The Grip of Ideology: Alacanian Approach to Thetheory of Ideology 1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Grip of Ideology: Alacanian Approach to Thetheory of Ideology 1 Journalof Political Ideologies (2001), 6(2),191– 214 The grip of ideology: aLacanian approach to thetheory of ideology 1 JASONGLYNOS Departmentof Government, University of Essex, Wivenhoe Park, ColchesterCO4 3SQ, UK ABSTRACT Is it possible to say somethingabout how an ideology grips subjects that goesbeyond today’ s sophisticated accountsof howparticular socio-political traditions havebeen contingently constituted? This paperexplores howa Lacanianconceptual framework provides the resources with whichto offer an afrmative response to this question.In outlining such a response,I rely on Slavoj ZÏizÏek’s political re-articulations of psychoanalyticcategories andon Ernesto Laclau’s hegemonicapproach to ideology.I beginby situating the hegemonicapproach to ideologyin the context of other contemporaryap- proaches.I thenoffer areadingwhich suggests that ZÏizÏek’s Lacanianapproach canbe seen as aparticular version of the hegemonicapproach to ideology. Crucial to the former are the conceptsof desire, fantasy,and enjoyment. I suggest that aLacaniantheory of ideologyoffers us aset of conceptsdrawn from the clinic that provokeinteresting insights for the analysis andcritique of ideology. TheLacanian intervention into the eld ofideological analysis andcritique can beseen as aspecial versionof amoregeneral hegemonic approach to ideology. Andboth can be understoodagainst the backgroundof aquestionthat has come to dominatecontemporary normative political theoryin general,and post-struc- tural political theoryin particular. Givena contextin whichan emphasis on contingencyhas dealt asevere blowto the credibility ofmoral andpolitical claims to ‘universal andobjective truth’, is it still credible to speakof ideological critique? Ahegemonicapproach suggests that ideologycan, and should, be retained as apotentially fruitful political categorywith considerableanalytical andcritical value.It relies, however,upon a suitably revampedunderstanding of ideological misrecognition,a revampedunderstanding shared by post-structural approaches to ideology.Here contingency is takenas constitutive ofthe process of discursive construction,thereby making the invisibility ofcontingency constitu- tive ofideological misrecognition.Rendering contingency visible,therefore, groundsthe process ofideological critique. ISSN1356-9317 print; 1469-9613 online/ 01/020191–24 Ó 2001Taylor & FrancisLtd DOI: 10.1080/13569310120053858 JASON GLYNOS Onecrucial consequenceof takingcontingency seriously is the needto engage in detailed historico-contextual analyses. This is becauseit is felt that such detailed analyses helpmake visible the contingentnature of processes ofsocial construction.Accompanying this revampedunderstanding of ‘ misrecognition’, however,is averyimportant shift in focusthat ahegemonicapproach to the theoryof ideologyemphasizes: its capacity to accountfor an ideology’s grip, its powerto transx subjects. Thelink betweenideology and power is generallytaken for granted. More and more,so toois the link betweenpower and systems ofmeaning. It is nolonger uncommonto ndanalyses ofideological powerconducted in terms ofthe ‘naturalization’of meanings and patterns ofmeaning. Such naturalizations effectively concealthe political momentin whichdecisions couldhave been otherwise madeon account of the irreducible contingencythat inhabits the dynamicsof socio-political discourse.The crucial questionfrom a hegemonic perspective is the following:Is it possible to say somethingabout how an ideology grips subjects that goesbeyond today’ s sophisticated accountsof how particular socio-political traditions havebeen contingently constituted? Theanswer to this questionis byno means obvious.Among other things, it forces areconsiderationof the veryrole andfunction of theory in the studyof ideologyand political phenomenamore generally. For those political andsocial analysts that havetaken to heart post-positivist insights, sucha questioncannot butraise the twin spectres ofessentialism anddogmatism. Nevertheless, Iwould like to explorehow a Lacanianconceptual framework provides the resources with whichto makepossible anaf rmative responseto the abovequestion, withoutabandoning anti-essentialist presuppositions.In outlining such an ap- proach,I rely onthe workof ErnestoLaclau and, more