The Metaphysics of Similarity and Analogical Reasoning

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Metaphysics of Similarity and Analogical Reasoning THE METAPHYSICS OF SIMILARITY AND ANALOGICAL REASONING A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE DIVISION OF THE UNIVERSITY OF HAWAI‘I AT MĀNOA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN PHILOSOPHY by Jarrod Brown August 2018 Dissertation Committee Members: Tamara Albertini Aridam Chakrabarti (chairperson) Vrinda Dalmiya George Tsai Amy Schafer Jesse Knutson Keywords: analogy, similarity, comparative philosophy, relations 1 ABSTRACT This work introduces the importance of similarity and analogy to philosophy, argues that analogy should be seen as “similarity based reasoning,” overviews different philosophical discussions to illustrate the scope of similarity-based reasoning, and introduces the assumptions for similarity-based reasoning that form the central topics of the present work. It demonstrates that approaches that reduce or identify relations to non-relational ontological categories fail primarily through the strategy of seeking truthmakers for relational claims. It takes up the related problems of co-mannered relations, substitution instances, individuating relations and similarities. It attacks the notion that substitution instances provide a non-relational account of relations and provides a proof that similarity is a more fundamental concept than substitution. Given, however, that similarity is relational, it argues relations are non-reducible to non-relational entities, but that if given the notion of relating in general and of similarity, one can construct a non-reductive theory of relations that can individuate all relations, including similarity relations themselves. This provides a workable theory of relations, but does not solve problems related to the epistemology of relations and similarity. Sanskritic debates concerning the metaphysical nature of similarity and its knowability are explored through contrasting the views of four Indian schools of thought: the Buddhist, Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika, Bhaṭṭa Mīmāṃsāka, and Prābhākara Mīmāṃsā. Within the Islamic tradition, analogy is rejected as a valid tool for legal reasoning by the Ẓāhirī school, and this is contrasted with the very tempered defense by the Shāfiʿī school. The Islamic debates bring out more clearly the hermeneutical challenges, but it is argued that these challenges of interpretation are bound up in the challenges of the epistemology of relations and similarities. The work concludes that an epistemic virtue-theoretic account can help us better understand how analogical arguments can be true and non-vacuous, and argues we should cultivate the virtue of similarity and relation sensitivity. i. 2 TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract …......... i Table of Contents …......... ii Chapter One: The Importance and Scope of Analogy and the Relation of Similarity …......... 1 Chapter Two: The Metaphysical Basis of Analogy I: Relations as Universals or Tropes …......... 29 Chapter Three: The Metaphysical Basis of Analogy II: Theories of Relations …......... 87 Chapter Four: The Metaphysical Basis of Analogy III: Theories of Relations Continued …......... 107 Chapter Five: The Epistemology of Relations and Similarity: Knowing Relations, Knowing Analogies …......... 141 Chapter Six: The Epistemology of Relations and Similarity II: Seeing Analogies ......... 214 References …......... 228 ii 3 CHAPTER ONE: THE IMPORTANCE AND SCOPE OF ANALOGY AND THE RELATION OF SIMILARITY ANALOGY AS CENTRAL TO ALL PHILOSOPHICAL PURSUITS The problem of analogical reasoning is, simply put, the most fundamentally important problem in philosophy, and one that straddles the full range of philosophical areas of inquiry—metaphysics, epistemology, aesthetics, ethics, logic, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language, and it therefore finds itself implicated in every philosophical discussion. The full complexity of the problem is brought to the foreground when one acknowledges that analogical reasoning is simply that which depends on the relation and recognition of similarity. Once we realize that an explanation of analogical reasoning requires an explication of the relation of similarity and its recognition, we are forced to confront the fact that we must take such reasoning for granted in any attempt to explain it. One would be unable to recognize the words on these pages as words one knows if one does not have the epistemic ability to detect and cognize similarity; without similarity, we are rendered ineludibly mute. One could not speak of “types of things” since types depend on similarities holding between the particulars of that type. One could not speak of persistence over time since knowledge of persistence would depend on the ability to recognize relevant similarity through time. We would be left with a language of proper names (which is no language at all): without the ability to recognize similarity diachronically, it would be a language of ever changing names. In fact, the very ability to recognize what you are reading now is the same text as what you were reading moments before, and your ability to recognize these words as words you already know, depends on your ability to recognize a sameness, and what is sameness if not absolute similarity? Your ability to find this manuscript, after having set it down for a while, and