Lea Ypi on Revolution in Kant and Marx
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
What Is Wrong in Heidegger's Revolution?
CHAPTER 4 WHAT IS WRONG IN HEIDEGGER’S REVOLUTION? One of the consequences of Heidegger’s active participation in the National Socialist revolution is that the year 1933 functions as a kind of prism, separating Heideggerians and Heidegger’s detractors into different groups. At the same time, the different views and critiques provide light on Heidegger’s thought on revolution. The conundrum that Heidegger was both a Nazi and possibly the most influential philosopher of the 20th century forms a kind of entry-level exam for all wannabe revolutionary philosophers. This is also the reason why Heidegger’s thought on revolution forms a necessary background for Žižek. A SMALL MAN LIVING IN HARD TIMES Maybe the saddest but still quite an understandable apology—heard from some of Heidegger’s pupils1, from some commentators who haven’t looked at the matter in detail and from many orthodox Heideggerians who want to continue along the lines of the defence prepared by Heidegger himself—is the claim that Heidegger was basically an apolitical man, not very well aware of social questions, who is swept away, very briefly, in the powerful current of Nazism. Often the claim is combined with the general backdrop that philosophers and deep thinkers are not even supposed to be very sensitive towards their immediate surroundings. They deal with grander, deeper, if not eternal things. Forwarded by a philosopher, such a view is understandable, because it at the same time provides its presenter a kind of diplomatic immunity. For the same reason it is very sad, implying that philosophy should happen in an ivory tower (and, by being a comment on philosophy and politics, it manages to pull the rug from under itself). -
7: MARX's THEORY of ETHICS Svetozar Stojanovic
7: MARX'S THEORY OF ETHICS Svetozar Stojanovic I In the history of Marxism and Marxology two kinds of interpretation of Marx can be easily distinguished. One might be called nonethical and the other ethical. I shall argue in the spirit of the latter, namely that Marx's writings have considerable ethical content that could be used as a starting point to work out a Marxist normative ethics. How ever at present there exists no such ethics, at least none satisfactory and worthy of Marx's name. Why? Several reasons are usually cited and from them I can accept a poli tical one, namely Stalinism which prevented work on the develop ment of the true Marxist ethics. However the root, in my opinion, goes much deeper and can be found within Marx's own writings. I shall try to show that unless some theoretical obstacles contained in these writings are removed, the efforts to create a Marxist evaluative ethics will not succeed. II In attempting to develop this thesis it is necessary to consider two questions: what has served as a basis for a completely nonethical interpretation of Marx and what are the reasons usually given by those who claim that Marx's writings have no ethical content, indeed that they could not have such content? First of all it is a fact that Marx himself wrote that he had tran scended the domain of philosophy and entered the field of a “ real, positive science." Consequently he thought that he was the founder of scientific socialism in contrast to a utopian one. -
1 Jerry Shang 5/9/2018 History 310 Austro-Marxism: Finding
1 Jerry Shang 5/9/2018 History 310 Austro-Marxism: Finding Socialism in Modernity Introduction In Otto Bauer’s What is Austro-Marxism? (1927), he stated that Austro-Marxism was first coined by an American socialist, L. Boudin, to describe a collection of Marxist thinkers including Max Adler, Karl Renner, Rudolf Hilferding, Otto Bauer and others who grew up in the socialist student movement of fin-de-siècle Vienna. Despite these thinkers’ common background, Austro- Marxism as a school of thought lacked the unity L. Boudin conferred to it through its name. Even Otto Bauer himself noted that this group of scholars “were united not so much by a specific political orientation.”1 These thinkers cited above all had interests in different areas, for example, Max Adler took on a theoretical approach and tried to apply a neo-Kantian emphasis on subjectivity and human volitions to the Marxist concept of historical progression; Karl Renner focused more on the law and its ability to support the capitalist system; Rudolf Hilferding was known for his discussion on finance capital and his extension upon Marxist economic theories; Otto Bauer focused on the question of nationality and its incorporation into Marxist thoughts. Though this was not to say that there were no communications and references between these thinkers, the various focuses and interests made it hard to characterize Austro-Marxism as a unified movement. In a sense, Otto Bauer’s question posed by his title remained unanswered. Current historiography on Austro-Marxism has also shied away from this question by focusing on individual thinkers. -
Reading Arendt's on Revolution After the Fall of the Wall