heavily, on the workof Slavoj ZÏ izÏ ek. Ibeginby situating the hegemonicapproach to ideologyin the contextof othercontemporary approaches. Central in the elaborationof a hegemonic approachto ideologyis the workof Ernesto Laclau who, I suggest,effects ashift fromtreating ideologyin epistemological terms to treating it in ontological terms. Ioffera readingwhich suggests that ZÏ izÏ ek’s Lacanianapproach can be seen as aparticular versionof the hegemonicapproach to ideology.In this reading,the hegemonicapproach is presentedas the genusof whicha Lacanian theoryof ideology is aspecies. Iprovidea sketch ofthe conceptualframework against whichthe Lacanianintervention can be understood.Crucial in this regard are the conceptsof desire, fantasy,and enjoyment (jouissance).Isuggest that a Lacaniantheory of ideology offers us aset ofconcepts drawn from the clinic that are ofpotentially insightful relevancefor the analysis andcritique of ideology. Hegemonyin the contextof contemporary approaches to ideological analysis Contemporaryperspectives onideology are split. Onthe onehand, there are those whoannounce the endof ideology or the endof history, implicitly 192 THE GRIP OFIDEOLOGY brandingsimilar declarations of1950s and early 1960sas either prematureor simply erroneous.Here, the increasingly widespreadacceptance of capitalist liberal democratic ideals is usually offeredup asdenitive proofof these ‘ends’. 2 Onthe otherhand, there are those whoare keento reassert the pertinenceof ideologyoften precisely because liberal capitalism’s ideals are becomingever morenaturalized andthus invisible. Inthis view,the fact that there is a widespreadfeeling that wehave nally arrivedat anend is itself usually counted as evidenceindicating ideology’s presenceand strength ofhold. 3 Myselective overviewof contemporaryapproaches to the theoryof ideologywill focuson the latter group. Thepositions ofthose whoaccept the presenceof ideology can by no means becharacterized as homogeneous.Their differences turnnot on whetherwe live in anideologically-imbued society buton whether and howideology can be retained as ananalytically andcritically useful theoretical categoryin studyingmany political phenomena. 4 So,while ideologyis still seen as fully operativein contemporarysocieties, suchcommentators— whether Marxist, post-Marxist, ornon-Marxist— wish to investigate its valueas atheoretical categorywith the aim either ofabandoning it in favourof otherconceptual tools orof revamping it bymeans ofan alternative articu- lation. But whatexactly motivates this renewedinterest in,and debate over, ideology?At least oneimportant motivational sourceis to befound in philosophy’s ‘linguistic turn’in the third quarterof the twentieth century. Wittgensteinian languagegames, Heideggerian post-phenomenological her- meneutics, Lacanianpsychoanalysis, Derridean deconstruction, and Foucaultian archaeologiesand genealogies, have all in their waycontributed to today’s so-called era of‘ post-foundationalism’. It is onlyrelatively recently that suchanti-essentialist insights haveseeped into the humanities andsocial sciences, instigating are-articulation oftraditional categories suchas object andsubject, orstructure andagency. The importance of language’ s constitutive natureis appreciatedmore and more beyond the disciplinary boundariesof (post-analytical andcontinental) philosophyand literature, oftenresulting in ashift ofanalytical emphasis towardsystems ofmeaning and identity, discursive conditionsof possibility, andthe specicity ofsocio-histori- cal contexts. Thesigni cance of this ‘linguistic turn’for ideological analysis is nottoo hard to apprehend.No longer can the categoryof ideology be propped up by the traditional dichotomywhich pits ‘misrecognition’or ‘ false-consciousness’ against a‘true objective knowledge’— aknowledgethat canbe grasped by means ofa seemingly transparent linguistic medium.It is in comingto terms with the constitutive natureof language and, more generally, discourse, that several ofthe positions in the debateover the critical productivenessof ideology as atheoretical categorymay be mapped.In illustrating howthese positions can beconceivedin terms oftheir stances towardthe role oflanguage and meaning 193 JASON GLYNOS in ideological analysis, Iwill canvass the worksof Michael Freedenand Michel Foucaultin orderbetter to place into contextthe interventions ofErnestoLaclau and Slavoj ZÏ izÏ ek. Michael Freedenhas beenled to investigate notideology as suchbut (political) ideolog ies,in the plural.