resume reading from where you left off depends on an enormous number of operations, an edifice of recognition and reasoning built upon a foundational ability to 4 perceive, to be aware of, and to reason with similarity relations. Indeed, it is the very sophistication with which we as human beings can perform these actions that forms part of our uniqueness as a species of “rational animal.” To group organisms together in taxonomic structures, or to see ideas falling under a concept, to recognize something as the same type as another previously experienced thing, or to see some particular as belonging to a category all depend necessarily on similarity. All philosophizing needs concepts. There are no concepts without similarity. Therefore, without similarity, there can be no philosophizing. It further seems that similarity is a necessary feature of the universe. Given any two unique entities, they are similar in that they are both not some other third unique entity. Similarity, then, is a given, but an incredibly significant one. To claim that “x is like y” demands some specifiable similarity: a particular resemblance, something that they are similar in respect to. This claim differs from, say, literary analogies—similes —which Donald Davidson rightly points out are trivially true.1 So love is like a red, red rose sprung in June because something can be found in common between any two things (freshness, beauty, et cetera), but as Davidson and others before him have pointed out, some commonality can be found between any two things. Hence we have the adage, “Everything is like everything else” or as Stuart Hampshire has formulated it, echoing Charles Sanders Peirce, "it is . necessarily true that everything resembles everything in some respect. Of any two things whatever, there is some respect in which they can be said to resemble each other and not to resemble some third thing."2 Douglas Greenlee has argued that indeed that this is a necessary and significant truth, whereas Davidson sees it, at least through the lens of similes, as a trivial truth.3 Greenlee calls this the Similarity of Discernables principle. So love is like a red, red rose but also like a rotting corpse. This triviality and generality of the similarity relation has cast analogical reasoning in a shadow of doubt and distrust, evident in some of the earliest theoretical discussions of the concept up to contemporary considerations. Semiotician Umberto Eco 1 Donald Davidson, “What Metaphors Mean,” Critical Inquiry, 1978, 245–64. 2 Stuart Hampshire, Thought and Action, vol. 11 (University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), 31. 3 Douglas Greenlee, “The Similarity of Discernibles,” The Journal of Philosophy, 1968, 753–63. 5 has remarked on this suspicion, echoing sentiments we will see were earlier expressed by Plato, that “[the] criterion of similarity displayed an overindulgent generality and flexibility. Once the mechanism of analogy has been set in motion there is no guarantee that it will stop . The image, the concept, the truth that is discovered beneath the veil of similarity, will in its turn be seen as a sign of another analogical deferral. Every time one thinks to have discovered a similarity, it will point to another similarity, in an endless progress. In a universe dominated by the logic of similarity (and cosmic sympathy) the interpreter has the right and the duty to suspect that what one believed to be the meaning of a sign is in fact the sign for a further meaning.4 This triviality, transitivity and universality, though, violates the norms we use in assessing analogies. To illustrate what is meant, consider the old analogy tests from standardized exams: a fish is to a school like a tree is to a ______. There is a specific resemblance between the first set (fish, school) and the second set (tree, forest) which one must deduce in order to answer correctly. Another example avoids language altogether. Consider the set of images. To correctly answer this visual analogy, it too relies on recognizing the relevant similarities. Fig. 1. The visual analogy above is important, because as much as the present work will have to say about language and reasoning, it is important to bear in mind the often overlooked fact that mental activity is 4 Umberto Eco and Stefan Collini,
Recommended publications
  • A Companion to Analytic Philosophy
    A Companion to Analytic Philosophy Blackwell Companions to Philosophy This outstanding student reference series offers a comprehensive and authoritative survey of philosophy as a whole. Written by today’s leading philosophers, each volume provides lucid and engaging coverage of the key figures, terms, topics, and problems of the field. Taken together, the volumes provide the ideal basis for course use, represent- ing an unparalleled work of reference for students and specialists alike. Already published in the series 15. A Companion to Bioethics Edited by Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer 1. The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy Edited by Nicholas Bunnin and Eric 16. A Companion to the Philosophers Tsui-James Edited by Robert L. Arrington 2. A Companion to Ethics Edited by Peter Singer 17. A Companion to Business Ethics Edited by Robert E. Frederick 3. A Companion to Aesthetics Edited by David Cooper 18. A Companion to the Philosophy of 4. A Companion to Epistemology Science Edited by Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa Edited by W. H. Newton-Smith 5. A Companion to Contemporary Political 19. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy Philosophy Edited by Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit Edited by Dale Jamieson 6. A Companion to Philosophy of Mind 20. A Companion to Analytic Philosophy Edited by Samuel Guttenplan Edited by A. P. Martinich and David Sosa 7. A Companion to Metaphysics Edited by Jaegwon Kim and Ernest Sosa Forthcoming 8. A Companion to Philosophy of Law and A Companion to Genethics Legal Theory Edited by John Harris and Justine Burley Edited by Dennis Patterson 9. A Companion to Philosophy of Religion A Companion to African-American Edited by Philip L.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics. by Peter Van Inwagen Review By: Timothy O'connor the Philosophical Review, Vol
