The Cambridge Companion to Newton Edited by I

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Cambridge Companion to Newton Edited by I Cambridge University Press 0521651778 - The Cambridge Companion to Newton Edited by I. Bernard Cohen and George E. Smith Index More information index Abb´e Conti, 450, 456, 459 optics and, 235, 238–45 abduction, 161 refraction and, 235 aberration, 212–13 Alchemist, The (Jonson), 25 absolute motion, 33–6, 174; see also alchemy, 11–12, 17, 23, 27–9, 316, motion 382–6, 390 absolute quantity, 64 composition theory and, 372–4 absolute space, 33–6, 40–1, 174; see also criticism of, 25–6 space Maier and, 374–81 absolute time, 40–1 Newton’s manuscripts and, 370–1 controversies over, 33–6, 174 prisca sapientia, 370–1, 374–5 Newton’s context and, 36–8 religion and, 24, 378–81 see also time see also chemistry acceleration, 12, 64 algebra, 11, 309, 311, 323 absolute time/space and, 40–1 ancient wisdom and, 433–4 conic motion and, 93–5 attacks on, 317 great inequality and, 215–17 geometry and, 431–2, 439–40 harmonic rule and, 180 Newton vs. Leibniz and, 439–40 impulsive to continuous forces and, see also mathematics 74–5 Analyse des infiniment petits mathematical to physical (L’Hospital), 322 characterization and, 153 Analysis per Quantitatum Series, unification of Moon and, 183–4 Fluxiones et Differentias (Jones), Account of Sir Isaac Newton’s 444 Philosophical Discoveries, An analysis, see dynamic analysis (Maclaurin), 329, 348–9 Analyst, The (Berkeley), 22 Account of the Commercium ancient wisdom, 370–1, 374 Epistolicum (Newton), 324 algebra and, 433–4 Achmet, 401 Rosicrucianism and, 375–81 Acta Eruditorum, 435, 440–1, 444–5, 450 angular momentum, 121 action at a distance, 152 Antichrist, 393–5 Act of Uniformity, 421 antimony, 363 Adams, J. C., 221–2 aphelia, 178–80 ad hoc reasoning, 158 Apocalypse, 387, 390, 421 aether, 207–8 argument from design and, 391–2 mechanical philosophy and, 340–2, construction of, 393 344 experimentalism and, 396–400 481 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521651778 - The Cambridge Companion to Newton Edited by I. Bernard Cohen and George E. Smith Index More information 482 Index Apocalypse (cont.) atomism interpretive rules of, 396–400 color and, 245–9 methodization of, 391–6 hypothesis and, 250–1 apogee, 210–11 see also optics curvature method of computation, 100–6 Bacon, Francis, 1, 3 Apollonius, 309, 324 ballistics, 450 approximations, 157–8, 161–3 Barrow, Isaac, 10–11, 311, 315, 432 Archbishop Sharp, 422 Barton, Catherine, 13 Archbishop Tenison, 422 Beast of the Apocalypse, 394 Archimedes, 309 Bedford, Arthur, 411–12 area law, see Kepler’s area law Bentley, Richard, 417, 419, 448 arguing more securely, 141, 150, 160–7 Berkeley, George, 1, 22–3, 334, 417 Arianism, 412, 414–15, 417 absolute space/time and, 33, 46 Aristotle, 1–3, 10, 60, 204, 334 metaphysics and, 331, 335 Arithmetica Infinitorium (Wallis), 311 Bernoulli, Jakob, 437 Arithmetica Universalis (Newton), Bernoulli, Johann, 322 318–19, 432 Charta Volans and, 445 Arius, 23 Leibniz controversy and, 431, 435, Arnauld, Antoine, 1, 456 437, 439, 443–4, 450 astrology, 23 reconciliation of, 450–1 Astronomia Britannica (Wing), 205–6 Bernoulli, Nikolaus, 444 Astronomia Carolina (Streete), 205 Beveridge, William, 412 Astronomia Nova (Kepler), 202–3 biblical studies, 11, 28 Astronomia Philolaica (Boulliau), 204–5 Antichrist, 393–5 astronomy, 15, 330 Book of Daniel, 24, 387–8, 394, 412, aberration and, 212–13 414–15, 419, 421–2 aether and, 207–8, 235, 238–45, 340–2, Book of Nature, 323 344 Book of Revelation, 24, 387, 390–400, Earth, 81; see also Earth 421 geometry and, 317–18; see also correct philosophy and, 390 geometry; Kepler’s area law corruption of scripture and, 409–10, great inequality and, 215–17 419 group effort of, 15 False Prophet, 394 Jupiter and, 