Neostoic Anger: Lipsius's Reading and Use of Seneca's Tragedies And

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Neostoic Anger: Lipsius's Reading and Use of Seneca's Tragedies And Chapter 5 Neostoic Anger: Lipsius’s Reading and Use of Seneca’s Tragedies and De ira Jan Papy Quid ratio possit? Vicit ac regnat furor, potensque tota mente dominatur deus. What can reason do? Passion’s conquered and reigns, And a potent god commands my whole heart. Seneca, Phaedra, 184–185 The Roman Stoic Seneca was omnipresent in the humanist Justus Lipsius’s scholarly career and life.1 This life was situated in the middle of the terrors of the religious wars which tore Europe apart; this life was traumatized by the civil unrest and Spanish rule in the Low Countries.2 In Lipsius’s time death was arbitrary, freedom of speech unthinkable, fear and anger daily experi- ence. Stoicism, that philosophy always looked for in periods of crisis, was, so Lipsius argued, the welcome therapy and remedy.3 Seneca’s dramas and prose works staged death and how to face it courageously while, if possible, even strengthening one’s ability to maintain one’s consistent self-command when facing fate’s adversities and calamities. 1 Morford M., Stoics and Neostoics: Rubens and the Circle of Lipsius (Princeton: 1991) 139–80; Lagrée J., Juste Lipse et la restauration du stoïcisme. Étude et traduction des traités stoïciens De la constance, Manuel de philosophie stoïcienne, Physique des stoïciens (extraits) (Paris: 1994). 2 See, for instance, The World of Justus Lipsius: A Contribution Towards his Intellectual Biography, ed. M. Laureys et al. (= Bulletin de l’Institut historique belge de Rome 68 [1998]); Mouchel C. (ed.), Juste Lipse (1547–1606) en son temps (Paris: 1996). 3 Papy J., “Virtue and Doctrine: Justus Lipsius’s Humanist Programme”, Annales Societatis Litterarum Humaniorum Regiae Upsaliensis—Kungliga Humanistiska Vetenskaps-Samfundets i Uppsala Årsbok 1998 (1999) 197–215; De Bom E. et al. (eds.), (Un)masking the Realities of Power: Justus Lipsius’s Monita et exempla politica and the Dynamics of Political Writing in Early-Modern Europe (Leiden – Boston: 2011). © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, ���5 | doi ��.��63/9789004300835_006 NEOSTOIC ANGER: LIPSIUS’S READING AND USE OF SENECA 127 Besides, in Lipsius’s view the Stoic recipe was not only welcome, it was also simple yet demanding. The individual had to train the Self in order to overcome emotional reactions by the power of reason (ratio). Simultaneously, everyone had to teach that nothing beyond our control, including death, wealth and sickness, is evil or good in se. Moral choices are good or bad, and the only aim of Stoic philosophy is to develop virtue (virtus), including steadfastness, cour- age, goodness. The key to happiness, so Lipsius followed the Stoic doctrine, is obedience to reason, not passion. Maintaining dignity and strength of spirit under oppression, facing death as the ultimate guarantee of liberty: this was the Stoic wise man’s path of true virtue.4 Conversely, when reading Seneca’s “revenge dramas”, Lipsius could not but notice that passions and power corrupt and blind.5 Often, kingship trumps moral considerations, pursuits revenge and spreads terror. Tragic heroes and kings, victim to their passions, seek power and control over others while forget- ting Oedipus’s lines: “I abandoned the kingship gladly, but I keep the kingship over myself”.6 Yet, if the development of an internalised ability to eliminate passions was of central concern to Stoic philosophy and if the devastating effects of out-of-control passions, and especially furor or irrational savagery, have been visualised by Seneca in titanic figures of insatiable appetite for conquest and destruction,7 Lipsius could read the most extensive reflection on self-shaping and self-control in Seneca’s dialogue De ira (On Anger).8 In this dialogue, addressed to his brother Novatus, the provincial governor with virtually unlimited power over non-citizens in his jurisdiction, Seneca called for judgement (iudicium) and careful decisions (arbitria), especially when provocations might elicit over-reactions, while advocating a therapeutic 4 Morford M., “ ‘Theatrum Hodiernae Vitae’: Lipsius, Vaenius and the Rebellion of Civilis”, in Enenkel K. et al. (eds.), Recreating Ancient History: Episodes from the Greek and Roman Past in the Arts and Literatures of the Early Modern Period, (Leiden – Boston – Cologne: 2001) 57–74. On Stoic rationality and the good life, see Inwood B., Ethics and Human Action in Early Stoicism (Oxford: 1985). 5 Schiesaro A., “Passion, Reason, and Knowledge in Seneca’s Tragedies”, in Braund S.M. – Gill C. (eds.), The Passions in Roman Thought and Literature (Cambridge: 1997) 89–111; Id., The Passions in Play: “Thyestes” and the Dynamics of Senecan Drama (Cambridge: 2003); Pypłacz J., The Aesthetics of Senecan Tragedy (Kraków: 2010) 9–13; Winter K., Artificia mali: das Böse als Kunstwerk in Senecas Rachetragödien (Heidelberg: 2014). 6 Seneca, Phoenissae, vv. 104–5: “regna deserui libens; / Regnum mei retineo.” 7 Braden G., Renaissance Tragedy and the Senecan Tradition: Anger’s Privilege (New Haven – London: 1985) 28. 8 Cupaoiolo G., Introduzione al De ira di Seneca (Naples: 1975)..