‘ [I]noppositionto traditional studies of political thoughtwhich focus on “ truth andepistemology, ethical richness, logical clarity, origins andcauses” , andaim to direct orrecommend political action, [Freedensuggests the need ] to developa formof conceptual analysis of ideologies that is sensitive to concretepolitical languageand debate.’ 5 Here, ‘[t]hefocusis notsimply onlogical andabstract conceptualpermutations; rather, it is onthe location ofpolitical conceptsin terms ofthe patterns in whichthey actually appear’, 6 therebygenerating complex conceptual morphologies that are delimited throughdecontestation andthat are sensitive to concrete,historically- situated ideologies. Inthis wayFreeden is able to establish apowerfuldemarcation criterion with
Recommended publications
  • Hegel's Critique of Contingency in Kant's Principle of Teleology Kimberly Zwez [email protected]
    Florida International University FIU Digital Commons FIU Electronic Theses and Dissertations University Graduate School 3-26-2014 Hegel's Critique of Contingency in Kant's Principle of Teleology Kimberly Zwez [email protected] DOI: 10.25148/etd.FI14040885 Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.fiu.edu/etd Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Zwez, Kimberly, "Hegel's Critique of Contingency in Kant's Principle of Teleology" (2014). FIU Electronic Theses and Dissertations. 1194. https://digitalcommons.fiu.edu/etd/1194 This work is brought to you for free and open access by the University Graduate School at FIU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in FIU Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of FIU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. FLORIDA INTERNATIONAL UNIVERSITY Miami, Florida HEGEL’S CRITIQUE OF CONTINGENCY IN KANT’S PRINCIPLE OF TELEOLOGY A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS in RELIGIOUS STUDIES by Kimberly Zwez 2014 To: Dean Kenneth G. Furton College of Arts and Sciences This thesis, written by Kimberly Zwez, and entitled Hegel’s Critique of Contingency in Kant’s Principle of Teleology having been approved in respect to style and intellectual content is referred to you for judgment. We have read this thesis and recommend that it be approved ____________________________________________________ Christine Gudorf ____________________________________________________ Kenneth Rogerson ____________________________________________________ Whitney Bauman, Major Professor Date of Defense: March 26, 2014 This thesis of Kimberly Zwez is approved.
    [Show full text]
  • Contingency Planning Guide for Federal Information Systems
    NIST Special Publication 800-34 Rev. 1 Contingency Planning Guide for Federal Information Systems Marianne Swanson Pauline Bowen Amy Wohl Phillips Dean Gallup David Lynes NIST Special Publication 800-34 Rev. 1 Contingency Planning Guide for Federal Information Systems Marianne Swanson Pauline Bowen Amy Wohl Phillips Dean Gallup David Lynes May 2010 U.S. Department of Commerce Gary Locke, Secretary National Institute of Standards and Technology Patrick D. Gallagher, Director Certain commercial entities, equipment, or materials may be identified in this document in order to describe an experimental procedure or concept adequately. Such identification is not intended to imply recommendation or endorsement by the National Institute of Standards and Technology, nor is it intended to imply that the entities, materials, or equipment are necessarily the best available for the purpose. There are references in this publication to documents currently under development by NIST in accordance with responsibilities assigned to NIST under the Federal Information Security Management Act of 2002. The methodologies in this document may be used even before the completion of such companion documents. Thus, until such time as each document is completed, current requirements, guidelines, and procedures (where they exist) remain operative. For planning and transition purposes, federal agencies may wish to closely follow the development of these new documents by NIST. Individuals are also encouraged to review the public draft documents and offer their comments to NIST. All NIST documents mentioned in this publication, other than the ones noted above, are available at http://csrc.nist.gov/publications. National Institute of Standards and Technology Special Publication 800-34 Natl.