153; see also Jupiter Genesis, 387 lunar apse and, 213–15 idolatry, 420 Moon-test and, 182–3; see also Moon infant baptism, 420 Mercury and, 194, 206, 222–3 I John 5:7, 409–10, 419, 421–3 Newton’s place in, 7–8 Joshua, 457–8 planetary motion and, 193–4; see also literalism and, 420–1 planetary motion Mace and, 409 reflecting telescope and, 11 monotheism and, 378 Sun and, 203–5; see also Sun Moses, 410–11 uniform circular motion and, 86–93, prophecy and, 387–405 143–4 rejection of Trinity, 10–11, 23–4, van Schooten and, 310–11 409–10, 412–15, 419–23 see also celestial mechanics; orbital Rosicrucianism and, 376 motion I Timothy 3:16, 409–10, 419, 421–2 Atalanta Fugiens (Maier), 24 truth and, 390–1 Athanasius, 394 understanding and, 392 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521651778 - The Cambridge Companion to Newton Edited by I. Bernard Cohen and George E. Smith Index More information Index 483 universal law and, 371 lunar motion and, 120–4, 213–15 Whore of Babylon, 394 Newton vs. Leibniz and, 13–14, 432, see also God 439–40, 445–7 binomial theorem, 312 “Quadrature” and, 439 Bishop Lloyd, 422 resistance forces and, 118–20 Book of Daniel, 24, 387–8, 394 see also mathematics eighteenth-century Christianity and, Cambridge, 9–13 412, 414–15, 419, 421–2 Caroline, Princess of Wales, 411, prophecy of Seventy Weeks and, 412, 448–9 419, 422 Leibniz–Clarke correspondence and, Book of Nature, 323 455–63 Book of Revelation, 24, 421 Cartesian ovals, 237 Apocalypse and, 387, 390–400 Case, Thomas, 256 bootstrapping, 174 Castelli, Benedetto, 457 Borelli, G. A., 15, 435 Catholic Church, 415–16, 420, 422 Boscaglia, Cosimo, 457–8 causal interactions, 37 Bouillau, Ishmael,¨ 15, 152, 179, 204–5 absolute time/space and, 38–49 Boyle, Robert, 16, 25, 338 gravity and, 152 alchemy and, 26 greater certainty and, 228 chemistry and, 359–60, 363 Kepler and, 204 density and, 59 Caussin, Nicolas, 401 theft and, 445 celestial circularity, 86 Brackenridge, J. Bruce, xi, 6, 85–137 celestial mechanics, 224–6 Bradley, James, 212–13, 217 aberration and, 212–13 Brahe, Tycho, 15–16 aether and, 207–8; see also aether absolute time/space and, 37 comets and, 208, 218–20, 222 accuracy of data and, 152–3 Earth’s figure and, 220–1 harmonic rule and, 178–80 gravitation theory limitations and, lunar motion and, 120–1 221–3 mathematical to physical harmonic rule and, 206–10 characterization and, 156 inverse-square law and, 213–15 puffy-cheeked orbit and, 203 Jupiter/Saturn inequality and, Brewster, David, 25, 442–3 215–17 bright-idea myth, 6–8 Kepler’s laws and, 202–10 British Board of Admiralty, 217 Moon and, 213–18; see also Moon Brown, Ernest W., 223 nutation and, 212–13 Buffon, Comte de, 439 precession and, 212–13 Bur, 360 problem of the tides and, 220–1 Burckhardt, Johann Karl, 218 vortices and, 205–7 Burg, Johann Tobias, 218 see also astronomy Burnet, Thomas, 366 Celestial Mechanics (Laplace), 7, 217 Burnet, William, 442 center of force, 12, 125 conic motion and, 93–5 Cabalieri, Bonaventura, 311 curvature method and, 100–6 Cadmus, 379 early computational methods and, Cajori, Florian, 207 95–106 calculus, 10–11, 21, 117, 388–9 harmonic rule and, 206–7 Charta Volans and, 445–6 Kepler’s area law and, 107–10 dynamic analysis and, 313–16, spiral motion and, 96 319–20, 324 uniform circular motion and, 87–93 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521651778 - The Cambridge Companion to Newton Edited by I. Bernard Cohen and George E. Smith Index More information 484 Index centrifugal force, 88–9 Chymical Lectures (Freind), 441 absolute time/space and, 44–5 circular motion, see orbital motion curvature method and, 100–6 Civil War, 9 Huygens and, 145, 206 Clairaut, Alexis-Claude, 158, 167 centripetal force, 6, 12, 57, 62–3 comets and, 219–20 First Law of Motion and, 64–5 Earth’s figure and, 220 harmonic rule and, 