    Philosophical Review Metaphysics. by Peter van Inwagen Review by: Timothy O'Connor The Philosophical Review, Vol. 104, No. 2 (Apr., 1995), pp. 314-317 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical Review Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2185999 . Accessed: 25/06/2014 03:49 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 185.44.77.146 on Wed, 25 Jun 2014 03:49:57 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions BOOK REVIEWS such issues as the completeness of quantum mechanics and whetherit is a local theory.Part of the problem has been in figuringout what is meant by 'completeness' and 'locality'.A lot of hard work has also been done in designing and performingexperiments to test quantum mechanics and compare it to rival theories. Shimony has made importantcontributions to all aspects of this endeavor-for example, his proof that quantum mechanical nonlocality,what he refersto as passion-at-a-distance,cannot be exploited for the purposes of sending signals at velocitiesgreater than the velocityof light (2:134-36).
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 351 Nominalism
    Philosophy 351 September 9, 2008 Prof. Clare Batty Universals: Nominalism 1. Recap Metaphysical realism: the world contains both universals and particulars. Certain things (particulars) are alike in attribute (property, relation, kind) because they exemplify the same universal. Metaphysical realists claim that their two-category framework not only provides us with the machinery with which to explain attribute agreement/similarity/resemblance but also a pair of important phenomena: i. The truth of subject-predicate discourse ii. Our use of abstract reference. 2. Issues we have raised about metaphysical realism a. What universals is the metaphysical realist willing to allow into his/her ontology? • Does he/she allow the universal bachelor or just unmarried, adult, male (does he/she even allow unmarried?). What about he universal green or just green (or light green)? 52 b. Are there unexemplified universals? • Certainly there might have been different properties in the world. Are there universals corresponding to these non-existent, but possible, properties? c. Is the relation of exemplification itself a universal? If so, doesn’t this commit the metaphysical realist to an infinite regress? • Suppose a and b are both F. That is, they exemplify the universal F-ness. But now they have an additional thing in common: they are both exemplifications of F-ness. That is, they both exemplify the universal exemplification of F-ness. Can you see where this is going? d. Doesn’t the metaphysical realist overestimate the degree of agreement/likeness/resemblance in the world? • Grass, peas and wasabi paste are all similar; but they are not exactly alike. 3.
    [Show full text]
  • " CONTENTS of VOLUME XXXVIII—1964 >•
    " CONTENTS OF VOLUME XXXVIII—1964 >• it ARTICLES: pAGE Anderson, James F., Was St. Thomas a Philosopher? 435 Boh, Ivan, An Examination of Some Proofs in Burleigh's Propo- sitional Logic 44 Brady, Jules M., St. Augustine's Theory of Seminal Reasons.. 141 Burns, J. Patout, Action in Suarez 453 Burrell, David B., Kant and Philosophical Knowledge 189 Chroust, Anton-Hermann, Some Reflections on the Origin of the Term " Philosopher " 423 Collins, James, The Work of Rudolf Allers 28 Fairbanks, Matthew J., C. S. Peirce and Logical Atomism 178 Grisez, Germain G., Sketch of a Future Metaphysics 310 O'Brien, Andrew J., Duns Scotus' Teaching on the Distinction between Essence and Existence 61 McWilliams, James A., The Concept as Villain 445 Pax, Clyde V., Philosophical Reflection: Gabriel Marcel 159 Smith, John E., The Relation of Thought and Being: Some Lessons from Hegel's Encyclopedia 22 Stokes, Walter E., Whitehead's Challenge to Theistic Realism. ... 1 Tallon, Andrew, Personal Immortality in Averroes' Tahafut Al- Tahafut 341 REVIEW ARTICLE : O'Neil, Charles J., Another Notable Study of Aristotle's Meta­ physics 509 ill iv Contents of Volume XXXVIII DEPARTMENTS : PAGE Book Brevities 551 Books Received 133, 274, 415, 557 Chronicles: The Husserl Archives and the Edition of Husserl's Works 473 International Congresses of Philosophy in Mexico City.. 278 Progress Report: Philosophy in the NCE 214 The Secretary's Chronicle 80, 218, 358, 483 BOOK REVIEWS: Anderson, James P., Natural Theology: The Metaphysics of God 265 Austin, J. L., Philosophical Papers 125 Capek, Milec, The Philosophical Impact of Contemporary Physics 248 Caturelli, Alberto, La fdosofiu en Argentina actual 403 Crocker, Lester G., Nature and Cidture: Ethical Thought in the French Englightement 539 Dufrenne, Mikel, Language and Philosophy, transl.
