Deconstructing Equality-Versus-Difference: Or, the Uses of Poststructuralist Theory for Feminism Author(S): Joan W

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Deconstructing Equality-Versus-Difference: Or, the Uses of Poststructuralist Theory for Feminism Author(S): Joan W Deconstructing Equality-versus-Difference: Or, the Uses of Poststructuralist Theory for Feminism Author(s): Joan W. Scott Source: Feminist Studies, Vol. 14, No. 1 (Spring, 1988), pp. 32-50 Published by: Feminist Studies, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3177997 . Accessed: 02/08/2011 15:25 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=femstudies. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Feminist Studies, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Feminist Studies. http://www.jstor.org DECONSTRUCTING EQUALITY-VERSUS- DIFFERENCE: OR, THE USES OF POSTSTRUCTURALISTTHEORY FOR FEMINISM JOAN W. SCOTT Thatfeminism needs theory goes without saying(perhaps because it has been said so often). What is not always clear is what that theory will do, althoughthere are certaincommon assumptionsI think we can find in a wide range of feminist writings. We need theory that can analyze the workings of patriarchyin all its manifestations- ideological, institutional, organizational,subjec- tive - accountingnot only for continuitiesbut also for changeover time. We need theory that will let us think in terms of pluralities and diversities rather than of unities and universals. We need theory that will break the conceptualhold, at least, of those long traditionsof (Western)philosophy that have systematicallyand repeatedly construed the world hierarchically in terms of masculine universalsand feminine specificities.We need theory that will enable us to articulatealternative ways of thinkingabout (andthus actingupon) genderwithout either simply reversingthe old hierarchiesor confirmingthem. And we need theory that will be useful and relevantfor politicalpractice. It seems to me that the body of theory referredto as poststruc- turalismbest meets all these requirements.It is not by any means the only theory nor are its positions and formulationsunique. In my own case, however, it was readingpoststructuralist theory and arguing with literary scholars that provided the elements of clarificationfor which I was looking.I found a new way of analyz- ing constructions of meaning and relationshipsof power that called unitary,universal categories into question and historicized Feminist Studies 14, no. 1 (Spring 1988). ? 1988 by Feminist Studies, Inc. 33 qn., A.4_ br /' Am -.Op AJ IN lop* Ewa Kuryluk, Face, 1981, from the Installation, Fall in Princeton, 1984. Kuryluk modulates the gestures and facial expressions depicted on her canvases by the way she chooses to drape them on any given occasion. This is an alternative in- stallation of the same drawing on page 10. 34 Joan W. Scott conceptsotherwise treated as natural(such as man/woman)or ab- solute (such as equalityor justice). In addition,what attractedme was the historicalconnection between the two movements. Post- structuralism and contemporary feminism are late-twentieth- centurymovements that sharea certainself-conscious critical rela- tionship to established philosophicaland political traditions. It thus seemed worthwhilefor feminist scholarsto exploitthat rela- tionship for their own ends.' This articlewill not discussthe historyof these various"exploita- tions"or elaborateon all the reasonsa historianmight look to this theoryto organizeher inquiry.2What seems most useful here is to give a short list of some majortheoretical points and then devote most of my effortto a specificillustration. The firstpart of this arti- cle is a brief discussionof conceptsused by poststructuraliststhat are also useful for feminists.The second partapplies some of these conceptsto one of the hotly contestedissues amongcontemporary (U.S.)feminists- the "equality-versus-difference"debate. Among the useful terms feminists have appropriatedfrom post- structuralismare language,discourse, difference, and deconstruc- tion. Language.Following the work of structuralistlinguistics and an- thropology,the term is