180 lunar motion and, 213–15, 217 induction and, 187–9 Clarke, Samuel infinitesimals and, 75–8 Leibniz correspondence and, 455–63 mathematical to physical Newton vs. Leibniz and, 448–50 characterization and, 153 religion and, 411–13, 417, 422–3 Newtonian style and, 144, 148, 156 “Clavis,” 24–5 theory-mediated measurement and, Clavis Apocaliptica (Mede), 387 144 Clavis Mathematicae (Oughtred), 311 three measures of, 64 cogitatio caeca, 325 unification of Moon and, 181–5 Cohen, I. Bernard, xi, 1–32, 57–84, 154 Chambers, Ephraim, 29 Collins, John, 11, 14, 311, 442 Charles II, 9 collisions, 87–93 Charleton, Walter, 16 color, 10–11, 389 Charta Volans, 445–6 aether and, 238–45 Chaucer, Geoffrey, 25 atomism and, 245–9 chemistry, 11–12, 17, 24, 358–60, 368–9 Hooke’s objections and, 400 corpuscularism and, 363–7 reflection and, 230 Helmontian matter-theory and, 361–3 refraction and, 230, 237 Paracelsian principles and, 362 theory of, 229–32 vitriol and, 361 see also optics see also alchemy Comet Encke, 222 Chevalier Ramsay, 413 Comet Halley, 208, 222 Cheyne, George, 438, 441 comets, 208, 218–20, 222 Christianity, 394, 424–30 Commandino, Federico, 308 anti-Catholicism and, 415–16 Commercium Epistolicum, 324, 442–4, Bedford and, 411–12 450–1 Berkeley and, 417 common analysis, 312; see also dynamic Chronology and, 411 analysis Greek Fathers and, 416 composition theory, 372–4 historical accuracy and, 412 Conclusio (Newton), 360 Hutchinsonians and, 418–19 Conduitt, John, 13 literalism and, 420–1 conic motion, 93–5, 208 Moses and, 410–11 Conics (Appolonius), 324 Observations and, 409–10 continuous forces rejection of Trinity and, 10–11, 23–4, First Law of Motion and, 64–5 409–10, 412–15, 419–23 impulsive forces and, 70–5 Shuckford and, 416–17 controversies, 11–12 Warburton and, 416–17 Commercium Epistolicum and, 442–4 Whiston and, 412–13 gravity and, 174–5 see also biblical studies Leibniz and, 455–63; see also Leibniz, Chronology of Ancient Kingdom’s Gottfried Wilhelm Amended, The (Newton), 411, 417 Observations and, 409–10 Church of England, 10, 411, 414, 417, publishing dates, 439–41 420, 422–3 religious, 412; see also Christianity © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 0521651778 - The Cambridge Companion to Newton Edited by I.
Recommended publications
  • Newton.Indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag
    omslag Newton.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag. 1 e Dutch Republic proved ‘A new light on several to be extremely receptive to major gures involved in the groundbreaking ideas of Newton Isaac Newton (–). the reception of Newton’s Dutch scholars such as Willem work.’ and the Netherlands Jacob ’s Gravesande and Petrus Prof. Bert Theunissen, Newton the Netherlands and van Musschenbroek played a Utrecht University crucial role in the adaption and How Isaac Newton was Fashioned dissemination of Newton’s work, ‘is book provides an in the Dutch Republic not only in the Netherlands important contribution to but also in the rest of Europe. EDITED BY ERIC JORINK In the course of the eighteenth the study of the European AND AD MAAS century, Newton’s ideas (in Enlightenment with new dierent guises and interpre- insights in the circulation tations) became a veritable hype in Dutch society. In Newton of knowledge.’ and the Netherlands Newton’s Prof. Frans van Lunteren, sudden success is analyzed in Leiden University great depth and put into a new perspective. Ad Maas is curator at the Museum Boerhaave, Leiden, the Netherlands. Eric Jorink is researcher at the Huygens Institute for Netherlands History (Royal Dutch Academy of Arts and Sciences). / www.lup.nl LUP Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 1 Newton and the Netherlands Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 2 Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag.
