Principle of Utility to Say That We Are Morally Obligated to Perform That

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Principle of Utility to Say That We Are Morally Obligated to Perform That The Journal of Value Inquiry 20:125-136 (1986). @ t gA0 Martinus Niihoff Publishers, Dordrecht. Printed in the Netherlands. THE PRINCIPLE OF UTILITY AND MILL'S MINIMIZING UTILITARIANISM * REM B. EDWARDS Department of Philosophy, The University of Tennessee, Knoxville, TN 37996 I t, I In contemporary moral philosophy, there is considerable confusion not only about what John Stuart Mill meant by the Principle of Utiiity but also about the position which the Principle occupies in his moral philosophy. Many interpreters regard Mill as an act utilitarian whose Principle of Utility was identical with a qualitatively hedonisticl version of the first principle of act utilitarianism which affirms that we are morally obligated to perform that relevant individual act which is most like- ly to have the best consequences for all persons or sentient beings affected by the act.2 Others regard him as a quaiitativeiy hedonistic rule utilitarian and take his Principle of Utility to say that we are morally obligated to perform that relevant act which falls under a general rule, universal obedience to which would have the best consequences for all persons or sentient beings affected.3 As a qualitative hedonist, Mill equated intrinsically good consequences with happiness, defined as "an existence exempt as far as possibie from pain, and as rich as possible in enjoy- ments, both in point of quantity and quality."4 We are thus repeatedly informed that Mill's ultimate moral principle, the Principle of Utility itself, is that we are morally bound both to maximize happiness and minimize unhappiness either through each individual act that we perform or through the societal adoption and enforcement of general rules or behavior which would maximize happiness and minimize unhappiness for the greatest possible numbers if everyone acted on the rules. I hope to show that Mill offers us a third form of utilitarianism which I shall call minimizing utilitarianism. There are many things wrong with attempts to construe Mill as being either an act or a rule utilitarian. Both positions are maximizing utilitarianisms which main- tain that we are morally obligated to maximize goodness, but Mill's utilitarianism was actually a minimizing utilitarianism which claims only that we are morally obligated to abstain from inflicting harm, to actively prevent harm, to actively provide I for all persons or sentient beings certain minimal essentials of any sort of I positive well being whatsoever, such as life, liberty, security, individuality and self- I determination, food and shelter, basic education, equal opportunity to pursue "! * Writing of this article was supported by a Summer Research Grant from the University of Tennessee. 125 126 happiness, etc., and beyond that to exercise a decent minimum of charity. This minimizing utilitarianism is far superior in many ways to what often passes for "the utilitarian position" in much of the literature. Mill did not formulate or advo- cate a maximizing utilitarianism at all. The assumption that he did has been based upon a careless or incomplete reading of what Mill had to say about the Principle of Utility, both with respect to its formulation and its position in his general theory of value and morality. 1. The meaning of the Principle of Utility What did Mill mean by the Principle of Utility? Due to Mill's own carelessness about the matter, there is no simple answer and thus no simple identification of his ultimate normative position with act or rule utilitarianism. Mill often suggested that he accepted Jeremy Bentham's Principle of Utility.s If so, he may have been committed to the following formulation which Bentham presented rn hrs An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation: "By the principle of utility is meant that principle which approves or disapproves of every action what- soever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose interest is in question."6 Bentham then explained immediately that the "party" could be either a particular individual or the com- munity in general.T Bentham's Principle of Utility contained both a distinction between correct and incorrect acts and a theory of the end or the good consequent upon acts - approved acts are those which promote the end of happiness, dis- approved acts are those which diminish happiness. When we examine Mill's own characterizations of the Principle of Utility, which he frequently calls "the greatest happiness principle," it is by no means clear what he means by this. Definition I below, perhaps the most influential of Mill's formu- lations, seems to be very close to Bentham's containing both a reference to correct versus incorrect acts and a reference to the