used to mean not simply words or even a vocabularyand set of grammaticalrules but, rather,a meaning- constitutingsystem: that is, any system- strictlyverbal or other- through which meaning is constructed and cultural practices organizedand by which, accordingly,people representand under- stand their world, includingwho they are and how they relateto others. "Language,"so conceived, is a central focus of poststruc- turalistanalysis. Languageis not assumed to be a representationof ideas that either cause material relations or from which such relations follow; indeed, the idealist/materialistopposition is a false one to impose on this approach.Rather, the analysisof languageprovides a crucial point of entry, a startingpoint for understandinghow social relations are conceived, and therefore-because under- standinghow they are conceived means understandinghow they work- how institutionsare organized,how relationsof production are experienced, and how collective identity is established. Joan W. Scott 35 Withoutattention to languageand the processesby which mean- ings and categories are constituted, one only imposes over- simplified models on the world, models that perpetuateconven- tional understandings rather than open up new interpretive possibilities. The point is to find ways to analyze specific "texts"-notonly books and documentsbut also utterancesof any kind and in any medium, includingcultural practices-in terms of specific histori- cal and contextualmeanings. Poststructuralistsinsist that words and texts have no fixed or intrinsic meanings, that there is no transparentor self-evidentrelationship between them and either ideas or things, no basic or ultimate correspondencebetween languageand the world. The questionsthat must be answeredin such an analysis,then, are how, in what specific contexts,among which specific communitiesof people, and by what textual and social processes has meaning been acquired?More generally,the questions are: How do meaningschange? How have some mean- ings emergedas normativeand othershave been eclipsedor disap- peared?What do these processes reveal about how power is con- stituted and operates? Discourse.Some of the answers to these questionsare offeredin the concept of discourse,especially as it has been developedin the work of Michel Foucault.A discourse is not a languageor a text but a historically,socially, and institutionallyspecific structureof statements,terms, categories,and beliefs. Foucaultsuggests that the elaboration of meaning involves conflict and power, that meanings are locally contested within discursive"fields of force," that (at least since the Enlightenment)the power to controla par- ticular field resides in claims to (scientific)knowledge embodied not only in writing but also in disciplinary and professional organizations,in institutions(hospitals, prisons, schools, factories), and in social relationships (doctor/patient, teacher/student, employer/worker,parent/child, husband/wife). Discourse is thus containedor expressedin organizationsand institutionsas well as in words; all of these constitutetexts or documents to be read.3 Discursive fields overlap, influence, and compete with one another;they appeal to one another's"truths" for authorityand legitimation.These truthsare assumedto be outsidehuman inven- tion, either already known and self-evident or discoverable through scientific inquiry. Precisely because they are assigned the 36 JoanW. Scott statusof objectiveknowledge, they seem to be beyond disputeand thus serve a powerfullegitimating function. Darwinian theories of naturalselection are one exampleof such legitimatingtruths; bio- logicaltheories about sexual differenceare another.The power of these "truths"comes from the way they functionas givens or first premises for both sides in an argument,so that conflicts within discursive fields are framed to follow from ratherthan question them. The brillianceof so much of Foucault'swork has been to il- luminate the shared assumptionsof what seemed to be sharply differentarguments, thus exposingthe limits of radicalcriticism and the extent of the power of dominant ideologies or epistemologies. In addition,Foucault has shown how badly even challengesto fundamentalassumptions often fared. They have been marginal- ized or silenced, forced to underplaytheir most radicalclaims in order to win a short-termgoal, or completely absorbedinto an existingframework. Yet the fact of change is crucialto Foucault's notion of "archaeology,"to the way in which he uses contrasts from differenthistorical periods to presenthis arguments.Exactly how the process happens is not spelled out to the satisfactionof