    [Show full text]
  • Special Events Contingency Planning
    Special Events Contingency Planning Job Aids Manual March 2005 FEMA IS-15: Special Events Contingency Planning Job Aids Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements ..................................................................................... 1 Introduction Preface ....................................................................................................... 1 Background ................................................................................................. 2 Scope ......................................................................................................... 3 Synopsis ..................................................................................................... 4 Chapter Overviews........................................................................................ 4 Chapter 1: Pre-Event Planning Introduction.............................................................................................. 1-1 Definition of Special Event and Mass Gathering .............................................. 1-1 Planning Meetings for Special Events/Mass Gatherings .................................... 1-2 The Planning Process.................................................................................. 1-3 State and Federal Roles in Terrorism Incident Prevention ................................ 1-4 Crowd Types ............................................................................................. 1-9 Crowd Composition .................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Ten PROBLEMS with AQUINAS' THIRD
    Ten PROBLEMS WITH AQUINAS' THIRD WAY Edward Moad 1. Introduction Of Thomas Aquinas’ five proofs of the existence of God, the Third Way is a cosmological argument of a specific type sometimes referred to as an argument from contingency. The Aristotelian argument for the existence of the First Unmoved Mover was based on the observation that there is change (or motion), coupled with the principle that nothing changes unless its specific potential to change is actualized by an actual change undergone by some other thing. It then arrives at the conclusion that there exists something in a constant state of pure activity, which is not itself moved but sets everything else in motion. The operative sense of contingency this argument turns on, then, is that of motion. That is, things have the potential to change in certain ways (depending on the kind of things they are), but may or may not do so; whether they actually do being contingent on whether they are acted on in the right way by something else. For this reason, Aristotle’s argument delivers a first mover, which brings about the motion in all that exists, but not a being that brings about the very existence of everything else. The argument referred to specifically as the argument from contingency, by contrast, turns on the idea of the contingency of the very existence of anything at all. That is, if something exists which may not have existed, and the fact that it does exist rather than not is contingent on the action of other existing things which are themselves contingent, then the existence of the whole lot of contingent things, taken together, is also contingent.
    [Show full text]
  • Aquinas' Third
    Aquinas’ Third Way A chain of causes cannot be infinite. Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas’ second way: 1. At least one thing has an efficient cause. 2. Every causal chain must either be circular, or infinite, or it has a first cause. 3. If something were the efficient cause of itself, it would be prior to itself. 4. Nothing can be prior to itself. 5. Nothing is either the efficient cause of itself, or is causally responsible for itself. (3,4) 6. A chain of causes cannot be infinite. __________________________________ C. There is a first cause. (1,2,5,6) Our main topic today will be a discussion of Aquinas’ third way. But before moving on to that argument, let’s talk briefly about a way in which the above reconstruction of the second way might be improved, and about a further criticism of the second way. Last time there was some confusion about the roles of premises 2, 5, and 6 in the argument. One way in which the roles of these premises might be made more clear is by splitting premise 2 up into the following three sub-premises: Every causal chain must either be circular or non-circular. Every causal chain must either be finite or infinite. Every non-infinite, non-circular causal chain must include a first cause. We’re making progress. We’ve got a valid argument, and we have seen that there’s good reason to believe that premises 1, 2, 3, and 4 are true. So the only independent premise - that is, the only premise which does not follow from other premises - which remains to discuss is premise 6.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on the Cosmological Argument
    Philosophers’ volume 14, no. 12 Introduction may 2014 Imprint In the section of the first Critique entitled “The Ideal of Pure Reason,” Kant constructs an elaborately layered critique of the so-called “cos- mological proof” of the existence of God.1 He portrays the cosmologi- cal argument (as I shall more neutrally term it) as having three main phases.2 First, one observes that there is at least one existent being, and argues that it exists contingently (28: 1006). Second, appealing to the Principle of Sufficient Reason, one argues for the existence of Kant on the an absolutely necessary being as the ultimate cause (A 605/B 633n*) or ground (28: 1006) of this contingently existing being. Third, one argues that this absolutely necessary being is a most real being — or ens realissimum (A 605–6/B 633–34). In “The Ideal,” Kant presents Cosmological Argument this third step as drawing the argument to a close (A 606/B 634). But, judging by his discussion in the Religion Lectures, he sometimes con- ceives of the argument as intended to be completed by a sort of coda in which one argues that the absolutely necessary being, since it is an ens realissimum, must possess each of the traditional “divine attributes.”3 Kant raises three main objections to this version of the cosmologi- cal argument. First, it “presupposes” the correctness of the ontological argument in the sense, apparently, of tacitly incorporating the onto- logical argument as a proper part (A 607/B 635; A 608–9/B 636–7). Second, it commits an ignoratio elenchi, a fallacy of arguing for some- thing other than what was at issue (A 609/B 637).