    [Show full text]
  • Reposs #19: Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690–1790
    RePoSS: Research Publications on Science Studies RePoSS #19: Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690–1790 Helge Kragh August 2012 Centre for Science Studies, University of Aarhus, Denmark Research group: History and philosophy of science Please cite this work as: Helge Kragh (Aug. 2012). Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690–1790. RePoSS: Research Publications on Sci- ence Studies 19. Aarhus: Centre for Science Studies, University of Aarhus. url: http://www.css.au.dk/reposs. Copyright c Helge Kragh, 2012 1 Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690-1790 HELGE KRAGH 1 Introduction In the present context, the Scandinavian countries refer to two national or administrative units, the one being Denmark and the other Sweden. In the period here considered, largely the century from 1690 to 1790, ‘Denmark’ means really Denmark-Norway, for until 1814 Norway was part of the double monarchy ruled by the king and his government in Copenhagen. It should also be kept in mind that parts of what is today Germany, namely Schleswig-Holstein, belonged to the kingdom. However, as far as language and culture were concerned, these parts of southern Denmark were more German than Danish, and they played no important role in the scientific life of the kingdom. Sweden covered a much larger geographical area than it does today. The country had expanded greatly during the seventeenth century, when not only Finland but also parts of the Baltic area and northern Germany came under Swedish rule. About 1720, after the Great Northern War, Sweden lost most of its possessions, but the major part of Finland remained as part of the country until Centre for Science Studies, Department of Physics and Astronomy, Aarhus University, Denmark.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Aspects of Thinking of Jakub Kresa for Development of School Mathematics
    Ján GUNČAGA, Katholische Universität in Ružomberok, SK Some aspects of thinking of Jakub Kresa for development of school mathematics This article makes an excursion into the history of mathematics, which is used in school mathematics. We would like to describe some components of mathematical notions developed by Jakub Kresa (1648-1715). We would like to compare his work with another two big mathematicians Isaac Newton (1643 -1727) and René Descartes (1596-1650), because it is pos- sible to see some similarities in topics of their works. Isaac Newton wrote separately arithmetic and algebra in Arithmetica universalis, but in his work Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica he used only geometry. René Descartes integrates the knowledge from algebra, arithmetic and ge- ometry in his work La Geometrie and in a similar way, Jakub Kresa descri- bed the mathematical theory in his work Analysis speciose trigonometriae sphaericae. 1. Introduction Jakub Kresa lived in the time in which arithmetic has geometrical represen- tations. René Descartes wrote in his book La Geometrie that “any problem in geometry can easily be reduced to such terms that a knowledge of the lengths of certain straight lines is sufficient for its construction. Just as arithmetic consisting of only four or five operations, namely, addition, sub- traction, multiplication, division and the extraction of roots.” Now let AB taken as unity (see Figure 1), and let be required to multiply BD by BC. Descartes argues that “I only have to join the points A and C, and draw DE parallel to CA, then BE is the product of BD and BC.
    [Show full text]
  • Isaac Newton on Mathematical Certainty and Method
    Isaac Newton on Mathematical Certainty and Method Niccol`oGuicciardini The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England c 2009 Massachusetts Institute of Technology All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or information storage and re- trieval) without permission in writing from the publisher. For information about special quantity discounts, please email special [email protected] This book was set in Computer Modern by Compomat s.r.l., Configni (RI), Italy. Printed and bound in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Guicciardini, Niccol`o. Isaac Newton on mathematical certainty and method / Niccol`o Guicciardini. p. cm. - (Transformations : studies in the history of science and technology) Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 978-0-262-01317-8 (hardcover : alk. paper) 1. Newton, Isaac, Sir, 1642–1727—Knowledge-Mathematics. 2. Mathematical analy- sis. 3. Mathematics-History. I. Title. QA29.N4 G85 2009 510-dc22 2008053211 10987654321 Index Abbreviations, xxi Andersen, Kirsti, 9, 140 Abel, Niels H., 40–41 Apagogical proofs (in Barrow’s sense), 177 Accountants, 5, 351 Apollonius, xviii, 15, 56, 63, 80, 81, 91, 105, Acerbi, Fabio, xviii, 83, 86, 88, 102 118, 145, 253, 342, 385 Adams, John C., 248, 307, 340, 348 Archimedes, xiii, 65–66, 145, 342 Affected equations, 136, 154, 156, 158, 162, Aristaeus, 81 166, 167, 179, 193, 194, 212, 231, Aristotelian conception of pure and mixed 345, 355, 356, 376 mathematics, 146, 172 Alchemy, 3, 238, 313, 342 Aristotelian inertia, 235 Algebra speciosa, 339 Aristotelian logic, 23 Algebraic curves, 6, 15, 42, 104, 157, 188 Aristotelian substantial forms and occult Algebraic equations qualities, 297 Newton’s method of resolution, 158–164, Aristotelian textbook tradition, 323 179, 355 Aristotle (pseudo) Problemata Mechanica, to be neglected, 256, 266, 289, 311, 344 4 used in common analysis, 5 Arithmetica speciosa, 298 used in the Principia, 259 Arthur, Richard T.