Recommended publications
  • Phenomenology As Philosophy and Method Applications to Ways of Doing Special Education
    Phenomenology As Philosophy and Method Applications to Ways of Doing Special Education JEAN C. McPHAIL ABSTRACT 1 HENOMENOLOGY IS A PHILOSOPHICAL MOVEMENT The theoretical positions of the preceding two texts THAT APPROACHES THE STUDY OF HUMAN BEINGS AND THEIR create significantly different orientations to the life worlds CULTURE DIFFERENTLY FROM THE LOGICAL POSITIVIST MODEL of people. The quote by Merleau-Ponty describes the USED IN THE NATURAL SCIENCES AND IN SPECIAL EDUCA- essential focus of the phenomenological movement in TION. PHENOMENOLOGISTS VIEW THE APPLICATION OF THE philosophy—human consciousness. The Individualized Edu- LOGICAL POSITIVIST MODEL TO THE STUDY OF HUMAN BEINGS cation Program written for a 13-year-old young man with AS INAPPROPRIATE BECAUSE THE MODEL DOES NOT ADDRESS learning disabilities characterizes the prevalent view of THE UNIQUENESS OF HUMAN LIFE. IN THIS ARTICLE, THE individuals working in the field of special education—an THEORETICAL ASSUMPTIONS AND METHODOLOGICAL orientation directed toward changing the behavior of indi- ORIENTATIONS OF PHENOMENOLOGY ARE DISCUSSED, viduals with disabilities. Whereas phenomenology privi- FOLLOWED BY THEIR APPLICATIONS TO WAYS OF DOING leges the nature of the meanings that people construct in RESEARCH IN SPECIAL EDUCATION. their lives and that guide their actions, special education focuses on the study and practice of behavioral change outside the context of the life meanings of individuals with disabilities. The shift that Bruner (1990) described in the early stages of the cognitive revolution from an emphasis on the "construction of meaning to the processing of mean- P. HENOMENOLOGY IS AN INVENTORY OF CON- ing" (p. 4) aptly characterizes the essential differences JLsciousness HEN( as of that wherein a universe resides.
    [Show full text]
  • The Transition from Studying Philosophy to Doing Philosophy
    Teaching Philosophy 34:3, September 2011 241 The Transition from Studying Philosophy to Doing Philosophy JOHN RUDISILL The College of Wooster Abstract: In this paper I articulate a minimal conception of the idea of doing philosophy that informs a curriculum and pedagogy for producing students who are capable of engaging in philosophical activity and not just competent with a specific domain of knowledge. The paper then relates, by way of back- ground, the departmental assessment practices that have played a vital role in the development of my department’s current curriculum and in particular in the design of a junior-year seminar in philosophical research required of all majors. After a brief survey of the learning theory literature that has informed its design, I share the content of this junior-year seminar. In the paper’s conclusion I provide some initial data that indicates our approach to curriculum and pedagogy has had a positive impact on student achievement with respect to reaching the learning goals associated with “doing” as opposed to “merely studying” philosophy. 1. Introduction Capstone projects are common among liberal arts colleges and fre- quently carry an expectation that the final product demonstrates the student’s achievement of becoming a budding biologist, historian, sociologist, philosopher and so on. Even without a formal capstone requirement, I would hope that my philosophy students could—as they finish their undergraduate studies—demonstrate such an achievement. This is because the full set of benefits made available by an education in philosophy includes but extends well beyond knowledge of the history of philosophy and mastery of a philosophical lexicon.