    [Show full text]
  • DIVINE WILL and HUMAN CHOICE Freedom, Contingency, and Necessity in Early Modern Reformed Thought
    DIVINE WILL AND HUMAN CHOICE Freedom, Contingency, and Necessity in Early Modern Reformed Thought RICHARD A. MULLER K Richard A. Muller, Divine Will and Human Choice Baker Academic, a division of Baker Publishing Group, © 2017. Used by permission. (Unpublished manuscript—copyright protected Baker Publishing Group) © 2017 by Richard A. Muller Published by Baker Academic a division of Baker Publishing Group P.O. Box 6287, Grand Rapids, MI 49516-6287 www.bakeracademic.com Printed in the United States of America All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means—for example, electronic, photocopy, recording—without the prior written permission of the publisher. The only exception is brief quotations in printed reviews. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Title: Divine will and human choice : freedom, contingency, and necessity in early modern reformed thought / Richard A. Muller. Description: Grand Rapids : Baker Academic, 2017. | Includes index. Identifiers: LCCN 2016052081 | ISBN 9780801030857 (cloth) Subjects: LCSH: Free will and determinism—Religious aspects—Christianity—History of doctrines. | Reformed Church—Doctrines. Classification: LCC BT810.3 .M85 2017 | DDC 233/.70882842—dc23 LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016052081 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Richard A. Muller, Divine Will and Human Choice Baker Academic, a division of Baker Publishing Group, © 2017. Used by permission. (Unpublished manuscript—copyright protected Baker Publishing Group) For Ethan, Marlea, and Anneliese Richard A. Muller, Divine Will and Human Choice Baker Academic, a division of Baker Publishing Group, © 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth and Truthmaking in 17Th-Century Scholasticism
    Truth and Truthmaking in 17th-Century Scholasticism by Brian Embry A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Brian Embry 2015 Truth and Truthmaking in 17th-Century Scholasticism Brian Embry Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2015 Abstract Some propositions are true and others are false. What explains this difference? Some philosophers have recently defended the view that a proposition is true because there is an entity, its truthmaker, that makes it true. Call this the ‘truthmaker principle’. The truthmaker principle is controversial, occasioning the rise of a large contemporary debate about the nature of truthmaking and truthmakers. What has gone largely unnoticed is that scholastics of the early modern period also had the notion of a truthmaker [verificativum], and this notion is at the center of early modern scholastic disputes about the ontological status of negative entities, the past and future, and uninstantiated essences. My project is to explain how early modern scholastics conceive of truthmaking and to show how they use the notion of a truthmaker to regiment ontological enquiry. I argue that the notion of a truthmaker is born of a certain conception of truth according to which truth is a mereological sum of a true mental sentence and its intentional object. This view entails the truthmaker principle and is responsible for some surprising metaphysical views. For example, it leads many early modern scholastics to posit irreducible negative entities as truthmakers for negative truths, giving rise to an extensive literature on the nature of negative entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz on Contingency and Freedom: a Molinism Friendly Account
    Leibniz on Contingency and Freedom: A Molinism Friendly Account Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Juan Garcia, MA Graduate Program in Philosophy The Ohio State University 2018 Dissertation Committee: Tamar Rudavsky, Advisor Julia Jorati, Advisor Lisa Downing William Taschek © 2018 by Juan Garcia All rights reserved. Abstract: Some philosophical ideas, like metals, reveal their most interesting qualities when stretched. As I see it, the intelligibility and plausibility of the concept of contingency, as a condition for freedom, is stretched significantly by three of Leibniz’s major philosophical commitments: i) a robust version of the principle of sufficient reason; ii) strong theological commitments like divine foreknowledge and robust providence; and iii) Leibniz’s distinctive thesis of complete individual concepts – the doctrine that every substance has an individual concept which includes predicates denoting everything that will ever happen to it. Many interpreters think that these Leibnizian commitments stretch contingency to the breaking point: Leibniz cannot retain a genuine type of contingency. In this dissertation, I argue that these interpreters are mistaken and that Leibniz can accommodate a plausible type of contingency. Two important steps in reaching this conclusion are the following. First, I identify a kind of explanation of rational action according to which the explanans does not necessitate the explanandum. Second, I develop an account that makes sense of individual concepts including contingent truths as contingent. This account both sheds new light on some of Leibniz’s central views on contingency and freedom, and expands our substantive understanding of contingency as a condition for freedom.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Contingencies in the Evolution of States and Their Militaries*
    Historical Contingencies in the Evolution of States and Their Militaries* Jonathan Bendor Jacob Shapiro August 28, 2018; 1:35 pm Forthcoming in World Politics ABSTRACT Historians and some scholars of international relations have long argued that historical contingencies play a critical role in the evolution of the international system, but have not explained whether they do so to a greater extent than in other domains nor why such differences might exist. We address these lacunae by identifying stable differences between war and other policy domains which render the evolution of the international system more subject to chance events than other domains. The selection environment of international politics has produced a handful of tightly integrated organizations (militaries) as the domain’s key players to a much greater degree than in other policy domains. Because there are few players, no law of large numbers holds; because organizations are tightly integrated, micro-shocks can reverberate up to macro- organizational levels. Finally, the impact of these shocks is amplified by the anarchic character of the international system. We explore these phenomena in a range of historical examples. * The authors thank Steve Biddle, Phil Hoffman, Massimo Morelli, and our anonymous reviewers for tremendously helpful comments as well as the participants in the March 2013 Historical Development of Modern Political Institutions conference at Princeton, the May 2013 Historical Working Group conference at Columbia University, and to the participants in the panel on “War, Development, and the Emergence of the State” at the 2015 American Political Science Association Annual Meeting. Emefa Agawu, Ben Crisman, and Myra Khalid provided outstanding research assistance.
