Marchamont Nedham and mystery of state

Book or Report Section

Published Version

Foxley, R. (2013) Marchamont Nedham and mystery of state. In: Mahlberg, G. and Wiemann, D. (eds.) European contexts for English republicanism. Politics and Culture in Europe, 1650–1750. Ashgate, Farnham, pp. 49-62. ISBN 9781409455561 Available at http://centaur.reading.ac.uk/29473/

It is advisable to refer to the publisher’s version if you intend to cite from the work. See Guidance on citing .

Publisher: Ashgate

All outputs in CentAUR are protected by Intellectual Property Rights law, including copyright law. Copyright and IPR is retained by the creators or other copyright holders. Terms and conditions for use of this material are defined in the End User Agreement . www.reading.ac.uk/centaur CentAUR

Central Archive at the University of Reading

Reading’s research outputs online © Copyrighted Material

Chapter 3 m o .c te a g h s Marchamont Nedham and Mystery of State.a w w w

m o Rachel Foxley c . te a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h It is some measure of the extraordinary qualities of Marchamonts Nedham that he .a w managed to serve virtually all of the political causes and regimesw of two of the most w

m unstable decades of English history, and lived to fight anothero day. Having served .c te both Parliament and king in the Civil Wars of the 1640s, aand charted a precarious g h s but profitable path through the shifting regimes.a and factions of the 1650s,he w w w turned again after monarchy was restored, and just before his death in the later m o 1 1670s was accepting pay for his attacks on Shaftesbury..c His willingness to test the te a g limits of his current political masters with audacioush and provocative journalism s .a was apparently matched only by his aptitude forw slipping across political divides w w to serve new masters when circumstances – personalm and national – demanded it. o .c The brilliance of Nedham’s wit attractedte his paymasters in the political a g h turmoil of the Civil Wars and Interregnum,s and it attracts scholars now. The .a w apparent flexibility of his conscience hasw been more of an embarrassment, and w

m interpretations of his career have triedo to draw out some threads of political .c te a commitment which stayed unbrokeng through at least some of his switches of h s allegiance, pointing to his hostility.a to the Scots and their Presbyterian allies in w w w England, or at the very least to his desire to secure freedom of conscience in m o England, or concern about the. c power of the army. While Jason McElligott has te a g urged us to take seriously Nedham’sh commitment as a supporter of the king and s .a w editor of the royalist newsbookw Mercurius Pragmaticus from 1647 to 1649, most w commentators have seen mNedham as having a deeper commitment to republican o .c te a g h 1 s Joseph Frank, Cromwell’s.a Press Agent: A Critical Biography of Marchamont w w Nedham, 1620–1678 (Washington,w DC, 1980), is now supplemented by much recent work,

m including Joad Raymond,o ‘Nedham, Marchamont (bap. 1620, d. 1678)’, Oxford Dictionary .c te a of National Biographyg (Oxford, 2004), hereafter ODNB. For an analysis of some of the h s vicissitudes and .a turning-points of Nedham’s career, see Raymond, ‘“A Mercury with a w w Winged Conscience”:w Marchamont Nedham, Monopoly and Censorship’, Media History,

m o 4 (1998), pp..c 7–18; Jason McElligott, Royalism, Print and Censorship in Revolutionary te a England (Woodbridge,g 2007), pp. 111–26; Jason Peacey, Politicians and Pamphleteers: h s Propaganda.a During the English Civil Wars and Interregnum (Aldershot, 2004), pp. 280–87, w w w 291–5. We should not forget that Nedham did not necessarily jump quickly when the m o balance.c of power shifted. McElligott emphasizes the trials he went through before making te a his gpeace with the new regime in 1649; Joad Raymond, ‘The Cracking of the Republican h s Spokes’,.a Prose Studies, 19 (1996), pp. 255–74, aligns him with Milton in holding out w w againstw restoration. © Copyrighted Material 50 European Contexts for English Republicanism © Copyrighted Material

2 thought. The plausibility of this rests not only on his parliamentarianism in his m o career up to 1646, which culminated in a series of controversial attacks on Charles.c te a g h I, but also on the quality of his writings under the republic and protectorate:s he .a w seemed keen, at least at times, to offer far more challenging models of republicanw w 3 government than his political masters were willing or able to implement.m Indeed, o .c te compared to the sometimes aristocratic or godly republicanism even ofa his fellow g h s republican theorists in the 1650s, Nedham’s writings seem strikingly.a populist. In w w an influential brief assessment in hisMachiavellian Moment, J.G.A.w Pocock found

m o Nedham’s republican editorials for Mercurius Politicus ‘consistently.c radical and te a democratic’: ‘the first sustained English exposition ofg republican democracy h s 4 .a in classical and Machiavellian terms.’ Many more recent writersw have aligned w w 5 Nedham’s republicanism with radical thought in a similar way. m o .c Nedham’s writings, republican and otherwise, displayte a strand of hard-edged a g h political calculation which makes him an interesting exemplars of the deployment .a w of controversial but increasingly influential contemporaryw modes of thought about w

m politics. Thus his familiarity from early in his journalistico career with the interest .c te theory of the duc de Rohan; his use of Machiavelli, afrom the anonymous Vox Plebis g h s in 1646 to the treatises and newspaper editorials .aof the 1650s; and his willingness w w w to deploy both Grotian and Hobbesian ideas in the cause of the new free state m 6 o have all been noted. All these authors could.c certainly be used to think about the te a g political challenges and exigencies of a newh state, or of changes in the political s .a balance, in ways which might have enabledw changes of allegiance for subjects as w w