intrinsic good of happiness, but Defini- tions II through IV below have been interpreted to equate the Principle of Utility strictly with the ideal that happiness is the only thing desirable as an end in itself. Definition 1: The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals "utili-, ty" or the "greatest happiness principle" holds that actions are right in pro- portion as they tend to produce happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure.E Definition /1: For instance, the principle of utility, - the doctrine that all things are good or evil, by virtue solely of the pleasure or the pain which they produce, - is as broadly stated, and as emphatically maintained against Pro- tagoras by Socrates, in the dialogue, as it ever was by Epicurus or Bentham.e Definition III: The utiiitarian doctrine is that happiness is desirable, and the only thing desirable as an end; all other things being only desirable as a means to that end.lo 127 Definition IV: lt (the Principle of Utility) *uy be more correctly de- scribed as supposing that equal amounts of happiness are equally desirable, whether felt by the same or different persons. This, however, is not a pre- supposition, not a premise needful to support the principle of utility, but the very principle itself ; for what is the principle of utility if it be not that "hap- piness" and "desirable" are synonymous terms?11 DeJinition Z: I merely declare my conviction, that the general principle to which all rules of practice ought to conform, and the test by which they should be tried, is that of conduciveness to the happiness of mankind, or rather, of all sentient beings: in other words, that the promotion of happiness is the ultimate principle of Teleology.r2 Two of Mill's most astute recent interpreters, D.G. Brown and David Lyons, have insisted that Miil's Principle of Utility is merely a theory of the good and not a theory of desirable action or obligation at all. Brown found at least fifteen dif- ferent wordings of the Principle of Utility in Mill's writings which Mill apparently regarded as equivalent.13 He insisted that they all reduce to the idea that "Happi- ness is the only thing desirable as an end."14 Similarly, David Lyons, who relies too uncritically I think on Brown's work, has recently advanced the view that Mill's "Principle of Utility says that happiness is the ultimate good, and thus it represents a theory of value - not of obligation."ls Elsewhere, Lyons admitted that the Principle could at least be used to rank actions with respect to desirability,l6 but he sees this ranking function as extraneous to the meaning of the Principle itself. It is tempting to agree with the Brown/Lyons thesis that the Principle of Utility as such did not incorporate a distinction between correct versus incorrect action at all, for if they are right it is at once apparent that neither a maximizing act or rule utilitarianism is identical with Mill's Principle of Utility since both in- volve normative theories of moral action. I am convinced, however, by the fol- lowing reasons that the Principle did contain some sort of prescriptive element in its very conception, despite what Brown and Lyons have to say. In the first place, as in Definition I, Mill frequently referred to the Principle of Utility as the "greatest happiness principle." Mill got it from Bentham, who got it from Helvetius and/or Hume,l7 who got it from older thinkers in the Moral Sense tradition of Scottish moral philosophy. As this principle was introduced into modern ethical theory by Francis Hutcheson, it clearly contained an action- guiding element: "...that Action is best, which procures the greatest Happiness for the greatest Numbers: and that, worst, which, in like manner, occasions Mise- rY,"rE The Principle had changed little by the time it got to Bentham. In a later footnote to his own definition of the Principle of Utility quoted above, Bentham himself defined the greatest happiness principle as follows: This for shortness, instead of saying at length that principle whichstates the greatest happiness of all those whose interest is in question, as being the right and proper, and only right and proper and univerially deiirabie, Jnd of f,u- 128 man action: of human action in every situation, and in particular in that of a functionary or set of functionaries exercising the powers^of government:1e Thus, the utiiitarian tradition to which Mill belonged clearly meant more by the greatest happiness principle than that happiness is the sole intrinsic good. It meant also that desirable actions are those which promote happiness and that undesirable actions are those which reduce happiness or permit or produce unhappiness. More decisively, however, Mill's Definitions II and III above both contain references to the meons of happiness, and Mill repeatedly insisted that certain kinds of human actions are effective means to that end.