    [Show full text]
  • Department of Philosophy the University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-4619 Russell's China Teapot Peter Van Inwagen
    Department of Philosophy The University of Notre Dame Notre Dame, Indiana 46556-4619 [email protected] Russell’s China Teapot Peter van Inwagen St Thomas Aquinas has presented five well-known arguments for the existence of God, but he has also presented—although not, of course, endorsed—two arguments that might be described as “arguments to the contrary” or as “objections to belief in God.” Summa Theologiae, I, q.2, a.3 (the “Five Ways” article, the article whose topic is indicated by the heading “Whether God exists”) opens with those two arguments. The first, Objection 1, is a version of the argument from evil—the argument that since the existence of evil is incompatible with the existence of God, God does not exist. The second Objection is as follows: Objection 2. It is, moreover, superfluous to suppose that what can be accounted for by a few principles has been produced by many. But it seems that everything we see in the world can be accounted for by other principles, without supposing God to exist. For all natural things can be accounted for by one principle, which is nature; and all voluntary things can be accounted for by one principle, which is human reason or will. Hence, there is no need to suppose that God exists. Here is a formulation of the essential point of this argument in language the modern mind may find more congenial than Thomas’s talk of “principles”: 2 The only reason we could have for believing in God would be that it was necessary to postulate his existence to account for some observed fact or facts.
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2012 The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Joseph Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Joseph, "The idea of mimesis: Semblance, play, and critique in the works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno" (2012). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 125. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/125 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play, and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno A Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy October, 2011 By Joseph Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Sciences DePaul University Chicago, Illinois 2 ABSTRACT Joseph Weiss Title: The Idea of Mimesis: Semblance, Play and Critique in the Works of Walter Benjamin and Theodor W. Adorno Critical Theory demands that its forms of critique express resistance to the socially necessary illusions of a given historical period. Yet theorists have seldom discussed just how much it is the case that, for Walter Benjamin and Theodor W.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal for Philosophy of Religion
    EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION VOLUME 4 NUMBER 4 WINTER 2012 ARTICLES David S. ODERBERG Survivalism, Corruptionism, and Mereology 1 Dale JACQUETTE Anselm’s Metaphysics of Nonbeing 27 Erik J. WIELENBERG An Inconsistency in Craig’s Defence of the Moral Argument 49 Andrei A. BUCKAREFF Omniscience, the Incarnation, and Knowledge de se 59 T. Ryan BYERLY Infallible Divine Foreknowledge Cannot Uniquely Threaten Human Freedom, But Its Mechanics Might 73 T. J. MAWSON On Determining How Important It Is Whether or Not There Is a God 95 Jerome GELLMAN A Theistic, Universe-Based, Theodicy of Human Suffering and Immoral Behaviour 107 Anders KRAAL Hedenius’ Soteriological Argument from Evil 123 Peter JONKERS Redefining Religious Truth as a Challenge for Philosophy of Religion 139 Louis CARUANA Science, Religion and Common Sense 161 DISCUSSIONS AND REPLIES John BISHOP In Quest of Authentic Divinity: Critical Notice of Mark Johnston’s ‘Saving God: Religion after Idolatry’ 175 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES Timothy O’Connor. Theism and Ultimate Explanation: The Necessary Shape of Contingency Reviewed by Sho Yamaguchi 193 Georg Gasser (ed.). Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? Reviewed by Joshua Farris 196 Timothy Yoder. Hume on God: Irony, Deism and Genuine Theism Reviewed by Dan O’Brien 201 Earl Stanley B. Fronda. Wittgenstein’s (Misunderstood) Religious Thought Reviewed by Klaus von Stosch 206 Neil Spurway (ed.). Theology, Evolution and the Mind Reviewed by Aku Visala 208 SURVIVALISM, CORRUPTIONISM, AND MEREOLOGY DAVID S. ODERBERG University of Reading Abstract. Corruptionism is the view that following physical death, the human being ceases to exist (until Resurrection) but their soul persists in the afterlife.