m o .c te 2 a McElligott, Royalism, Print and gCensorship, pp. 120–25; contrast Raymond, ‘The h s .a Cracking of the Republican Spokes’, p.w 257. w 3 w On Nedham’s views in his parliamentarian writing to 1646, see Joyce Macadam, m o ‘Mercurius Britanicus on Charles I:.c An Exercise in Civil War Journalism and High Politics, te a g August 1643 to May 1646’, Historicalh Research, 84 (2011), pp. 470–92; Joad Raymond, s .a The Invention of the Newspaper:w English Newsbooks, 1641–1649 (Oxford, 1996), w w pp. 42–8, but see Peacey, Politicians and Pamphleteers, pp. 298–300; Jonathan Scott, m o Commonwealth Principles:.c Republican Writing of the English Revolution (Cambridge, te a g 2004), pp. 241–7; on Nedhamh exceeding his brief in the 1650s, see Peacey, Politicians s .a and Pamphleteers, pp. w291–5; Blair Worden, ‘Marchamont Nedham and the Beginnings w w of English Republicanism, 1649–1656’, in David Wootton (ed.), Republicanism, Liberty, m o and Commercial Society,.c 1649–1776 (Stanford, 1994), pp. 64–5. te a 4 g h J.G.A. Pocock,s The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the .a w Atlantic Republicanw Tradition (Princeton, 1975), p. 382. w 5 Worden,m ‘Marchamont Nedham and the Beginnings of English Republicanism’, o .c pp. 66–7; Paulte Rahe, Against Throne and Altar: Machiavelli and Political Theory under a g h the Englishs Republic (Cambridge, 2008), pp. 198–9, 233–4. .a 6 w Felixw Raab, The English Face of Machiavelli: A Changing Interpretation 1500–1700 w

m (London,o 1964), pp. 159–64; Marco Barducci, ‘Machiavelli nella Cultura Politica Inglese’, .c te in Alessandroa Arienzo and Gianfranco Borrelli (eds), Anglo-American Faces of Machiavelli: g h Machiavellis e Machiavellismi Nella Cultura Anglo-Americana (Milan, 2009), pp. 193–8; .a w w wRahe, Against Throne and Altar, pp. 175–244. © Copyrighted Material Marchamont Nedham and Mystery of State 51 © Copyrighted Material

well as offering controversial prescriptions for rulers; and there is no doubt thatm o .c te they all contributed significantly to the distinctive character of Nedham’s thought.a g h s Nedham’s range of reference, however, is much broader than this. His ause of . w w classical authors in citation and quotation, and his references to a wide rangew of

m more modern authorities, have facilitated his adoption into the canon of o‘classical .c te a republicanism’ and elicited a (cautious) admiration for his learning andg the base h s .a of reading on which he built his topical and versatile political argumentation.w His w w sources did not, of course, predetermine the direction of his political argument. m o .c As Blair Worden once nicely put it, Nedham’s arguments had ate habit of ‘turning a g h on their footnotes’: the same material might be marshalleds for or against a .a 7 w proposition as circumstances demanded. We should certainlyw never expect w

m Nedham’s relationship to his sources to be simple. Nonetheless,o it is perhaps .c te surprising that so little attention has been paid to Nedham’sa ‘footnotes’ – the g h s marginal citations which appear only in a couple of his.a publications in the early w w w Commonwealth period – as they turn out to tell us some surprising things about m o the way in which he wrote and the reading matter to.c which he most readily turned te a g in the process of composition. h s .a The two works which used marginal citationw of authorities to bolster their w w arguments were Certain Considerations Tenderedm in all Humility, to an Honorable o .c Member of the Councell of State (1 August 1649)te and the much longer and better- a g h known Case of the ,s Stated, published in May 1650. .a w Both were concerned with the problems wfaced by governors and people under the w

m new regime of the Commonwealth. Theo first, a 14-page pamphlet, offered some .c te a advice to the Council of State on howg to manage its potential opponents – advice h s which Nedham advertised as drawn.a out of ‘the Opinion and Practice of many w w w the most [sic] eminent Statesmen ’, but which was skilfully oriented towards the m o lenient treatment of Nedham himself.c (he had been thrown into prison) as well as te a g the potential success of the newh regime. The second, Nedham’s ‘job application’ s .a 8 w to his employers in the neww regime, used brutal de facto arguments justifying w the power of the sword asm the only title to government, as well as analyses of the o .c te ‘interest’ of the differenta groups which found themselves in opposition to their g h s new governors, and finally.a a classicizing peroration on the superiority of ‘free w w states’ to monarchies,w to try and induce the new regime’s unwilling population

m to offer it their obedience.o Both texts cited an impressive mixture of ancient and .c te a modern texts in theirg marginal notes. There is little scholarly comment on Certain h s .a Considerationsw , but Joad Raymond finds it ‘significant for its extensive use of w w Roman precedent’, and suggests that it prefigures Nedham’s phase of classical m o .c republican te writing. Joseph Frank commented on its ‘outpouring of classical a g h s .a w 7 w Blairw Worden, ‘“Wit in a ”: The Dilemma of Marchamont Nedham’,

m in Susano Amussen and Mark Kishlansky (eds), Political Culture and Cultural Politics in .c te a Earlyg Modern England: Essays Presented to David Underdown (Manchester and New h s York,.a 1995), p. 301. w w 8 w Rahe, Against Throne and Altar, p. 213. © Copyrighted Material 52 European Contexts for English Republicanism © Copyrighted Material

9 allusions’ and pronounced the tract ‘judicious and learned’. Nigel Smith notes m o its ‘solid references’ to Seneca, Suetonius and Livy, and entertains the thought.c te a g h that it was the result of Nedham’s reading of classical sources in prison, markings .a w the ‘emergence of the republican theory’ which Nedham was then to developw w 10 in his editorials for Mercurius Politicus. The Case of the Commonwealthm has o .c te received more scrutiny, and Philip Knachel’s 1969 edition completeda Nedham’s g h s citations and attempted – sometimes in vain – to collate them with the.a works cited. w w Knachel noticed some inaccuracy in quotation, lamented Nedham’sw ‘casual habits’

m o in citation and suspected him of ‘short cuts’, asking, ‘Had he actually.c read each of te a the authors he quotes?’ – a suspicion presumably fostered by theg incidences noted h s .a in the footnotes where Knachel found citations of other worksw lifted from Gregor w w Richter’s Axiomatum Politicorum of 1604 (Görlitz). Nonetheless, he concluded m o .c that Nedham’s more obscure citations ‘must have requiredte some hard searching, a g 11 h which does suggest that he had read widely.’ More recents scholars, not forced to .a w do such painstaking editorial work, have tended to lookw directly to the classical w

