of identity and self-promotion of status by means of elite education during the first and second centuries CE, a cultural and historical period termed by many as the Second Sophistic. Though the Second Sophistic has traditionally been treated as a Greek cultural movement, individual Romans also viewed engagement with a past, Greek or otherwise, as a way of displaying education and authority, and, thereby, of promoting status. Readings of the work of Quintilian, Tacitus and Pliny, first- and second-century Latin prose authors, reveal a remarkable engagement with the methodologies and motivations employed by their Greek contemporaries—Dio of Prusa, Plutarch, Lucian and Philostratus, most particularly. The first two chapters of this study illustrate and explain the centrality of Greek in the Roman educational system. The final three chapters focus on Roman displays of that acquired Greek paideia in language, literature and oratory, respectively. As these chapters demonstrate, the social practices of paideia and their deployment were a multi-cultural phenomenon. Table of Contents Acknowledgements ........................................................................... 2 Introduction ....................................................................................... 4 Chapter One.
    [Show full text]