Recommended publications
  • Commentary on Englert Martha Nussbaum I Admire Englert's
    Commentary on Englert Martha Nussbaum I admire Englert's paper. I find its major conclusions entirely convincing: (1) the analysis of the difference between Epicurean and Stoic attitudes to suicide; (2) the account of the original Stoic position; (3) the argument that Seneca is an orthodox Stoic about suicide; and (4) the very interesting claims about the role of dif- ferent sorts of freedom in Seneca's arguments. Although I am persuaded by his analysis, I am inclined to be somewhat more critical of the Stoic position than he seems inclined to be: for I think that in a crucial way it is internally incoherent. In what follows, therefore, I want to focus on a problem in the Stoic account itself, with respect to the ambivalence the suicide theory reveals toward the importance of externals. I shall do this by focusing on one line of argument leading to suicide, in Seneca's De Ira.l 1. The Stoics famously hold that only virtue is worth choosing for its own sake. And virtue all by itself suffices for a complete- ly fulfilled and fulfilling human life, that is, for eudaimonia. Virtue is something unaffected by external contingency—both, apparently, as to its acquisition and as to its maintenance once acquired? Items that are not fully under the control of the 1. My interpretation of this work is developed at greater length in Nussbaum 1994. My general account of Stoic virtue theory and its relationship to the call for the extirpation of passion is in chapter 10, my detailed analysis of the argu- ments about anger in the De Ira in chapter 11.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Seneca
    03/05/2017 Seneca (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Seneca First published Wed Oct 17, 2007; substantive revision Thu Dec 24, 2015 Seneca is a major philosophical figure of the Roman Imperial Period. As a Stoic philosopher writing in Latin, Seneca makes a lasting contribution to Stoicism. He occupies a central place in the literature on Stoicism at the time, and shapes the understanding of Stoic thought that later generations were to have. Seneca's philosophical works played a large role in the revival of Stoic ideas in the Renaissance. Until today, many readers approach Stoic philosophy through Seneca, rather than through the more fragmentary evidence that we have for earlier Stoics. Seneca's writings are stunningly diverse in their generic range. More than that, Seneca develops further and shapes several philosophical genres, most important, the letter and so­called “consolations”; his essay On Mercy is considered the first example of what came to be known as the “mirror of the prince” literature. After several centuries of relative neglect, Seneca's philosophy has been rediscovered in the last few decades, in what might be called a second revival of Senecan thought. In part, this renewed interest is the result of a general reappraisal of Roman culture. It is also fuelled by major progress that has been made in our understanding of Greek Hellenistic philosophy, and by recent developments in contemporary ethics, such as a renewed interest in the theory of emotions, roles and relationships, and the fellowship of all human beings. And finally, some influential scholars have found, in the wake of Foucault's reading of Seneca, that Seneca speaks to some distinctively modern concerns.