    [Show full text]
  • Blumer's Symbolic Interactionism: Methodological Implications
    University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Electronic Theses and Dissertations Theses, Dissertations, and Major Papers 1-1-1971 Blumer's symbolic interactionism: Methodological implications. Jan Spurway Marks University of Windsor Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/etd Recommended Citation Marks, Jan Spurway, "Blumer's symbolic interactionism: Methodological implications." (1971). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. 6691. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/etd/6691 This online database contains the full-text of PhD dissertations and Masters’ theses of University of Windsor students from 1954 forward. These documents are made available for personal study and research purposes only, in accordance with the Canadian Copyright Act and the Creative Commons license—CC BY-NC-ND (Attribution, Non-Commercial, No Derivative Works). Under this license, works must always be attributed to the copyright holder (original author), cannot be used for any commercial purposes, and may not be altered. Any other use would require the permission of the copyright holder. Students may inquire about withdrawing their dissertation and/or thesis from this database. For additional inquiries, please contact the repository administrator via email ([email protected]) or by telephone at 519-253-3000ext. 3208. - BLUMER'S SYMBOLIC INTERACTIONISM: METHODOLOGICAL IMPLICATIONS A THESIS 'SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES THROUGH THE DEPARTMENT OF SOCIOLOGY AND ANTHROPOLOGY IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS AT THE UNIVERSITY OF WINDSOR JAN SPURWAY MARKS UNIVERSITY OF WINDSOR 1971 Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. UMI Number: EC53094 INFORMATION TO USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relevance of Carnap's Inductive Logic for Supervised Classification
    University Utrecht Artificial Intelligence Master’s Thesis The Relevance of Carnap’s Inductive Logic for Supervised Classification Supervisor: Author: Dr. Janneke van Lith Wessel de Jong Dr. Sander Beckers March 19, 2019 Department of Theoretical Philosophy University Utrecht Abstract Recent advances in the field of machine learning have cast new light on the long-standing debate within the philosophy of science between falsificationists and inductivists. As a result of many failed attempts at justifying inductive in- ference, falsificationism has tended to be preferred over inductivism. However, Gillies claims that the success of certain machine learning procedures neces- sarily leads to the conclusion that inductivism has shown to be successful [19]. In this thesis I will challenge this claim by examining how criticism voiced against the inductive logic of one of the central figures of the inductivism, Rudolf Carnap, might still be relevant for modern day machine learning pro- cedures. Since a general claim about all machine learning procedures would be prone to counterexamples this thesis will be limited to only linear models for supervised classification. I will consider how three well-known critiques that strongly undermined Carnap’s inductive methods might still apply to such classification models. Department of Theoretical Philosophy University Utrecht Contents 1 Introduction3 2 Machine Learning7 2.1 Supervised Classification.........................7 2.2 Data Representation...........................9 2.3 Training.................................. 11 2.4 Testing................................... 15 3 Carnap’s Inductive Logic 18 3.1 Early Carnap............................... 19 3.2 Late Carnap................................ 22 3.2.1 Confirmation Functions..................... 23 3.2.2 Attribute Spaces......................... 24 3.2.3 Similarity Influence.......................