m authors cited in the margins, and to pick out a fewo canonical names from early .c te modern political thought, ignoring the rest of the scholarlya trappings. g h s This is a mistake, as it turns out that Richter’s.a Axiomatum was not the only w w w Latin textbook by a German author that Nedham had on his desk as he wrote – or, m o in some cases, compiled – his tracts. Nedham .cseems to have been inordinately fond te a g of the genre, and two other systematic and compendioush treatises lie behind a large s .a number of his citations. One is Arnold Clapmar’sw De Arcanis Rerum Publicarum, w w first published posthumously by hism brother in 1605 (Bremen). This influential o .c book took up many of the ideas of thete Italian reason of state tradition – Clapmar a g h had been a correspondent of Scipiones Ammirato and was particularly heavily .a w w indebted to him – and repackagedw them under the notion of ‘arcana imperii’,

m transforming ‘reason’ of state intoo ‘mysteries’ of state. Among the authors who .c te a followed Clapmar’s lead in thisg analysis was the jurist Christoph Besold, whose h s .a short De Arcanis Rerum Publicarumw Dissertatio was appended to some editions of w w 12 Clapmar’s work, including, I suspect, the one which Nedham used. The second, m o .c te a g h s .a w w 9 w Raymond, ‘Nedham’, ODNB; Frank, Cromwell’s Press Agent, p. 73. m o 10 .c Nigel Smith,te Literature and Revolution in England, 1640–1660 (New Haven and a g h London, 1994), pp.s 32–4. .a 11 w Marchamontw Nedham, The Case of the Commonwealth of England, Stated, ed. P.A. w

Knachel (Charlottesville,m 1969), pp. v, xxxiii, 10, 11, 13. o 12 .c te Nedham’sa citation of this as a ‘dissertatio’ points towards an edition such as Arnold g h Clapmar, sDe Arcanis Rerum Publicarum Libri Sex … Accessit Chr. Besoldi De eadem .a w materia wDiscursus (Leiden, 1644) rather than the Elsevier edition (Amsterdam, 1644), which w

m also includeso the Besold tract but refers to it as a ‘discursus’ rather than a ‘dissertatio’. I will .c te cite athe Leiden edition for both texts. The Camena project at Heidelberg and Mannheim g h hass made this volume available conveniently online: http://www.uni-mannheim.de/mateo/ .a w w camenahtdocs/camenahist.html.w © Copyrighted Material Marchamont Nedham and Mystery of State 53 © Copyrighted Material

longer treatise used heavily by Nedham was Besold’s own Synopsis Politicaem o 13 .c te Doctrinae. a g h s Nedham’s use of these texts was intensive, and to a modern reader coulda seem . w w dishonest. Certain Considerations is effectively a tissue of material translatedw out

m of both Clapmar’s and Besold’s texts on the arcana, plus Clapmar’s Conclusioneso , .c te a also in the same volume, held together in some places by only the mostg tenuous h s .a connective phrases of Nedham’s own. Nedham, of course, contributedw his own w w unmistakable brio to some of his more paraphrastic translations, and to some m o .c extent reshaped his material by inserting notions which were notte necessarily there a g h in the original. He certainly drove home the message that theses lessons were of .a w paramount importance to the rulers of new states, and free states,w altering not only w

m the terminology of translations but also the wording of someo of his Latin quotations. .c te But in other respects he engaged in surprisingly little selectiona or reshaping: whole g h s strings of references and quotations follow in a sequence.a which is almost identical w w w to the original, so that in places a paragraph of Nedham can be traced directly to a m o page or two of Clapmar or Besold. The pamphlet is .clarded with marginal citations te a g from learned authors, but Clapmar, to whom Nedhamh was most indebted, did not s .a appear among them. Besold’s De Arcanis was atw least cited more than once, but w w in very small proportion to the amount of materialm which Nedham mined directly o .c from it. The Case of the Commonwealth is a morete considered piece and is certainly a g h not as reliant on a dense use of second-hands sources as the shorter pamphlet, .a w but sections of it are similarly derivativew in the citation of authorities, exploiting w

m Besold’s Synopsis Politicae Doctrinaeo as well as the arcana texts and evidently .c te a Richter. Thus the section on the Levellersg illustrates the evils of extreme democracy h s 14 with the help of references lifted directly.a from Besold’s section on this. w w w Of course, these compendious Latin texts were partly designed to be used m o in such ways. Books like Besold’s.c Synopsis served in the realm of politics the te a g same kind of purpose as the h reference books and compendia discussed by Ann s .a w Blair, offering ‘a stockpile ofw notes ready for use without the difficulties of taking w 15 them directly’. Nedham mwas not unusual, either in making use of these treasure- o .c te troves of thematically organizeda classical and modern quotations, or in failing to g h s acknowledge them. Nonetheless,.a this does put Nedham’s working methods, and w w his notoriously opportunisticw use of his sources, in a new light. Scholars have

m tended to assume thato Nedham’s quotations from the central classical authors, at .c te a least, reflected someg genuine influence from the thinking of those authors. When h s .a we find, in Certainw Considerations, that a string of classical references – Cicero, w w Aristotle, Tacitus and Juvenal – has in fact been mined directly from Clapmar with m o .c te a g h 13 s Christoph.a Besold, Synopsis Politicae Doctrinae: Editio Sexta (Amsterdam, 1648). w 14 w wFor examples, references to Bodin, Pierre Gregoire, Contzen and Polybius

m (Nedham,o Case of the Commonwealth, ed. Knachel, pp. 101, 103–4) are taken from Besold, .c te a Synopsisg Politicae Doctrinae, pp. 125–7. h s 15 .a Ann Blair, Too Much to Know: Managing Scholarly Information before the Modern w w Agew (New Haven, 2010), p. 4. © Copyrighted Material 54 European Contexts for English Republicanism © Copyrighted Material