Keeping the Republic: Reading Arendt’s On Revolution after the Fall of the Wall Dick Howard Introduction: From where do you speak, comrade? Two decades after the fall of the Wall seemed to announce – by default, as an unexpected gift – the triumph of democracy, optimism appears at best naïve, at worst an ideological manipulation of the most cynical type. The hope was that the twin forms of modern anti-politics – the imaginary planned society and the equally imaginary invisible hand of the market place – would be replaced by the rule of the demos; citizens together would determine the values of the commonwealth. The reality was at first the ‘New World Order’ of George H.W. Bush; then the indecisive interregnum of the Clinton years; and now the crass take over of democratic rhetoric by the neo-conservatives of George W. Bush. ‘Man is born free, yet everywhere he is in chains,’ wrote Rousseau at the outset of The Social Contract; how this came about was less important, he continued, than what made it legitimate: that was what needed explanation. So it is today; what is it about democracy that makes it the greatest threat to its own existence? In this context, it is well to reread Hannah Arendt’s On Revolution, published in 1963. On returning recently to my old (1965) paperback edition, I was struck by the spare red and black design of the cover, which was not (as I thought for a moment) a subtle allusion to the conflict of communism and anarchism for the realization of ‘true’ democracy, but simply the backdrop against which the editor stressed these sentences: ‘With nuclear power at a stalemate, revolutions have become the principal political factor of our time. -
Clases Sociales Y Estado En El Pensamiento Marxista: Cuestiones De Método
Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México Programa de Posgrado en Estudios Latinoamericanos Taller de investigación: clases sociales y Estado en el pensamiento marxista: cuestiones de método Profesor: Matari Pierre Email: [email protected] Semestre 2021-1 (septiembre-diciembre 2020) 15 sesiones de 4 horas (jueves 16 a 20 horas) Objetivo general El análisis de las clases sociales y de las formas de Estado estructura el pensamiento social y político marxista. Sin embargo, estos conceptos no fueron claramente definidos ni por Marx ni por Engels. Los comentarios posteriores se apoyan en algún aspecto o aforismo de sus obras. De suerte que ambas nociones entrañan problemas de teoría y de método que tensan el marxismo desde sus orígenes: el determinismo económico del proceso histórico; la antropología subyacente a las definiciones de las clases y de sus relaciones recíprocas; la naturaleza específica de lo político y de las formas de Estado. El taller propone introducir y discutir estas tres cuestiones a partir de una selección de textos de representantes, comentaristas y críticos del pensamiento social y político marxista del siglo XX. El programa está organizado en dos grandes partes divididas en tres secciones cada una. Introducción (dos sesiones) Lecturas obligatorias: Eric J. Hobsbawm, “La contribución de Karl Marx a la historiografía”. Shlomo Avineri, El pensamiento social y político de Marx (capítulo I “Reconsideración de la filosofía política de Hegel). Jean-Paul Sartre, Cuestiones de método (primera parte “Marxismo y existencialismo”). Lecturas complementarias: Raymond Aron, Las etapas del pensamiento sociológico (“los equívocos de la sociología 1 marxista” extracto del capítulo 3). Tom Bottomore y Maximilien Rubel, “La sociología y la filosofía social de Marx”. -
Havel and Habermas on Identity and Revolution
260 Praxis International Praxis International 261 HAVEL AND HABERMAS ON IDENTITY AND REVOLUTION Martin J. Matuštík A few months before the November 1989 collapse of „real existing socialism” in Central and Eastern Europe, Habermas reflected on the revolutionary ideas of 1789. How is one to think within plural and secular modernity about a radical democratic republic? He notes the paradox of post-traditional ethical self-realization and moral self-determination: social revolutions project contents and forms that in a finite way transcend the revolutionary action, but revolution shipwrecks before the project gets off the ground. He proposes that to overcome the “sorrow” and the “melancholy” of projected revolutionary possibility, one must form post- traditional identities in those life-forms which are nurtured by a “permanent and everyday-becoming revolution.”1 In a key essay that comes to terms with the ideas and revolutions of November 1989, Habermas reiterates his proposal. But now he consoles the melancholy leftists who despair over the lost meaning of socialism. Has “socialism” become an empty phrase and “ritual oracle,” to use Havel’s characterizations?2 Does it designate merely the deposed mafia of the Communist nomenclature? Why are some unorthodox and reformed Western Marxists in a disenchanted condition of hopelessness? Has the utopia of non-authoritarian life-forms and open identity-formation been lost?3 Habermas stipulates that a „non-communist leftist“ translates the projected revolutionary possibility into a concrete, not concretistic, life-form based on the collective rational will-formation. This formal expression of a life-form means that a radical democratic republic provides that “placeless place” which cures revolutionary melancholy, and which complements and stabilizes post-traditional identity. -