    [Show full text]
  • 210 the Genesis of Neo-Kantianism
    SYNTHESIS PHILOSOPHICA Book Reviews / Buchbesprechungen 61 (1/2016) pp. (207–220) 210 doi: 10.21464/sp31116 of his book is that the movement’s origins are to be found already in the 1790s, in the Frederick Charles Beiser works of Jakob Friedrich Fries, Johann Frie- drich Herbart, and Friedrich Eduard Beneke. They constitute “the lost tradition” which pre- The Genesis of served the “empiricist-psychological” side of Neo-Kantianism Kant’s thought, his dualisms, and things-in- themselves against the excessive speculative idealism of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel who Oxford University Press, tried to rehabilitate the dogmatic rationalist Oxford 2014 metaphysics of Spinoza, Leibniz, and Wolff after Kant’s critical project. Frederick Charles Beiser, professor of phi- The first chapter of the first part (pp. 23–88) losophy at Syracuse University (USA) whose is concerned with the philosophy of Fries field of expertise is the modern German phi- who tried to base philosophy on empirical losophy, is one of the most erudite historians psychology, and epistemology on psychol- of philosophy today. His first book The Fate ogy which could recognize the synthetic a of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant priori but not prove it. His book Reinhold, to Fichte (1987) didn’t only present a fresh Fichte und Schelling (1803) saw the history account of German philosophy at the end of of philosophy after Kant as the “struggle of th the 18 century, but it also introduced a new rationalism to free itself from the limits of method of historical research. His more re- the critique”. In his political philosophy Fries cent works, starting with The German His- was an anti-Semite, but gave the leading role toricist Tradition (2011) until the most recent to public opinion which could correct even Weltschmerz: Pessimism in German Philoso- the ruler, although he encountered problems phy, 1860–1900 (2016), have focused on the in trying to reconcile his liberal views with th main currents of the 19 century German the social injustice that liberalism created.
    [Show full text]
  • Atheistic and Christian Existentialism: a Comparison of Sartre and Marcel Thomas C
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 8-1-2010 Atheistic and Christian Existentialism: A Comparison of Sartre and Marcel Thomas C. Anderson Marquette University, [email protected] Accepted version. "Atheistic and Christian Existentialism: A Comparison of Sartre and Marcel," in New Perspectives in Sartre. Eds. Adrian Mirvish and Adrian van den Hoven. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2010: 44-63. Publisher link, © 2010 Cambridge Scholars Publishing. Used with permission. NOT THE PUBLISHED VERSION; this is the author’s final, peer-reviewed manuscript. The published version may be accessed by following the link in the citation at the bottom of the page. Atheistic and Christian Existentialism: A Comparison of Sartre and Marcel Thomas C. Anderson Department of Philosophy, Marquette University Milwaukee, WI In Existentialism and Humanism Jean-Paul Sartre states that there are “two kinds of existentialists,” the atheistic, in which he includes himself, and the Christian, among whom he includes his fellow countryman Gabriel Marcel.1 Needless to say, these two existentialists significantly disagree on many things and yet, surprisingly, they also have notable areas of agreement, as we shall see. The purpose of this paper is to compare the views of the two men on a number of important philosophical issues. My comparison is aided by the fact that Sartre and Marcel knew each other personally and occasionally directly commented in writing on each other’s ideas. First, some information about their history and personal relationship. Both men were born, Marcel in 1889, Sartre in 1905, and for the most part lived and wrote in Paris.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 7-1-2018 Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology (07/18). DOI. © 2018 Oxford University Press. Used with permission. Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Kant, Neo-Kantianism, and Phenomenology Sebastian Luft The Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology Edited by Dan Zahavi Print Publication Date: Jun 2018 Subject: Philosophy, Philosophy of Mind, History of Western Philosophy (Post-Classical) Online Publication Date: Jul 2018 DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198755340.013.5 Abstract and Keywords This chapter offers a reassessment of the relationship between Kant, the Kantian tradi­ tion, and phenomenology, here focusing mainly on Husserl and Heidegger. Part of this re­ assessment concerns those philosophers who, during the lives of Husserl and Heidegger, sought to defend an updated version of Kant’s philosophy, the neo-Kantians. The chapter shows where the phenomenologists were able to benefit from some of the insights on the part of Kant and the neo-Kantians, but also clearly points to the differences. The aim of this chapter is to offer a fair evaluation of the relation of the main phenomenologists to Kant and to what was at the time the most powerful philosophical movement in Europe. Keywords: Immanuel Kant, neo-Kantianism, Edmund Husserl, Martin Heidegger, Marburg School of neo-Kantian­ ism 3.1 Introduction THE relation between phenomenology, Kant, and Kantian philosophizing broadly con­ strued (historically and systematically), has been a mainstay in phenomenological re­ search.1 This mutual testing of both philosophies is hardly surprising given phenomenology’s promise to provide a wholly novel type of philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Marburg Neo-Kantianism As Philosophy of Culture
    SamanthaMatherne (Santa Cruz) Marburg Neo-Kantianism as Philosophy of Culture 1Introduction Although Ernst Cassirer is correctlyregarded as one of the foremost figures in the Neo-Kantian movement thatdominated Germanyfrom 1870 – 1920,specifying ex- actlywhat his Neo-Kantianism amountstocan be achallenge. Not onlymustwe clarify what his commitments are as amember of the so-called MarburgSchool of Neo-Kantianism, but also giventhe shift between his earlyphilosophyof mathematics and naturalscience to his later philosophyofculture, we must con- sider to what extent he remained aMarburgNeo-Kantian throughout his career. With regard to the first task, it is typical to approach the MarburgSchool, which was foundedbyHermann Cohen and Paul Natorp, by wayofacontrast with the otherdominant school of Neo-Kantianism, the Southwest or Baden School, founded by Wilhelm Windelband and carried forward by Heinrich Rick- ert and Emil Lask. The going assumption is that these two schools were ‘rivals’ in the sense that the MarburgSchool focused exclusively on developing aKantian approach to mathematical natural sciences(Naturwissenschaften), while the Southwest School privileged issues relatingtonormativity and value, hence their primary focus on the humanities (Geisteswissenschaften). If one accepts this ‘scientist’ interpretation of the MarburgSchool, one is tempted to read Cas- sirer’searlywork on mathematicsand natural science as orthodoxMarburgNeo- Kantianism and to then regardhis laterwork on the philosophyofculture as a break from his predecessors, veeringcloser
    [Show full text]
  • Exe-Xi-Sis on Making China Great Again Xi Jinping's 19Th Party
    Exe‐Xi‐sis on Making China Great Again Xi Jinping’s 19th Party Congress Report Stephen B. Herschler Oglethorpe University January 2018 Just after the 19th Party Congress in October, a second volume of Xi Jinping’s Thoughts was published, I quickly moved to order my own copy through Amazon. Weeks later, still no anticipated delivery date. If I am to believe the website Stalin’s Moustache, that’s because Chinese citizens are voraciously buying up books by and about Xi Jinping Thought. The recent 19th Party Congress may well require revising many previous publications. At the Congress, Xi Jinping followed Communist Party of China (CPC) tradition in presenting a Report – 报告 baogao ‐ to the 2,200‐odd delegates assembled and to the nearly 1.4 billion Chinese citizens more generally. One thing that broke with tradition was the sheer length of his speech: 3 ½ hours. The length results in part from the CPC’s comprehensive governance – implicating all facets of Chinese society. That’s lots of ground for a speech – and the Party – to cover. Xi clearly felt comfortable claiming the verbal space, using it to map out a path to Make China – as State and Nation – Great Again. Western press reports have picked up on the event as Xi’s fast‐track enshrinement among the pantheon of Great Chinese Communist leaders. Xi’s trademark ideology – Xi Jinping Thought on Socialism with Chinese Special Characteristics – championed in the Report, has already been ensconced in the Chinese Constitution. This is notable as his predecessors, Jiang and Hu, were inscribed only toward the end of their ten‐year tenures, not mid‐term.