16 only a slight change of order, the quality of that influence feels rather different. m o Of course, it does not preclude the possibility that Nedham did have a fair degree.c te a g h of familiarity with some of the authors he was citing. He had a classical education,s .a w at the free school in Burford and then at All Souls, Oxford: an education whichw led w him to a job – which he kept patience with for only three years – at the Merchantm o 17 .c te Taylors’ School in London. He worked comfortably from the Latin acompendia g h s and himself undertook a more taxing translation in the service of .athe republic, w 18 w producing an English version of Selden’s Mare Clausum. We cannotw be sure

m o what depth of knowledge underlay Nedham’s use of snippets. c of the classical te a and modern texts excerpted in other sources. Mistakes, misattributionsg and h s .a misquotations point in one direction, but are entirely explicablew by Nedham’s own w w 19 purposes and the speed with which he was assembling his materials. They may be m o .c partly counterbalanced by occasions when Nedham replaceste Latin transcription of a g h terms with Greek, or by cases where he seems to be usings a classical text in ways .a w 20 which are more extensive than, or differ from, his usualw sources. When Nedham w

m later set out some of the arcana of rule in Mercuriuso Politicus, he clearly drew .c te on Clapmar in his editorial on the need for educationa appropriate to a free state. g h s Here, however, Clapmar seems to have sent him.a back to the text of Tacitus, as w w w Nedham accurately continued (in translation) the passage which Clapmar quoted m 21 o incomplete. On the other side of the balance,.c Nedham cites three passages of te a g Guicciardini in Certain Considerations andh the Case of the Commonwealth: all are s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h 16 s Nedham, Certain Considerations.a , pp. 2–3; Clapmar, De Arcanis, pp. 307–9. w w 17 w Frank, Cromwell’s Press Agent , pp. 5–6. m 18 o , Of the Dominion,.c or, Ownership of the Sea, trans. Marchamont te a g Nedham (London, 1652). h s 19 .a See for example Nedham,w Certain Considerations, p. 8: the words ‘opprobria’ and w w

‘& suos’ are Nedham’s own;m the quotation is from Tacitus, Annals 2.50, not Suetonius; o .c Nedham takes it from Clapmar,te De Arcanis, p. 312. More than once Nedham credits a phrase a g h to the wrong name from as selection cited on that point in his source text; he sometimes cites .a w parts of Clapmar’s or Besold’sw own wording as if they were quotations from another text. w 20 Nedham substitutedm Greek typography for ‘Isonomia’ when following Besold: o .c Besold, Synopsis Politicaete Doctrinae, p. 125; Nedham, Case of the Commonwealth, ed. a g h Knachel, p. 98; s in Nedham’s Certain Considerations, the quotations from Seneca are .a w virtually the onlyw Latin phrases which cannot be traced to the Clapmar/Besold volume on w the arcana: Nedhamm was presumably using a different source (whether or not it was the o .c original text)te or working from memory. a g 21 h Mercuriuss Politicus 104 (27 May–3 June 1652), p. 1629. The first part of the .a w passage wfrom Tacitus, Annals 1.3 is quoted in Clapmar, De Arcanis, p. 295, and Nedham is w

m clearlyo following Clapmar’s argument about Augustus’s superior guile compared to Caesar. .c te The afinal part of the passage from Tacitus is quoted in Clapmar,De Arcanis, p. 78; Nedham g h quotess from this page of Clapmar in this editorial, pp. 1625, 1627. The middle part of the .a w w Tacitusw passage is not found in Clapmar and is accurately supplied by Nedham. © Copyrighted Material Marchamont Nedham and Mystery of State 55 © Copyrighted Material

to be found in Besold, so we have no evidence that Nedham had read Guicciardinim o 22 .c te himself at this point. a g h s In some ways, this insight into Nedham’s way of writing and citing raisesa more . w w questions than it answers: further work will be required to pin down the wbalance

m between sources which Nedham used in the original and those he used oat second .c te a hand. What it does show us, however, is Nedham’s deep familiarity withg a genre of h s .a contemporary political books which have not been linked to Nedhamw in previous w w scholarship. This is interesting because it puts the more canonical contemporary m o .c influences on Nedham in a slightly different light. The Germante treatises which a g h shaped so many of the sequences of classical and modern materials which Nedham .a w used in his arguments offered a rather different view of politicalw morality from w

m these more well-known sources, although one which had opoints of contact with, .c te and complicated debts to, Machiavellian thought. They alsoa belonged to a tradition g h s which was not marked by any commitment to republicanism,.a and we should w w w question the relationship between such materials and any republican message that m o Nedham derived from them. .c te a g On the face of it, the mystery of state traditionh might seem to endorse a s .a rather cynical approach to politics, lining up withw the precepts of Machiavelli w w and enhancing our sense of Nedham as a pragmaticm advocate of amoral political o .c rationality. The German mystery of state writers,te like the Italian reason of state a g h theorists on whom they drew, did argue thats rulers sometimes needed to disregard .a w law and morality in defence of their statesw or of their own power. Clapmar grafted w

m the category of ‘arcana’ or ‘mysteries’o onto these notions of reason of state, .c te a interpreting such acts of pragmatic gpolitical calculation as part of a tradition of h s secret political knowledge, hinted at.a in Aristotle’s discussion of ‘sophismata’ and w w 23 w in Tacitus. This gave the practice of reason of state a certain ancient and mystical m o pedigree, and it also brought to.c the fore the element of deception or simulation te a g which might be involved. Clapmar’sh work divided its material up into superficially s .a w systematic, although sometimesw overlapping, categories. The last book was w 24 devoted to a species of them arcana which he called ‘simulacra’. These were ways o .c te in which rulers could createa the illusion of adherence to one constitutional form, g h s even when it had in fact.a been changed for another. This naturally had particular w w relevance to new regimes,w and, arguably, to propagandists, and Nedham was drawn