    [Show full text]
  • Jerome Zanchi (1516–90) and the Analysis of Reformed Scholastic Christology
    Stefan Lindholm, Jerome Zanchi (1516–90) and the Analysis of Reformed Scholastic Christology © 2016, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525551042 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647551043 Stefan Lindholm, Jerome Zanchi (1516–90) and the Analysis of Reformed Scholastic Christology Reformed Historical Theology Edited by Herman J. Selderhuis in Co-operation with Emidio Campi, Irene Dingel, Elsie Anne McKee, RichardMuller,Risto Saarinen, and Carl Trueman Volume 37 © 2016, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525551042 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647551043 Stefan Lindholm, Jerome Zanchi (1516–90) and the Analysis of Reformed Scholastic Christology Stefan Lindholm Jerome Zanchi (1516–90) and the Analysis of Reformed Scholastic Christology Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht © 2016, Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG, Göttingen ISBN Print: 9783525551042 — ISBN E-Book: 9783647551043 Stefan Lindholm, Jerome Zanchi (1516–90) and the Analysis of Reformed Scholastic Christology Bibliographic informationpublishedbythe Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliotheklists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data available online:http://dnb.d-nb.de. ISSN 2198-8226 ISBN 978-3-525-55104-2 Yo ucan find alternative editions of this book and additionalmaterial on ourWebsite:www.v-r.de 2016, Vandenhoeck & RuprechtGmbH & Co.KG, Theaterstraße13, D-37073 Göttingen/ Vandenhoeck & RuprechtLLC,Bristol, CT,U.S.A. www.v-r.de All rightsreserved. No partofthis work maybereproduced or utilized in anyform or by anymeans, electronicormechanical, including photocopying, recording,orany information storage and retrieval system, withoutprior written permissionfrom the publisher. Printed in Germany. Typesetting by Konrad Triltsch GmbH, Ochsenfurt Printed and bound by Hubert & Co GmbH & Co.KG, Robert-Bosch-Breite 6, D-37079 Göttingen Printed on aging-resistantpaper.
    [Show full text]
  • Scholasticism and the Problem of Intellectual Reform
    Tilburg University Introduction Wisse, P.M.; Sarot, M. Published in: Scholasticism reformed Publication date: 2010 Link to publication in Tilburg University Research Portal Citation for published version (APA): Wisse, P. M., & Sarot, M. (2010). Introduction: Reforming views of reformed scholasticism. In P. M. Wisse, M. Sarot, & W. Otten (Eds.), Scholasticism reformed: Essays in honour of Willem J. van Asselt (Published on the occasion of the retirement of Willem J. van Asselt from Utrecht University) (pp. 1-27). (Studies in theology and religion; No. 14). Brill. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 30. sep. 2021 Reforming Views of Reformed Scholasticism Introduction Maarten Wisse and Marcel Sarot 1 Introduction The title of the present work is intentionally ambiguous: Scholasticism Reformed. It may be read, firstly, as a simple reversion of “Reformed scholasticism,” as indeed some of the contributions to this volume study aspects of the type of theology between the early Reformation and the Enlightenment that continued to use the traditional methods rooted in the medieval period.
    [Show full text]