    [Show full text]
  • De Otio De Brevitate Vitae
    SENECA DE OTIO DE BREVITATE VITAE G. D. WILLIAMS Associate Professor of Classics, Columbia University, New York The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge , United Kingdom The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge, ,UK West th Street, New York, -, USA Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, , Australia Ruiz de Alarc´on , Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town , South Africa http://www.cambridge.org C Cambridge University Press This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typefaces Baskerville / pt and New Hellenic System LATEX ε [] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library hardback paperback CONTENTS Preface page vii Conventions and abbreviations viii Introduction Author and date: initial problems The Dialogues in context (a) The Stoicbackground (b) The Roman philosophical tradition (c) From Republicto Empire De otio (a) The view from above (b) Date, addressee and related problems De breuitate uitae (a) Preliminaries (b) Date and addressee (c) Theme and interpretation Style and language (a) Senecan style: context and general tendency (b) Senecan mannerism, vocabulary, wordplay The transmission of the text L. ANNAEI SENECAE DE OTIO; DE BREVITATE VITAE Commentary Bibliography Indexes General Latin words Greek words v INTRODUCTION . AUTHOR AND DATE: INITIAL PROBLEMS Born into a provincial equestrian family of Italian extraction at Corduba (modern C´ordoba) in southern Spain, Lucius Annaeus Seneca (c. – ) wasraisedand educated from an early age at Rome.
    [Show full text]
  • Discovering Romanity in Seneca's De Otio and De Brevitate Vitae Joshua Dean Wimmer [email protected]
    Marshall University Marshall Digital Scholar Theses, Dissertations and Capstones 1-1-2012 Lend Me Your Voice: Discovering Romanity in Seneca's De otio and De brevitate vitae Joshua Dean Wimmer [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://mds.marshall.edu/etd Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons Recommended Citation Wimmer, Joshua Dean, "Lend Me Your Voice: Discovering Romanity in Seneca's De otio and De brevitate vitae" (2012). Theses, Dissertations and Capstones. Paper 255. This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Marshall Digital Scholar. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses, Dissertations and Capstones by an authorized administrator of Marshall Digital Scholar. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LEND ME YOUR VOICE: DISCOVERING ROMANITY IN SENECA’S DE OTIO AND DE BREVITATE VITAE A Thesis submitted to the Graduate College of Marshall University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Latin by Joshua Dean Wimmer Approved by Dr. E. Del Chrol, Committee Chairperson Dr. Caroline Perkins Dr. Christina Franzen Marshall University May 2012 Copyright by Joshua Dean Wimmer 2012 ii Dedication and Acknowledgments DEDICATION Pro parentibus meis ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would sincerely like to extend my most deeply felt gratitude to Dr. E. Del Chrol, Dr. Caroline Perkins, and Dr. Christina Franzen of the Department of Classics at Marshall University, as well as to any and to all who have helped in some way, no
    [Show full text]
  • Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1947 Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters Robert James Koehn Loyola University Chicago Recommended Citation Koehn, Robert James, "Seneca's Concept of a Supreme Being in His Philosophical Essays and Letters" (1947). Master's Theses. Paper 641. http://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/641 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1947 Robert James Koehn SENECA'S CONCEPT OF A SUPRE.'ME BEING IN HIS PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS AND LETTERS BY ROBERT J. KOEHN, S.J. A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF ~qE REQUIREMENTS FOR A MASTER OF ARTS DEGREE IN THE CLASSICS AUGUST 1947 VITA AUCTORIS Robert James Koehn was born in Toledo, Ohio, on September 2, 1917. After attending St. James parochial school, he entered st. John's High School in September 1931. Upon his graduation in 1935 he attended St. John's and DeSales Colleges before entering the So­ ciety of Jesus on September 1, 1937. He matriculated at Xavier University, Cincinnati, and received a Bachelor of Li­ terature degree in June 1941. Following his transfer to West Baden College, West Baden Springs, Indiana, in the summer of 1941, he entered the graduate school of Loyola Uni­ versity, Chicago, in the Classics.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism a School of Thought That Flourished in Greek and Roman