m to this section of theo book for some of his material in the Certain Considerations. .c te a Even beyondg the tricks classified as ‘simulacra’, however, the theme of arcana as h s .a types of deceptionw was prominent, and the aim was the management of potentially w w troublesome, factious or discontented subjects. For Besold, the enforcement of m o .c te a g h 22 s Besold,.a De Arcanis, p. 22; Besold, Synopsis Politicae Doctrinae, pp. 4–5, 314; w w Nedham,w Certain Considerations, p. 3; Nedham, Case of the Commonwealth, ed. Knachel,

m title page,o pp. 100, 117. .c 23te a g Aristotle, Politics, 4.13, for example. h s 24 .a Peter Donaldson, Machiavelli and Mystery of State (Cambridge and New York, w w w1988), pp. 113, 121–39. © Copyrighted Material 56 European Contexts for English Republicanism © Copyrighted Material legal penalties by lawyers was to be supplemented by politicians’ use of guile and m 25 o ‘persuasiuncula’ to secure subjects’ obedience. Nedham certainly seemed to.c be te a g h comfortable, at least at times, with the culture of political mystery which s these .a w writings promoted. In Mercurius Politicus in October 1651 he endorsed the wRoman w division between people and Senate, which allowed the ‘secrets of Government’m o .c 26 te to be handled by men wise and experienced enough for such ‘State-Affairs’.a A g h s few issues later, he made a similar argument for the Athenians’ placing.a of ‘State w 27 w Transactions’ in the Areopagus. Even while arguing for a form of governmentw by

m o elected legislative assemblies as the shibboleth of a truly free state,.c he reserved a te a place for political wisdom which was not to be found in or sharedg with the people. h s .a This is in sharp contrast with John Streater, the other great populistw republican of w w the 1650s, for whom ‘secret reasons of State’ were anathema, and who argued that m o .c Rome’s greatness was secured only when ‘every member teof that Common-wealth a g 28 h perfectly understood the mysteries of State’. s .a w Streater’s desire to dissolve secrets and mysteriesw into universal knowledge w

m points up the fact that the literature endorsing mysteryo of state was far from .c te populist. In constitutional terms, the theory wasa superficially neutral, and g h s Clapmar’s book was divided into sections which .aexplained in turn how each of the w w w three types of state, or particular regimes of each kind, might preserve themselves m o against threats from the other two types. But Clapmar’s.c assumptions clearly tended te a g against democracy: when he discussed theh ‘flagitia dominationis’, the intolerable s .a crimes which each type of regime mightw use to perpetuate itself, he took care to w w note with Cicero that the people, too, couldm be tyrannical, and argued that in fact o .c 29 the ‘flagitia’ were found far more in tpopulare states than in others. Both in Besold a g h and in Clapmar, the emphasis on governors’s use of various forms of flattery and .a w w deception to keep the people placidw is tinged with a contempt for the ease with

m 30 which the ‘plebs’ can be taken ino by such tricks. .c te a At the time when Nedhamg was making use of Clapmar and Besold in Certain h s .a Considerations and the Casew of the Commonwealth, he was happy to endorse w w such a view of the people. He opened Certain Considerations by explaining to m o England’s new governors.c that they were not to expect a rational or disciplined te a g h response to their currents hardships from the people: ‘It is not in their Power to .a w 31 consider the Circumstancesw of Reason’. Clapmar similarly commented in the first w

m section of his booko that applying laws and philosophical precepts was useless for .c te a g h 25 s .a Besold, wDe Arcanis, p. 7. w 26 w Mercurius Politicus 70 (2–9 October 1651), p. 1111. m 27 o Mercurius.c Politicus 73 (23–30 October 1651), p. 1158. te a 28 g h Johns Streater, A Glympse of that Jewel, Judicial, Just, Preserving Libertie (London, .a w 1653), p.w 1; cf. the same, Secret Reasons of State in Reference to the Affairs of these Nations, w

At the mInterruption of this Present Parliament: Anno 1653. Discovered (London, 1659). o 29.c te Clapmar, De Arcanis, pp. 239, 277–9. a g h 30 s Ibid., pp. 1–4. .a w 31 w w Nedham, Certain Considerations, p. 1. © Copyrighted Material Marchamont Nedham and Mystery of State 57 © Copyrighted Material

those among whom there was no place for reason (the margin helpfully explainedm o .c te that this meant the people); therefore the plebs were to be handled by using tricksa g 32 h s and obfuscations and images (simulacra). Nedham’s recommendationsa were . w w less explicitly deceptive, recommending instead a certain indulgence andw lenity

m on the part of the new regime, but he was happy to lift from Clapmar Aristotle’so .c te a thought that (in Nedham’s translation) ‘The common people are naturallyg of a h s .a loose disposition, so that if they may enjoy a kind of dissolute liberty,w they like the w 33 w present state of Government whatsoever it be.’ The anti-populist tone continued m o .c in Nedham’s condemnation of the in the Case of thete Commonwealth, a g h where many of the anti-democratic tropes thrown at the Levellerss were taken .a w from Besold’s account of ‘democratia libera’, the Greek stereotypew of extreme w

m democracy, as discussed in Besold’s Synopsis Politicae Doctrinaeo . Nedham also .c te 34 endorsed Clapmar’s assertion that the ‘flagitia’ flourisheda in democratic states. g h s Even in making an argument for popular, electoral. a government in Mercurius w w w Politicus, Nedham retained some of this attitude, arguing that the people’s power m o was less to be feared than that of kings or grandees, as.c they were so easily contented te a 35 g with ‘Panem, & Circenses’ that they would not runh into excesses of luxury. He s .a had cited Juvenal’s line about bread and circusesw in Certain Considerations two w w years earlier, straight out of Clapmar. Similarly,m later in his great series of editorials o .c defending popular government by successivete assemblies, Nedham countered a g h the objection that popular government wass factious by asserting that the people .a w themselves were ‘purely passive’, merelyw ‘wrought upon by the subtil insinuations w