Losurdo, Domenico. Non-Violence: a History Beyond the Myth Lanham: Lexington Books, 2015
The Philosophical Journal of Conflict and Violence Vol. I, Issue 2/2017 © The Authors, 2017 Available online at http://trivent-publishing.eu/ Losurdo, Domenico. Non-Violence: A History beyond the Myth Lanham: Lexington Books, 2015. vii + 246 pp. Domenico Losurdo, in his book Non-Violence: A History Beyond the Myth, aims to demonstrate the historical contradictions of non-violent action. This book embraces two centuries of the history of non-violence, reconstructing the great historical crises that this movement has faced from its inception. In his analysis, Losurdo does not limit himself to a history of the ideas, but instead investigates theories, political opinions, contradictions, moral dilemmas, and concrete behaviors in the context of central historical crises and transformations. Losurdo affirms that the popularity of non-violence movements is in part based on frustration with wars and revolutions that promised to achieve a state of perpetual peace by implementing their different methods. In other words, violence was used to guarantee the eradication of the scourge of violence once and for all. The First World War was greeted by mass enthusiasm to enlist in “the war to end all wars.” Similarly, the revolution in Russia was expected to overcome the brutality of capitalist exploitation and war. Therefore, we are familiar with the blood and tears that have dirtied projects to change the world through war or revolution, but what do we know of the dilemmas, “betrayals,” disappointments, and veritable tragedies that have befallen the movement inspired by the ideal of non-violence (5)? The author recognises that the first group committed to build a socio-political order characterized by non-violence was the Christian abolitionists in the United States in the nineteenth century. -
Hannah Arendt's Political Action: a Dialectic of Expression and Deliberation
Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 2018 Hannah Arendt's Political Action: A Dialectic of Expression and Deliberation Paul Richard Leisen Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Leisen, Paul Richard, "Hannah Arendt's Political Action: A Dialectic of Expression and Deliberation" (2018). Dissertations. 3347. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/3347 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2018 Paul Richard Leisen LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO HANNAH ARENDT’S POLITICAL ACTION: A DIALECTIC OF EXPRESSION AND DELIBERATION A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY BY PAUL R. LEISEN CHICAGO, IL DECEMBER 2018 Copyright by Paul R. Leisen, 2018 All rights reserved. “I’ll have grounds more relative than this–the play’s the thing Wherein I’ll catch the conscience of the King.” —Wm. Shakespeare, Hamlet, III.i.603 (RS 1159) ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I am fortunate to acknowledge the following people for their support and commitment to my work. Without their guidance, love, and shared investment, this project would not have come to fruition. KellyAnn Corcoran’s love and unwavering belief made the pursuit of this work possible. Our children: Betty, Matthias, Penelope, and Sven grew up as this project developed, they have known Hannah Arendt’s name for as long as they can remember. -
Domenico Losurdo
C Abstract: C R R I Starting from the category “totalitarianism” mainstream ideology I S considers Hitler and Stalin as twin brothers. On the contrary, during S I the struggle for his country’s independence, starting in this case from I Stalin and Hitler: S S the category “colonialism”, Gandhi considered Churchill as the twin & brother of Hitler: the goal of the latter was to build the “German Indies” & in Eastern Europe and in Soviet Russia in particular. Which of the C C R two categories can help us understand the twentieth century better? R I Nowadays renowned historians agree on characterising the war between I Twin Brothers or T T I the Third Reich and the Soviet Union as the greatest colonial war in world I Q history. We can say that Hitler and Stalin were both “totalitarian” but we Q U are not allowed to forget that the former, while continuing and further U E E radicalising the Western colonial tradition, strived to subjugate and even Mortal Enemies? / enslave the “inferior races” in Eastern Europe, and that this attempt was / vanquished by the fierce resistance of the country ruled by the latter. In Volume 3 / Volume 3 / Issue 1 this sense Stalin was not the twin brother but the mortal foe of Hitler. The Issue 1 rout in Stalingrad of Hitler’s project to build the “German Indies in Eastern Europe was the beginning of the decline of the British Indies too and of the world colonial system in general. Keywords: Domenico Totalitarianism, Colonialism, German Indies, World War II, British Indies 1.Historical Events and Theoretical Categories When philosophers investigate historical events, they try to discuss at the same time the categories with which historical events are Losurdo reconstructed and described. -