    Stoicism A school of thought that flourished in Greek and Roman antiquity. It was one of the loftiest and most sublime philosophies in the record of Western civilization. In urging participation in the affairs of man, Stoics have always believed that the goal of all inquiry is to provide man with a mode of conduct characterized by tranquillity of mind and certainty of moral worth. Nature and scope of Stoicism For the early Stoic philosopher, as for all the post-Aristotelian schools, knowledge and its pursuit are no longer held to be ends in themselves. The Hellenistic Age was a time of transition, and the Stoic philosopher was perhaps its most influential spokesman. A new culture was in the making. The heritage of an earlier period, with Athens as its intellectual leader, was to continue, but to undergo many changes. If, as with Socrates, to know is to know oneself, rationality as the sole means by which something outside of the self might be achieved may be said to be the hallmark of Stoic belief. As a Hellenistic philosophy, Stoicism presented an ars vitae, a way of accommodation for people to whom the human condition no longer appeared as the mirror of a universal, calm, and ordered existence. Reason alone could reveal the constancy of cosmic order and the originative source of unyielding value; thus, reason became the true model for human existence. To the Stoic, virtue is an inherent feature of the world, no less inexorable in relation to man than are the laws of nature. The Stoics believed that perception is the basis of true knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Impulse and Animal Action in Stoic Psychology
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1996 Impulse and Animal Action in Stoic Psychology John A. Stevens East Carolina University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Stevens, John A., "Impulse and Animal Action in Stoic Psychology" (1996). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 204. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/204 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. Impulse and Animal Action in Stoic Psychology John A. Stevens East Carolina University There is contradictory evidence on the cause of impulse, op μη , in Stoic psychology. Sources clearly indicate that impulse cannot occur without assent, συγκατάθεσή (Plut. D e Stoic, rep. 1057A = SV F 3.175) and that impulses are assents (Stob. E e l 2.88.1-6= SV F 3.171). But other sources indicate that the actual cause of impulse is not assent but impression, φ α ν τα σ ία (Stob. Eel. 2.86.17-18 =SVF 3.169), “They (the Stoics) say that what moves an impulse is nothing other than an hormetic impression of something that is self-evidently appropriate.” 1 Some texts openly suggest that impulse may precede assent (Plut.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reading of Porphyry's on Abstinence From
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Justice Purity Piety: A Reading of Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Classics by Alexander Press 2020 © Copyright by Alexander Press 2020 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Justice Purity Piety: A Reading of Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings by Alexander Press Doctor of Philosophy in Classics University of California, Los Angeles, 2020 Professor David Blank, Chair Abstract: Presenting a range of arguments against meat-eating, many strikingly familiar, Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings (Greek Περὶ ἀποχῆς ἐµψύχων, Latin De abstinentia ab esu animalium) offers a sweeping view of the ancient debate concerning animals and their treatment. At the same time, because of its advocacy of an asceticism informed by its author’s Neoplatonism, Abstinence is often taken to be concerned primarily with the health of the human soul. By approaching Abstinence as a work of moral suasion and a work of literature, whose intra- and intertextual resonances yield something more than a collection of propositions or an invitation to Quellenforschung, I aim to push beyond interpretations that bracket the arguments regarding animals as merely dialectical; cast the text’s other-directed principle of justice as wholly ii subordinated to a self-directed principle of purity; or accept as decisive Porphyry’s exclusion of craftsmen, athletes, soldiers, sailors, and orators from his call to vegetarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Mastery This Emphasis Is Not Exclusive of Social Responsibility and Concern
    University of Alberta Stoicism, Moral Education and Material Goods by David Patrick Burns A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theoretical, Cultural and International Studies in Education Department of Educational Policy Studies ©David Patrick Burns Spring 2011 Edmonton, Alberta Permission is hereby granted to the University of Alberta Libraries to reproduce single copies of this thesis and to lend or sell such copies for private, scholarly or scientific research purposes only. Where the thesis is converted to, or otherwise made available in digital form, the University of Alberta will advise potential users of the thesis of these terms. The author reserves all other publication and other rights in association with the copyright in the thesis and, except as herein before provided, neither the thesis nor any substantial portion thereof may be printed or otherwise reproduced in any material form whatsoever without the author's prior written permission. To my loving wife, thank you. ABSTRACT Material goods play an important role in ethical life and moral education. Judging which goods are preferable to which − and which are therefore worth pursuing over which − is an ethically crucial process. The currently dominant paradigms of moral education (virtue education, cognitive developmentalism and care theory) do not satisfactorily contribute to this important topic. I argue that the resultant lacuna may be resolved by attending to the insight of the classical Stoics and their modern day neo‐Stoic interpreters. Stoicism, I argue, provides a unique set of philosophical resources that fosters critical deliberation and reflection regarding the attribution of value to material goods.