m 36 of the prime Engineers of each faction’.o .c te a Nedham wrote Certain Considerationsg under severely restricted circumstances: h s either in prison, or recently escaped.a and in hiding. He here publicly addressed a w w w ‘Member of the Councell of State ’, as he was also to do by more personal means, m o 37 eventually securing his release.c after surrendering himself in November 1649. te a g That he apparently drew virtuallyh all of his illustrative material from a single s .a w volume is thus hardly surprising;w but Nedham’s choice of a volume which allowed w him to cite ‘the Opinion mand Practice of many the most eminent Statesmen’ in o .c te manipulating the arcanaa of rule was perhaps pointed when directed at a Council g h s of State whose hold on.a power had immediately become the focus of radical fury. w w w

m o 32 .c Clapmar, Dete Arcanis, pp. 2–3. a g 33 h Nedham, s Certain Considerations, p. 2; Clapmar, De Arcanis, p. 308; Aristotle, .a w Politics, VI.4, onw extreme democracy and the democratic indulgences offered by tyrants. w 34 m Nedham,o Case of the Commonwealth, ed. Knachel, p. 101. .c 35 te Mercuriusa Politicus 84 (8–15 January 1652), p. 1334; the fuller Juvenal quotation g h s is also given.a in Latin on p. 2 of Certain Considerations, from Clapmar, De Arcanis, p. 316. w 36 w wMercurius Politicus 97 (8–15 April 1652), p. 1522.

m 37 o .c The Oxinden and Peyton Letters, 1642–1670, ed. Dorothy Gardiner (London, te a 1937),g p. 161; Blair Worden, Literature and Politics in Cromwellian England (Oxford, h s 2007),.a pp. 45–7 on Bradshaw; Peacey, Politicians and Pamphleteers, p. 283 on Nedham w w appealingw to Thomas Scot. © Copyrighted Material 58 European Contexts for English Republicanism © Copyrighted Material

Equally sly was Nedham’s use of the arcana of rule. His condemnation of informers m o – naturally harsh, as it was just such an informer who had put him in prison – was.c te a g h facilitated by the inclusion of the use of informers as one of the impermissibles .a 38 w ‘flagitia’ characteristic of kingly rule by Clapmar. Virtually the whole of wthe rest w of the pamphlet’s more positive prescriptions from Clapmar, however, werem drawn o .c te rather tellingly from Book 6, which dealt with ‘simulacra’. Specifically,a they were g h s drawn from the sections which discussed the simulacra of democratic.a rule, that w w is, the ways in which a regime could make itself seem more democraticw than it

m o was. The democratic arcana were designed to pacify the people,.c by making the te a constitution seem more oriented towards their needs and desiresg than it really was. h s .a In Certain Considerations, Nedham called on the democraticw arcana from w w Clapmar, along with more general material from Besold’s De Arcanis, in order to m o .c argue that a degree of indulgence towards the people was necessaryte for the regime. a g h Emphasizing the precarious position of new regimes, hes argued that the people – .a w who were irrational but responsive to their immediate painsw and pleasures – should w

m be treated gently. Drawing on Besold’s De Arcanis, heo suggested that governments .c te would do best to secure the love of their subjects,a rather than punishing them g h 39 s over-harshly. This apparently disinterested advice.a led into the core of Nedham’s w w w pamphlet, in which he pleaded the case for the tolerance of critical speeches and m o publications against the government, and argued.c that ‘Pasquils and Pamphlets’ te a g should be allowed to circulate. Nedham’sh personal interest here is obvious: he s .a wanted the authorities to overlook his publicationw of opposition newsbooks and w w endorse his release from prison, and hem was making the case for his own trade. o .c Nedham’s political position here, however,te is far less clear. Nigel Smith finds the a g h pamphlet troublingly noncommittal sand contradictory, an effect exacerbated when .a w w 40 reading it in the light of its opportunisticw mining of the volume on the arcana.

m However, some of the material othat Nedham used in Certain Considerations did .c te a point forward in intriguing waysg to the later concerns of his more republican h s .a newsbook editorials: not in thew simple use of certain classical sources, on which far w w too much weight has been placed as a marker of ‘classical republican’ sympathies, m o but in Nedham’s hints about.c the complicated play of forms, names and reality. te a g h Nedham was awares that he was counselling a regime which claimed to have .a w founded a ‘free state’.w Condemning the ‘flagitia’ characteristic of monarchy was w

m straightforward: theo Commonwealth authorities should surely want to distance .c te themselves from asuch practices. But Nedham did not generally choose his positive g h s recommendations.a from those suited to popular or even aristocratic governments. w w Rather than wadvising the Council of State on how to implement and defend

m o popular government,.c he explained how it could disguise the regime as a popular te a g government.h Allowing free speech, and accepting that ‘rumusculi & pasquilli’ (as s .a w w w 38 m Nedham, Certain Considerations, pp. 12–14; Clapmar, De Arcanis, pp. 267–9; The o .c Oxindente and Peyton Letters, pp. 160–61. a g h 39 s Besold, De Arcanis, pp. 18–22. .a w 40 w w Smith, Literature and Revolution, pp. 32–4. © Copyrighted Material Marchamont Nedham and Mystery of State 59 © Copyrighted Material

Clapmar calls them) could not be suppressed, were ways in which rulers couldm o .c te persuade a people that they were living in a more popular state than they reallya g h s were. The examples with which Clapmar illustrated this section of his booka were . w 41 w largely taken from Rome after the fall of the republic. Nedham slyly appliedw them

m to exactly the opposite constitutional situation: the replacement of a monarchyo by .c te a a supposedly ‘free state’. He covered his back, saying ‘If Emperors theng allowed h s .a so great a liberty of writing and speaking, much more may it be expectedw in a free w 42 w State and Common-wealth.’ But within a few lines he slipped back away from m o .c the notion of real freedom, and wrote that ‘this licence is to bete reckoned inter a 43 g h simulacra libertatis’. In a phrase which he did not translate intos the vernacular, .a w Nedham thus slyly drew attention to the provocative suggestionw that the new w