    [Show full text]
  • Gadamer and the Hermeneutics of Difference
    Self and Other: Gadamer and the Hermeneutics of Difference Fred Dalmayr Philosophy's relation to the world of lived experience (the life-world) is complex and controverted. In traditional vocabulary, the issue is whether philosophy's habitat resides inside or outside the Platonic cave. The issue has not come to rest in our time. While "analytic" philoso- phers prefer to externalize or distance their targets of analysis, Continen- tal thinkers (at least since Heidegger) refuse the comforts of this spectatorial stance. Like sensitive seismographs, European thinkers reg- ister the subterranean tremors which in our time affect the (once solid) underpinnings of Western culture: the pillars of subjectivity, of the cogito, and of rationality seen as a means of mastery over nature. What emerges from these seismographic soundings is an experience of disloca- tion or ontological decentering, blurring the boundaries between subject and object, between self and other, and between humans and nature (the former res extensa). As it happens, this experiential tremor is accompa- nied in our time by a broader geopolitical dislocation: the displacement of Europe from center stage and her insertion into a global welter of competing cultures and countercultures. To be sure, Europe (and the West in general) still forcefully asserts its hegemony; but the self-assur- ance of this hegemonic position has been irremediably lost or at least placed in jeopardy. The present pages seek to explore this double move of dislocation by attending to one particularly prominent and reliable seismograph: the work of Hans-Georg Gadamer. Born in 1900, Gadamer has been an astute participant and reflective witness (not just a spectator) throughout the entire course of our troubled century.
    [Show full text]
  • The “Ontological Difference” Again. a Dialetheic Perspective on Heidegger's Mainstay
    Open Philosophy 2018; 1: 143–154 Francesco Gandellini* The “Ontological Difference” Again. A Dialetheic Perspective on Heidegger’s Mainstay https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2018-0011 Received June 9, 2018; accepted August 16, 2018 Abstract: This paper intends to offer a new assessment of the “Ontological Difference” (OD), one of Martin Heidegger’s mainstays, in the light of the metaphysical view called “dialetheism”. In the first paragraph I briefly summarize the main argument of Heidegger’s contradiction of Being, where OD is present as a premise. In the second paragraph I introduce dialetheism, indicate two kinds of dialetheic solutions to the paradox and explain why they face comeback troubles from OD. The third paragraph is devoted to a review of Heidegger’s uses of OD and underlines the crucial role of negation in it. In the fourth paragraph I investigate the philosopher’s account of negation and show similarities with the account provided by the paraconsistent logic called “Logic of Paradox”. The fifth paragraph puts forward two possible readings of OD, the first based on the classical notion of negation and the second on the notion of negation pointed out in the previous paragraph. The second reading is proved suitable for dialetheists and in accordance with the exegesis of some textual passages from Heidegger’s late works. Keywords: Martin Heidegger, ontological difference, dialetheism, Logic of Paradox 1 Introduction Analytic philosophy’s adjudication to set aside old hates and resentments and to establish contact with Martin Heidegger’s philosophy is quite a recent phenomenon in the philosophical literature1. Casati and Wheeler2 have shown examples of this productive engagement in the fields of metaphysics and philosophy of mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Phenomenology and Ontology.Pdf
    PHENOMENOLOGY AND ONTOLOGY John J. Drummond Fordham University Ontologie ist nur als Phänomenologie möglich. —Martin Heidegger ([1927] 1967, 35) David Woodruff Smith’s Husserl (2007)1 sculpts Husserl, along with Aristotle and Kant, on the Mount Rushmore of Western philosophy. He does so because all three were great systematic philosophers whose systems radically changed and improved earlier ones (5).2 Smith says, “Integrating theories in logic, ontology, phenomenology, epistemology, and social cum ethical theory—in a way that is not yet widely understood—Husserl developed a complex and wide-ranging system of philosophy” (2). The phenomenology for which Husserl is best known is, for Smith, only a part of Husserl’s systematic philosophy, albeit a part that “plays its special role” (1). Its special role derives from the fact that it is the study of intentionality and thereby provides “the proper foundation for knowledge” (12; see also 77). But that alone, according to Smith, is insufficient to make Husserl’s phenomenology fundamental. Phenomenology, Smith sometimes suggests, is first among equals, foundational in a special way among reciprocally founding parts: For Husserl…all philosophy is founded on the phenomenological theory of intentionality, but phenomenology, logic, ontology, and epistemology are in certain ways mutually founding. Thus, Husserl’s philosophy developed with a kind of structured holism, even as phenomenology became the avowed centerpiece and the proclaimed foundation for the whole system (12). As we can detect in the last quoted sentence, however, Smith’s acknowledgment of the priority Husserl gives phenomenology over the other philosophical sciences is grudging: “the avowed centerpiece and the proclaimed foundation” (my emphases) grudging.