Transtext(E)S Transcultures 跨文本跨文化 Journal of Global Cultural Studies
Transtext(e)s Transcultures 跨文本跨文化 Journal of Global Cultural Studies 14 | 2019 Re-thinking Latin America: Challenges and Possibilities Epistemología de la crisis: apuntes zavaletianos sobre coyuntura chilena y andina Epistemology of the Crisis: the Chilean and Andean Situation Through a Zavaleta Mercado’s Framework of Analysis Felipe Lagos-Rojas Edición electrónica URL: http://journals.openedition.org/transtexts/1301 DOI: 10.4000/transtexts.1301 ISSN: 2105-2549 Editor Gregory B. Lee Referencia electrónica Felipe Lagos-Rojas, « Epistemología de la crisis: apuntes zavaletianos sobre coyuntura chilena y andina », Transtext(e)s Transcultures 跨文本跨文化 [En ligne], 14 | 2019, mis en ligne le 31 décembre 2019, consulté le 28 juillet 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/transtexts/1301 ; DOI : https:// doi.org/10.4000/transtexts.1301 Este documento fue generado automáticamente el 28 julio 2020. © Tous droits réservés Epistemología de la crisis: apuntes zavaletianos sobre coyuntura chilena y an... 1 Epistemología de la crisis: apuntes zavaletianos sobre coyuntura chilena y andina Epistemology of the Crisis: the Chilean and Andean Situation Through a Zavaleta Mercado’s Framework of Analysis Felipe Lagos-Rojas Introducción 1 El año 2019 nos dejó un mapa sociopolítico latinoamericano en el que resalta la franja andina, en un proceso de ajuste de placas sociales que promete tener alcances continentales, si bien desiguales o asincrónicos, y cuyo epicentro actual solo recientemente se ha desplazado desde la región andina hacia los Estados Unidos.1 El núcleo de este artículo estará puesto en el proceso Chile, pero se hacen necesarias asimismo referencias al proceso boliviano, así como alusiones a otros países del continente. -
CB Macpherson and the Twenty-First-Century Prospects Of
Document généré le 2 oct. 2021 09:47 Journal of the Canadian Historical Association Revue de la Société historique du Canada A Half-Century of Possessive Individualism: C.B. Macpherson and the Twenty-First-Century Prospects of Liberalism Ian McKay Volume 25, numéro 1, 2014 Résumé de l'article C.B. Macpherson (1911-1987) a été l’un des penseurs les plus influents et les URI : https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1032806ar plus controversés de son temps. Il est le plus souvent associé aux thèses de DOI : https://doi.org/10.7202/1032806ar « l’individualisme possessif » et du « transfert des pouvoirs ». Parfois considéré à tort comme étant marxiste, ce qui lui a attiré les foudres des partisans de Aller au sommaire du numéro l’École de Cambridge en pleine guerre froide, Macpherson a dit lui-même tenter d’utiliser les ressources de la tradition marxiste pour clarifier et ranimer le libéralisme. À une époque où le néolibéralisme est devenu hégémonique Éditeur(s) dans toute la société civile occidentale, un regard nouveau est aujourd’hui porté sur Macpherson. En faisant de la propriété un phénomène The Canadian Historical Association / La Société historique du Canada philosophique, Macpherson a transformé le bon sens de son époque (et de la nôtre) en un problème politico-éthique, ce qui revêt un grand intérêt non ISSN seulement pour les historiens, mais aussi pour toute gauche émergente qui cherche à baliser un avenir plus rationnel. 0847-4478 (imprimé) 1712-6274 (numérique) Découvrir la revue Citer cet article McKay, I. (2014). A Half-Century of Possessive Individualism: C.B. -
Present Day Ideas on Revolution
PRESENT DAY IDEAS ON REVOLUTION. BY GILBERT REID. REVOLUTION is a word used of late more frequently than any other. Its use by many classes of society and in so many parts of the world indicates a general unrest and discontent, the usual precursor of revolutionary movements, unless met half way by opposing- and dominating forces in society and in the nation. Once let general discontent get started and revolution will not be long in coming. Use of the word revolution has a wider application than ever before. There are all kinds of revolution, some good and some bad. It is hard to think straight in the midst of confusion of ideas over the meaning of a word as dominating as revolution. There have been national revolutions all through the past, but now we hear of schemes for a world or international revolution. Along with revolution, instigated by radicals, there is counter-revolution, instigated by reactionaries. Thus it is that devotees of monarchism and absolutism are at one time anti-revolution and at another pro- revolution. ProHfic discussion now exists concerning social revolution, industrial revolution, and even moral revolution and spiritual rev- volution. Those who support the existing order find revolution- ists in abundance—among Socialists of the Left Wing, among ad- vocates of the Soviet system, and among Bolsheviks, Spartarcides^ syndicalists, communists, anarchists, I. W. W.'s, and other kinds of radical thinkers and busy agitators. These suspected revolu- tionists, rightly or wrongly, are looked upon by the intelligencia as of the worst and most dangerous type in human society.