m regime had no desire to bring about true liberty. Nedham odid not declare that he .c te was prescribing the deliberate simulation of democratic a government, and he did g h s not disclose his source. But an alert reader, particularly one.a with the minimal Latin w w w required to pick up the hint about simulated liberty, would surely notice that it was m o odd to advise a state which had just thrown off monarchy.c by recommending the te a 44 g wiles of Augustus, Tiberius and Lorenzo de’ Medici.h s .a None of this shows, of course, that Nedham atw this stage wanted a truly popular w w government rather than a simulation; or on them contrary that he positively wanted o .c what on the face of it he recommended: a stablete new regime which did just enough a g h to seem like a free state. His slowness to abandons the royalist cause and make his .a w peace with the new regime may suggest wthat he merely noted a certain hypocrisy w

m in a government whose crackdown ono opposition in print was at odds with its .c te a profession to be a free state. Nedhamg was adding his own gloss to Clapmar’s and h s Besold’s material when he pointed.a out that ‘above all others’ the governors of a w w w free state ‘must bear with these things, and take heed of crossing the people in this m 45 o licentious humor’. Why was the.c new free state so frightened of its own people? te a g As he established himselfh as an indispensable servant of the new regime, and s .a w as that regime established itselfw more securely in power, Nedham offered a far less w ambiguous commentary onm the shadow and substance of liberty, and the appearance o .c te and reality of constitutionala forms. His vocabulary and some of his material show g h s that in his republican editorials.a for Mercurius Politicus Nedham was still drawing w w on the mysteries andw simulacra of rule derived from Clapmar and Besold, although

m 46 the direct influenceo of Machiavelli also became more prominent. In a series of .c te a g h s .a 41 w Clapmar,w De Arcanis, pp. 309–12, naturally drawing heavily on Tacitus. w 42 Nedham,m Certain Considerations, p. 9. o 43 .c te ‘[A]monga the simulacra of liberty’. Nedham, Certain Considerations, p. 10. g h 44 s Ibid.,.a pp. 8–9. w 45 w wIbid., p. 8; cf. Clapmar, De Arcanis, p. 312; Besold, De Arcanis, pp. 42–3.

m 46 o .c Nedham’s use of Clapmar’s terminology: ‘flagitious Enormities’, Mercurius te a Politicusg 100 (29 April–6 May 1652), p. 1572; ‘inter flagitia Dominationis … one of the h s peculiar.a enormities, that attends the Lordly interest of Domination’, Mercurius Politicus 96 w w w(1–8 April 1652), p. 1506. © Copyrighted Material 60 European Contexts for English Republicanism © Copyrighted Material editorials beginning in the autumn of 1651, he set out to show that liberty would m o be best preserved by the people electing their own successive assemblies. When.c te a g h he came to refute objections, one urgent task was to answer the objections that .a w ‘Arcana Imperii, secrets of State’ could never be effectively handled by thew mass w of new members elected to each new successive assembly. Rather than mrejecting o .c te the need for the arcana, he agreed that they were ‘of a nature remote froma ordinary g h s Apprehensions’, but argued that they could safely be entrusted .a to a council w 47 w answerable to the sovereign legislative assembly. Alongside this wdefence of the

m o necessity of arcana, remade as executive power and integrated into.c his argument te a for the separation of powers, Nedham used the analytical toolsg offered by the h s .a mystery of state tradition to understand the mistakes of previousw regimes and the w w ways in which anti-popular interests would try to practise upon the people. Indeed, m o .c he argued that these arcana had to be divulged in order forte the people to defend a g h their liberty: ‘the mysteries of domination have been stills kept under Lock and .a w Key’. In a rare allusion to his reading of these texts, he wclaimed to have ‘made brief w

m Collections out of the monuments of this kind of learning’o which he would now .c 48 te expound. He duly proceeded over a series of editorialsa to analyse ‘those Rules, g h s which have been practised in time past by divers.a Nations, for the keeping of their w w w Freedom when they once had gotten it’, alongside the errors which other nations m o had made in not sufficiently warding off threats.c to liberty from others’ practice te a 49 g of such arcana. Unsurprisingly, much of hthis material came from Clapmar, and s .a while Nedham still drew from various sectionsw of the work, he recommended not w w the ways in which other regimes could simulatem democracy, but the ways in which o .c democratic and aristocratic regimes couldte preserve themselves against the threat a g 50 h of monarchy. s .a w w In his attempt to avert threatsw to the republic, Nedham returned constantly

m to the danger that liberty mighto become ‘a meer name and shadow’ – language .c te a which comes directly from Clapmar’sg discussion of the nature of simulacra – or h s .a that absolute monarchy mightw lose ‘its own Name’ in the ‘shifting of Forms’ while w w 51 ‘the Thing in it self’ persisted in disguise. Here Nedham’s reading of Clapmar m o appears to be fused with.c the notions of Machiavelli and Tacitus, which fed into te a g h the reason of state traditions which Clapmar drew on, and with Livy’s analysis of .a w early Roman history,w upon which Machiavelli had offered his famous commentary w

m o .c te a g h s 47 .a Mercuriusw Politicus 94 (18–25 March 1652), p. 1474. w 48 w

Mercuriusm Politicus 101 (6–13 May 1652), pp. 1585–6. o 49 .c Mercuriuste Politicus 102 (13–20 May 1652), p. 1593. a g 50 h Mercuriuss Politicus 101, pp. 1586, 1588–9; 102, p. 1594; cf. Clapmar, De Arcanis, .a w pp. 82–3w (aristocratic arcana), 88–90 (democratic arcana). w 51 m o Mercurius Politicus 110 (8–15 July 1652), p. 1725; cf. Clapmar, De Arcanis, pp. .c te 284–5;a Mercurius Politicus 100 (29 April–6 May 1652), p. 1570. Joad Raymond, ‘The g h Kings Is a Thing’, in Graham Parry and Joad Raymond (eds), Milton and the Terms of .a w w Libertyw (Cambridge, 2002), pp. 69–94. © Copyrighted Material Marchamont Nedham and Mystery of State 61 © Copyrighted Material