    [Show full text]
  • Sexual Difference, Animal Difference: Derrida and Difference
    H Y P A 1032 Dispatch: 18.2.09 Journal: HYPA CE: Nikhil Journal Name Manuscript No. B Author Received: No. of pages: 23 Op: Sumesh 1 Sexual Difference, Animal Difference: 2 3 Derrida and Difference ‘‘Worthy of its 4 5 Name’’ 6 7 8 KELLY OLIVER 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 I challenge the age-old binary opposition between human and animal, not as philos- 16 ophers sometimes do by claiming that humans are also animals, or that animals are 17 capable of suffering or intelligence, but rather by questioning the very category of ‘‘the 18 animal’’ itself. This category groups a nearly infinite variety of living beings into one 19 concept measured in terms of humans—animals are those creatures that are not 20 human. In addition, I argue that the binary opposition between human and animal is 21 intimately linked to the binary opposition between man and woman. Furthermore, I 22 suggest that thinking through animal differences or differences among various living 23 creatures opens up the possibility of thinking beyond the dualist notion of sexual 24 difference and enables thinking toward a multiplicity of sexual differences. 25 26 27 28 Reading the history of philosophy, feminists have pointed out that ‘‘female,’’ 29 ‘‘woman,’’ and ‘‘femininity’’ often fall on the side of the animal in the human– 30 animal divide, as the frequent generic use of the word ‘‘man’’ suggests. From 31 Plato through Hegel, Freud and beyond, women have been associated with 32 Nature and instincts to procreate, which place them in the vicinity of the an- 33 imal realm.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relevance of Natorp's Criticism of Husserl to the Hermeneutical
    Contents lists available at Vilnius University Press Problemos ISSN 1392-1126 eISSN 2424-6158 2020, vol. 98, pp. 8–20 DOI: https://doi.org/10.15388/Problemos.98.1 Filosofijos istorija / History of Philosophy The Relevance of Natorp’s Criticism of Husserl to the Hermeneutical Transformation of Heidegger’s Phenomenology Stefano Cazzanelli Universidad Francisco de Vitoria Email: [email protected] ORCID http://orcid.org/0000-0002-2320-7640 Abstract. This article will show how Natorp’s criticism of Husserlian phenomenology was one of the most important triggers of the hermeneutical transformation of Heideggerian phenomenology. Concepts like herme- neutical intuition, or tools like formal indication, are the means that Heidegger worked out in order to preserve the phenomenological access to pre-theoretical life as it gives itself. The first part of this article is devoted to presenting Natorp’s criticisms of Husserl’s phenomenology and Husserl’s attempts to answer them. The second part will illustrate how Heidegger, criticizing Natorp, retrieves the validity of the phenomenological intuition and expression by opening up their original, pre-theoretical meanings. It will conclude with a few critical remarks concerning Heidegger’s attempt to describe the motivation of philosophical activity in transcendental terms. Keywords: Heidegger; Natorp; Husserl; Hermeneutics; Neo-Kantianism Natorpo kritika Husserliui ir jos reikšmė hermeneutiniam Heideggerio fenomenologijos pokyčiui Santrauka. Straipsnyje parodoma, kad Natorpo kritika Husserlio fenomenologijai buvo vienas svarbiausių veiksnių, paskatinusių hermeneutinę Husserlio fenomenologijos transformaciją. Tokie konceptai kaip herme- neutinė intuicija ar tokie įrankiai kaip formalioji indikacija yra Heideggerio sugalvoti būdai išsaugoti feno- menologinę prieigą prie ikiteorinio gyvenimo, kaip jis pats save pateikia.
    [Show full text]