    [Show full text]
  • Transreal Newtonian Physics Operates at Singularities A
    Synesis, v. 7, n. 2, p. 57-81, jul/dez. 2015, ISSN 1984-6754 © Universidade Católica de Petrópolis, Petrópolis, Rio de Janeiro, Brasil TRANSREAL NEWTONIAN PHYSICS OPERATES AT SINGULARITIES A FÍSICA NEWTONIANA TRANSREAL OPERA EM SINGULARIDADES* JAMES A.D.W. ANDERSON SCHOOL OF SYSTEMS ENGINEERING AT READING UNIVERSITY, ENGLAND TIAGO SOARES DOS REIS INSTITUTO FEDERAL DE EDUCAÇÃO, CIÊNCIA E TECNOLOGIA DO RIO DE JANEIRO, BRASIL Abstract: Sir Isaac Newton, writing in Latin, defined his celebrated laws of motion verbally. When the laws of motion are read as relating to his arithmetic (the Arithmetica Universalis) and his calculus (the method of fluxions), division by zero is undefined so his physics fails at mathematical singularities. The situation is unchanged in modern real arithmetic and real calculus: division by zero is undefined so both Newtonian Physics and its modern developments fail at mathematical singularities. However, when Newton’s text is read as relating to transreal arithmetic and transreal calculus, division by zero is defined and we show that the resulting Transreal Newtonian Physics does operate at mathematical singularities. We hold out the hope that the whole of modern physics may be similarly extended. We use the new physics to predict a convection current at the singularity in a black hole and suggest experiments in astronomy and high energy physics that might confirm or rebut our predictions. Thus our exegesis of Newton’s text extends mathematical physics and may, in future, extend experimental physics. Keywords: Transreal numbers; Non-finite force; Newton’s laws of motion. Resumo: Sir Isaac Newton, escrevendo em latim, definiu verbalmente suas célebres leis do movimento.
    [Show full text]
  • The Birth of Calculus: Towards a More Leibnizian View
    The Birth of Calculus: Towards a More Leibnizian View Nicholas Kollerstrom [email protected] We re-evaluate the great Leibniz-Newton calculus debate, exactly three hundred years after it culminated, in 1712. We reflect upon the concept of invention, and to what extent there were indeed two independent inventors of this new mathematical method. We are to a considerable extent agreeing with the mathematics historians Tom Whiteside in the 20th century and Augustus de Morgan in the 19th. By way of introduction we recall two apposite quotations: “After two and a half centuries the Newton-Leibniz disputes continue to inflame the passions. Only the very learned (or the very foolish) dare to enter this great killing- ground of the history of ideas” from Stephen Shapin1 and “When de l’Hôpital, in 1696, published at Paris a treatise so systematic, and so much resembling one of modern times, that it might be used even now, he could find nothing English to quote, except a slight treatise of Craig on quadratures, published in 1693” from Augustus de Morgan 2. Introduction The birth of calculus was experienced as a gradual transition from geometrical to algebraic modes of reasoning, sealing the victory of algebra over geometry around the dawn of the 18 th century. ‘Quadrature’ or the integral calculus had developed first: Kepler had computed how much wine was laid down in his wine-cellar by determining the volume of a wine-barrel, in 1615, 1 which marks a kind of beginning for that calculus. The newly-developing realm of infinitesimal problems was pursued simultaneously in France, Italy and England.