52 in the Discorsi. His view of a political world full of disguises was not purely them o .c te creation of the German mystery of state tradition. How to operate in that worlda g h s was the key question, to which Machiavelli and subsequent writers had offereda . w w slightly differing answers. Nedham had a double strategy, of exposing thew arcana

m of monarchy and domination while exploiting the arcana of successful resistanceo .c te a against the return of monarchy. But how far did the German tradition ofg the arcana h s .a shape Nedham’s view of political morality, and how far could the requirementsw of w w the state – or of a free state – justify the exploitation of the tricks of the mystery of m o .c state tradition, or its Italian cousin, reason of state? te a g h For all their discussion of apparently amoral strategiess for deceiving .a w and manipulating the ruled, the reason of state and mysteryw of state traditions w

m set themselves in conscious, and sometimes over-protesting,o opposition to .c te Machiavelli. According to Donaldson, the reason of statea authors were always g h 53 s concerned to justify the exercise of reason of state; and.a that meant that categories w w w of morality and divine law could not be sidestepped completely in the name of m o preserving the state or the ruler’s own power. Reason.c of state or the arcana imperii te a g were deviations from human laws and from the ordinaryh prescriptions of morality, s .a but they were deviations in fulfilment of higherw laws. Besold characteristically w w upheld Clapmar’s limits to the arcana – religio,m fides, pudor – against Machiavelli’s o 54 .c willingness to dispense with them. Clapmarte accepted Frachetta’s original a g h distinction between good and bad reason ofs state, adopting Ammirato’s Tacitean .a w term of ‘flagitia’ for the ‘cattiva ragion diw stato’, and devoted a book of his treatise w

55 m to these illegitimate arcana. While othero scholars have emphasized the political .c te a morality already there in the Italian reasong of state writings, Richard Tuck has seen h s this reinforced in Clapmar and Besold.a through a distinctive recombination of the w w w 56 Tacitean tradition with a more conservatively Aristotelian viewpoint. Kenneth m o Schellhase is alone in seeing Clapmar.c as an unapologetic user of Machiavellian te a g 57 principle via his endorsementh of Tacitus. s .a w Nedham’s dependence won these writings points towards a less aggressive w disregard for political moralitym than we might expect from his apparently pre- o .c te existing engagement witha Machiavelli. Yet Nedham shared his contemporaries’ g h s caution about Machiavelli,.a rejecting his counsel on the need to be dishonest in a w w perfidious world as w‘a sad inference, and fit onely for the practice ofItaly where he

m wrot [sic] it’. He drewo a distinction between Machiavelli’s ‘many noble Principles’ .c te a g h s .a 52 w Niccolòw Machiavelli, Discourses on Livy, ed. and trans. Julia Conaway Bondanella w and Peter Bondanellam (Oxford, 1997), pp. 79-80, book I, ch. 25. o 53 .c te Donaldson,a Machiavelli and Mystery of State, pp. 111–12. g 54 h Besold,s De Arcanis, p. 10; Clapmar, De Arcanis, p. 187. .a w 55 w w‘Bad reason of state’; Donaldson, Machiavelli and Mystery of State, pp. 112–13,

m 118–21.o .c 56te a g Richard Tuck, Philosophy and Government (Cambridge, 1993), pp. 124–7. h s 57 .a Kenneth Schellhase, Tacitus in Renaissance Political Thought (Chicago and w w wLondon, 1976), pp. 154–5. © Copyrighted Material 62 European Contexts for English Republicanism © Copyrighted Material of popular liberty and the ‘pernitious sprinklings’ of such cynical policy to be found m 58 o in his work, particularly ‘in that unworthy Book of his entitled The Prince’. Paul.c te a g h Rahe expresses surprise that Nedham, who had ‘long championed raison d’état’,s .a w should ‘shy away’ from recommending Machiavelli’s political techniques alongsidew w his republican principles. Smith, too, sees Nedham’s repudiation of Machiavellim o .c te in Certain Considerations as disingenuous in a thoroughly Machiavelliana text. g h s Yet the sentiments which Rahe quotes from Nedham’s Excellency of.a a Free State w w (already expressed in Mercurius Politicus) are precisely those ofw the reason of

m o state/mystery of state tradition, rejecting ‘that reason of state’ which.c arises from te a the statesman’s personal ambition, will and lust, while acceptingg some elements h s 59 .a of the reason of state tradition. Theorists of reason or arcanaw of state insisted w w that – although the ruler’s survival was a legitimate aim, alongside the survival of m o .c the form of government – the ultimate end for which (legitimate)te reason of state a g h was practised was the good of the state and not the ruler’ss private good. Nedham’s .a w concern for effective political technique, not tied in exceptionalw times to ordinary w

m courses (as he argues at the end of the Case of the Commonwealtho ) might still be .c te 60 tempered by an ethical sense of what the ultimate endsa of these actions were. g h s In one sense, Nedham’s use of the German authors.a on mystery of state places w w w him exactly where we knew he was already – in the reason of state tradition, as a m o sharp calculator of political rationality attracted.c to new theories of the operation te a g of interest in politics. But it also casts a newh light on these allegiances, showing – s .a both in his alignment with the mystery of statew material and his divergences from it w w

– something of his political assumptionsm as well as his constitutional preferences. o .c Nedham was deeply influenced by thiste tradition, but he exploited its conventions a g h and assumptions rather than being bounds by them. He was, of course, personally .a w w involved in the exercise of these wpolitical arcana as a paid propagandist. He had

m read the textbook, but he proceededo both to copy from it and to play with it. .c te a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h s .a w w w

m o .c te a g h s .a 58 w wMercurius Politicus 112 (22–29 July 1652), pp. 1753–4; 113 (29 July–5 August w

1652),m p. 1769. o 59.c te Rahe, Against Throne and Altar, p. 243; Smith, Literature and Revolution, p. 34; a g h Mercuriuss Politicus 108 (24 June–1 July 1652), p. 1690; Besold, De Arcanis, pp. 9–13. .a w 60 w w Nedham, Case of the Commonwealth, ed. Knachel, pp. 126–7. © Copyrighted Material