    [Show full text]
  • Streetfood Und Stadtkultur – Hawker in Telok Bahang/Malaysia
    Asiatische Studien Études Asiatiques LXVI · 2 · 2012 Zeitschrift der Schweizerischen Asiengesellschaft Revue de la Société Suisse – Asie Edited by Roland Altenburger and Robert H. Gassmann Peter Lang Bern · Berlin · Bruxelles · Frankfurt am Main · New York · Oxford · Wien ISSN 0004-4717 © Peter Lang AG, Internationaler Verlag der Wissenschaften, Bern 2012 Hochfeldstrasse 32, CH-3012 Bern, Schweiz [email protected], www.peterlang.com Alle Rechte vorbehalten. Das Werk einschließlich aller seiner Teile ist urheberrechtlich geschützt. Jede Verwertung außerhalb der engen Grenzen des Urheberrechtsgesetzes ist ohne Zustimmung des Verlages unzulässig und strafbar. Das gilt insbesondere für Vervielfältigungen, Übersetzungen, Mikroverfilmungen und die Einspeicherung und Verarbeitung in elektronischen Systemen. Printed in Hungary INHALTSVERZEICHNIS – TABLE DES MATIÈRES CONTENTS Aufsätze – Articles – Articles JOHANNES BRONKHORST ............................................................................................................... 227 Levels of Cognition: Did Indian philosophers know something we do not? NADIA CATTONI .................................................................................................................................. 239 Le commentaire littéraire: entre classification et interprétation. Exemples issus de la Śṛṅgāradīpikā et de la Bhāvadīpikā de Vemabhūpāla BOGDAN DIACONESCU .................................................................................................................... 261 On the New Ways
    [Show full text]
  • Following the Argument Where It Leads
    Following The Argument Where It Leads Thomas Kelly Princeton University [email protected] Abstract: Throughout the history of western philosophy, the Socratic injunction to ‘follow the argument where it leads’ has exerted a powerful attraction. But what is it, exactly, to follow the argument where it leads? I explore this intellectual ideal and offer a modest proposal as to how we should understand it. On my proposal, following the argument where it leaves involves a kind of modalized reasonableness. I then consider the relationship between the ideal and common sense or 'Moorean' responses to revisionary philosophical theorizing. 1. Introduction Bertrand Russell devoted the thirteenth chapter of his History of Western Philosophy to the thought of St. Thomas Aquinas. He concluded his discussion with a rather unflattering assessment: There is little of the true philosophic spirit in Aquinas. He does not, like the Platonic Socrates, set out to follow wherever the argument may lead. He is not engaged in an inquiry, the result of which it is impossible to know in advance. Before he begins to philosophize, he already knows the truth; it is declared in the Catholic faith. If he can find apparently rational arguments for some parts of the faith, so much the better: If he cannot, he need only fall back on revelation. The finding of arguments for a conclusion given in advance is not philosophy, but special pleading. I cannot, therefore, feel that he deserves to be put on a level with the best philosophers either of Greece or of modern times (1945: 463). The extent to which this is a fair assessment of Aquinas is controversial.1 My purpose in what follows, however, is not to defend Aquinas; nor is it to substantiate the charges that Russell brings against him.
    [Show full text]
  • Contents Tempor Libero Condimentum Eu
    Campion News, Trinity Term 2014 page 1 Campion News The Newsletter of Campion Hall, Oxford University Number 1, Trinity Term 2014 From the Master The West Wing (1956) he point of this regular column T is to enable the Master each term to draw the attention of the readers of the newsletter to some event or matter which he considers important. It could either look backwards or around, or forwards, but it should have sufficient words—and no more—to fill the column on the left hand of the first page, like this. Several questions need to be settled; e.g., what size font should be used—and, for that matter, what font would be best. Also, whether the article should be signed, which would take-up a couple of lines. Aenean vitae lorem dui. Morbi tem- pus lacinia nisi, vel scelerisque nibh facilisis id. Integer urna tortor, ul- lamcorper aliquet viverra non, mollis sed dolor. Phasellus sagittis tempus massa, a Contents tempor libero condimentum eu. Mor- 1 From the Master bi ut nisi ante. Duis purus eros, ali- quam eu cursus tincidunt, feugiat The West Wing (illustration) vitae magna. Etiam sodales conse- quat nibh, eget rhoncus metus 2 New publications A fresh look at the Bible James Hanvey SJ Making history 3 Who’s Who at the Hall 7 A fond farewell 8 The Origins of Campion Hall 9 Conferences 10 Gerry (God of Surprises) Hughes at 90 11 Campion Treasures 1: The Bellarmine Jug 12 Supporting Campion Hall In pensive mood Campion News Trinity 2014 Campion News, Trinity Term 2014 page 2 New Publications A fresh look at the Bible Making History Once, when God and the Devil were having one of Professor Jack Mahoney was approached a couple their endless arguments, God finally said in exas- of years ago by the publishers of the best-selling peration, “I shall write a book”.
    [Show full text]