    [Show full text]
  • Newton's Early Unpublished Work in Mechanics I
    THE NEWTONIAN REVOLUTION – Part One Philosophy 167: Science Before Newton’s Principia Class 12 Newton’s Early Unpublished Work in Mechanics November 25, 2014 I. Background: Newton in the 1660s and 1670s ..................................................................................... 1 A. Huygens and the Science of Mechanics ……………...……………..................................... 1 B. Issue: What Difference Did Newton Make? ……….............................................................. 3 C. Newton: A Biographical Sketch (to 1679) ……..................................................................... 4 D. Newton's Work in Mathematics: 1664-1680 ………………………..................................... 6 E. Newton's Work in Optics: 1665-1680 ………………............................................................. 7 F. Newton's Intellectual Style, versus Huygens's ……............................................................... 8 II. Newton's Laws of Motion (vs. Descartes, Huygens) .......................................................................... 10 A. Newton's Conceptualization of the Problem …………………............................................. 10 B. The Principles Governing Angular Motion ………..………………………..……………... 11 C. The General Laws of Reflection on Impact …….….……...….………..………………….. 12 D. Newton's Results Contrasted with Huygens's ……….…….................................................. 13 E. Newton’s Reservations about the Potential for Evidence .................................................... 14 III. Newton on Circular Motion (vs.
    [Show full text]
  • Newton Raphson Method
    Newton Raphson Method Objective: 1. Derive the Newton-Raphson method formula, 2. Develop the algorithm of the Newton-Raphson method, 3. Use the Newton-Raphson method to solve a nonlinear equation (in Power System) Definition: Newton's method (also known as the Newton–Raphson method), named after Isaac Newton and Joseph Raphson, is a method for finding successively better approximations to the roots (or zeroes) of a real-valued function. History: Raphson's most notable work is Analysis Aequationum Universalis, which was published in 1690. It contains a method, now known as the Newton–Raphson method, for approximating the roots of an equation. Isaac Newton had developed a very similar formula in his Method of Fluxions, written in 1671, but this work would not be published until 1736, nearly 50 years after Raphson's Analysis. However, Raphson's version of the method is simpler than Newton's, and is therefore generally considered superior. For this reason, it is Raphson's version of the method, rather than Newton's, that is to be found in textbooks today. Raphson also translated Newton's Arithmetica Universalis into English. Newton’s Method: Faster, requires one initial guess Convergent not always guaranteed, Divergence at inflection points, Division by zero, Oscillations near local maximum and minimum, Intuition behind Newton Raphson Method: The Newton-Raphson method is based on the principle that if the initial guess of the root of ( ) = 0 is at , then if one draws the tangent to the curve at ( ), the point where the tangent crosses the x -axis is an improved estimate of the root.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematics (Class QA)
    LIBRARY OF CONGRESS COLLECTIONS POLICY STATEMENTS Mathematics (Class QA) Contents I. Scope II. Research Strengths III. Collecting Policy IV. Best editions and preferred formats V. Acquisition Sources VI. Collection Levels I. Scope The overall context for this policy is the Library’s position as the de facto national library of the United States. This Collections Policy Statement covers the subclass QA (Mathematics), with exception of major subset, QA75-QA76 (Computer Science), which is addressed in a separate Collections Policy Statement. Since the Library of Congress does not support a specific mathematical study or program, the collection includes a broad overview of titles that reflect the interests of both theoretical and applied mathematicians. Examples of mathematical studies covered under subclass QA are the following: analytical mechanics, elementary mathematics, geometry, mathematical logic, mathematical statistics, probabilities, numerical analysis, and number theory. Also represented are subjects on mathematical education, studying & teaching mathematics, history of mathematics, mathematical biographies, and bibliographies of mathematics (Z6651-Z6655). Works across multiple formats are collected, including print materials, electronic resources, audio-visual, and microform. Applied mathematical subjects that relate to Astronomy (QB), Business (HF/ HG), Engineering (T), Life Sciences (QH), and Physics (QC) are not addressed in this statement. II. Research Strengths A. General The Library’s mathematics collections include and are influenced by Thomas Jefferson’s personal library, which he sold to Congress after the British burned the Capitol and congressional library in 1814. Jefferson was an avid student of mathematics and had an enormous impact on the promotion of the study of mathematics at West Point and the University of Virginia.