    [Show full text]
  • Part 1 Anger Management in Early Modern Philosophical Discourses
    Part 1 Anger Management in Early Modern Philosophical Discourses ∵ Chapter 3 Neo-Stoicism as an Antidote to Public Violence before Lipsius’s De constantia: Johann Weyer’s (Wier’s) Anger Therapy, De ira morbo (1577) Karl A.E. Enenkel Among the works of Johann Weyer (Wier, Piscinarius; 1515/1516–1588), court physician to Wilhelm the Rich, 5th Duke of Cleve, Jülich, and Berg,1 occurs a most intriguing treatise, De ira morbo, eiusdem curatione philosophica, medic- ina et theologica—On the Disease (Kranckheit) of Anger, and its Philosophical, Medical, and Theological Therapy, which appeared in 1577.2 Weyer intended to 1 Johann Weyer served Wilhelm the Rich as court physician from 1555 onward until his well- deserved retirement in 1578. For Weyer’s biography cf. Hoorens V., Een ketterse arts voor de heksen. Jan Wier (1515–1588) (Amsterdam: 2011); Binz C., Doctor Johann Weyer, ein rheinischer Arzt, der erste Bekämpfer des Hexenwahns (1st ed. Bonn: 1885 [Zeitschrift des Bergischen Geschichtsvereins 21]; 2nd ed. Berlin: 1896; reprint of the 2nd ed. Wiesbaden: 1969, and New York: 1975); Meyer Th., “Weyer, Johann”, Biographisch-Bibliographisches Kirchenlexikon 20 (2002) cols. 1537–1544. Thus far, Weyer has become known in scholarly discussions almost exclusively with respect to his treatise on witches (De praestigiis daemonum [. .] [ed. pr. Basel, Johannes Oporinus: 1563); cf., inter alia, the above-quoted works, and Nahl R. van, Zauberglaube und Hexenwahn im Gebiet von Rhein und Maas. Spätmittelalterlicher Volksglaube im Werk Johan Weyers (1515–1588) (Bonn: 1983); Mora G. et al., Witches, Devils, and Doctors in the Renaissance: Johann Weyer, “De praestigiis daemonum”, Medieval & Renaissance Texts & Studies 73 (Binghamton, N.Y.: 1991); Cobben J.J., Duivelse bezetenheid, beschreven door dok- ter Johannes Wier, 1515–1588 (Rotterdam: 2002); Gunnoe Ch.D., “The Debate between Johann Weyer and Thomas Erastus on the Punishment of Witches”, in Van Horn Melton J.
    [Show full text]
  • A Comparative Study of Anger in Antiquity and Christian Thought
    Journal of Ethics in Antiquity and Christianity Susan Wessel JEAC 2 (2020) Article A Comparative Study of Anger in Antiquity and Christian Thought Susan Wessel Catholic University of America Washington, DC 20064 USA DOI 10.25784/jeac.v2i0.290 Abstract Among the ancient philosophers and the early Christians, anger was understood along a continuum. Aristotle and Philo- demus believed that anger, under the right conditions, could be useful and even advantageous. Some such as Seneca and Clement, refused the possibility of any sort of anger among the most enlightened, whereas Evagrius and Cassian permit anger that is expressed toward oneself for any perceived vices. Gregory of Nyssa believed that with ascetic training, anger could be transformed into the virtue of courage. Similar to Plutarch, John Chrysostom believed that anger is an expression of social tyranny and must be curbed for virtue to thrive. Tertullian is distinct for understanding anger in the context of the faith and the patience that the advent of Christ made come alive. Left uncontrolled, anger is a spiritual deception that negates the new law of Christ. Plutarch, Lactantius, and Augustine, in contrast, admit a righteous form of anger under certain conditions. In the ancient world, philosophers disagreed concerning to the steady operation of reason that is supposed to guide the the value of anger for the moral life. Some, such as Aristotle, philosopher’s mind. “[With anger], the mind is driven by believed that anger could be useful in motivating people to none more frantic nor susceptible to its own power, and, if it undertake courageous actions that might have eluded them succeeds, by none more arrogant, or, if it fails, by none more otherwise.
    [Show full text]