    [Show full text]
  • Joseph Raphson Biography
    Text Book Notes HISTORY Major Joseph Raphson ALL Topic Historical Anecdotes Sub Topic Text Book Notes – Raphson Summary A brief history on Raphson Authors Jai Paul Date August 27, 2002 Web Site http://numericalmethods.eng.usf.edu The life of Joseph Raphson (1648-1715) is one that is shrouded in mystery and rather difficult to follow. In fact, no obituary of Raphson appears to have been written and the details of his life and accomplishments can only be found in records, such as those kept at the University of Cambridge and the Royal Society. Born in Middlesex, England in 1648, it is known from such records that Joseph Raphson went to Jesus College Cambridge and graduated with a Master of Arts in 1692. As a rather older student (43 years old), Raphson was surprisingly made a member of the Royal Society in 1691, a year before his graduation. This honor was a direct result of his book published in 1690, entitled, Analysis aequationum universalis. This book focused primarily on the Newton method for approximating roots of an equation, hence the Newton-Raphson Method. Newton's Method of Fluxions described the same method and examples for approximating the roots of equations, however it was written in 1671, and not published until 1736, so Joseph Raphson published this material and its method 50 years before Newton! Although Raphson's relationship to Newton is not quite understood, it is known that Raphson was allowed, by Newton himself, to view and periodically study Newton's mathematical papers. Such a practice was not common. In fact, Raphson and Edmund Halley were involved with Newton on the publication of Newton's work from the early 1670's on quadrature curves, fluxions, and the a kind of mathematics that is now known as calculus, but they were unable to do so until 1704.
    [Show full text]
  • Transmathematics 2020
    Transmathematics Dr James Anderson 安德⽣ Topics • Why computer scientists like totality: • Transarithmetic - no error states • Transphysics - works at singularities • Transcomputing - faster, safer, more accurate • Summary 2 of 69 Totallity • Totality - every function is a total function • It is not necessary to waste states - so hardware and software can be more efficient • Every syntactically correct program is semantically correct - except for physical intervention, programs cannot crash 3 of 69 Totallity • Geometrical construction of the transreal numbers (1997) • Axiomatisation and machine proof of the consistency of transreal arithmetic (2007) • Human proof of the consistency of transreal and transcomplex arithmetic (2014, 2016) • Current research on the foundations and applications of transmathematics 4 of 69 Arithmetica Universalis Sir Isaac Newton 5 of 69 Arithmetica Universalis • Newton used the arithmetica universalis, which predates real arithmetic • Arithmetica universalis does not outlaw division by zero • Arithmetica universalis allows a number to have any factors. For example, 0 = 0 × 1 × 2 × … has factors 0, 1, 2, … on the right hand side • Modern integer factors are required to be smaller than the number they factorise 6 of 69 Arithmetica Universalis • Newton gave a faulty proof that division by zero is inconsistent • Newton defined x = y ⟺ x − y = 0 • This blocks transreal ±∞, Φ because (−∞) − (−∞) = ∞ − ∞ = Φ − Φ = Φ • If we read Newton’s equal (aequo) as a modern equality and restrict division by zero to transreal division
    [Show full text]
  • This Copy of the Thesis Has Been Supplied on Condition That Anyone
    University of Plymouth PEARL https://pearl.plymouth.ac.uk 04 University of Plymouth Research Theses 01 Research Theses Main Collection 2015 The Geometrical Thought of Isaac Newton: An Examination of the Meaning of Geometry between the 16th and 18th Centuries Bloye, Nicole Victoria http://hdl.handle.net/10026.1/3273 Plymouth University All content in PEARL is protected by copyright law. Author manuscripts are made available in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite only the published version using the details provided on the item record or document. In the absence of an open licence (e.g. Creative Commons), permissions for further reuse of content should be sought from the publisher or author. This copy of the thesis has been supplied on condition that anyone who consults it is understood to recognise that its copyright rests with its author and that no quotation from the thesis and no information derived from it may be published without the author’s prior consent. The Geometrical Thought of Isaac Newton An Examination of the Meaning of Geometry between the 16th and 18th Centuries by Nicole Victoria Bloye A thesis submitted to Plymouth University in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY School of Computing and Mathematics Faculty of Science and Environment Plymouth University December 2014 Abstract Our thesis explores aspects of the geometrical work and thought of Isaac Newton in order to better understand and re-evaluate his approach to geometry, and specifically his synthetic methods and the organic description of plane curves. In pursuing this research we study Newton’s geometrical work in the context of the changing view of geometry between the late 16th and early 18th centuries, a period defined by the responses of the early modern geometers to a new Latin edition of Pappus’ Collectio.
    [Show full text]