Recommended publications
  • John Stuart Mill's Sanction Utilitarianism
    JOHN STUART MILL’S SANCTION UTILITARIANISM: A PHILOSOPHICAL AND HISTORICAL INTERPRETATION A Dissertation by DAVID EUGENE WRIGHT Submitted to the Office of Graduate and Professional Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Chair of Committee, Linda Radzik Committee Members, Clare Palmer Scott Austin R.J.Q. Adams Head of Department, Gary Varner May 2014 Major Subject: Philosophy Copyright 2014 David Eugene Wright ABSTRACT This dissertation argues for a particular interpretation of John Stuart Mill’s utilitarianism, namely that Mill is best read as a sanction utilitarian. In general, scholars commonly interpret Mill as some type of act or rule utilitarian. In making their case for these interpretations, it is also common for scholars to use large portions of Mill’s Utilitarianism as the chief source of insight into his moral theory. By contrast, I argue that Utilitarianism is best read as an ecumenical text where Mill explains and defends the general tenets of utilitarianism rather than setting out his own preferred theory. The exception to this ecumenical approach to the text comes in the fifth chapter on justice which, I argue on textual and historical grounds, outlines the central features of Mill’s utilitarianism. With this understanding of Utilitarianism in place, many of the passages commonly cited in favor of the previous interpretations are rendered less plausible, and interpretations emphasizing Mill’s other writings are strengthened. Using this methodology, I critique four of the most prominent act or rule utilitarian interpretations of Mill’s moral theory. I then provide an interpretation of Mill’s theory of moral obligation and utilitarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Product Differentiation
    Product differentiation Industrial Organization Bernard Caillaud Master APE - Paris School of Economics September 22, 2016 Bernard Caillaud Product differentiation Motivation The Bertrand paradox relies on the fact buyers choose the cheap- est firm, even for very small price differences. In practice, some buyers may continue to buy from the most expensive firms because they have an intrinsic preference for the product sold by that firm: Notion of differentiation. Indeed, assuming an homogeneous product is not realistic: rarely exist two identical goods in this sense For objective reasons: products differ in their physical char- acteristics, in their design, ... For subjective reasons: even when physical differences are hard to see for consumers, branding may well make two prod- ucts appear differently in the consumers' eyes Bernard Caillaud Product differentiation Motivation Differentiation among products is above all a property of con- sumers' preferences: Taste for diversity Heterogeneity of consumers' taste But it has major consequences in terms of imperfectly competi- tive behavior: so, the analysis of differentiation allows for a richer discussion and comparison of price competition models vs quan- tity competition models. Also related to the practical question (for competition authori- ties) of market definition: set of goods highly substitutable among themselves and poorly substitutable with goods outside this set Bernard Caillaud Product differentiation Motivation Firms have in general an incentive to affect the degree of differ- entiation of their products compared to rivals'. Hence, differen- tiation is related to other aspects of firms’ strategies. Choice of products: firms choose how to differentiate from rivals, this impacts the type of products that they choose to offer and the diversity of products that consumers face.
    [Show full text]
  • Satisficing Consequentialism Author(S): Michael Slote and Philip Pettit Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol
    Satisficing Consequentialism Author(s): Michael Slote and Philip Pettit Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 58 (1984), pp. 139-163+165-176 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4106846 Accessed: 15/10/2008 09:26 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The Aristotelian Society and Blackwell Publishing are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes.
    [Show full text]
  • I. Externalities
    Economics 1410 Fall 2017 Harvard University SECTION 8 I. Externalities 1. Consider a factory that emits pollution. The inverse demand for the good is Pd = 24 − Q and the inverse supply curve is Ps = 4 + Q. The marginal cost of the pollution is given by MC = 0:5Q. (a) What are the equilibrium price and quantity when there is no government intervention? (b) How much should the factory produce at the social optimum? (c) How large is the deadweight loss from the externality? (d) How large of a per-unit tax should the government impose to achieve the social optimum? 2. In Karro, Kansas, population 1,001, the only source of entertainment available is driving around in your car. The 1,001 Karraokers are all identical. They all like to drive, but hate congestion and pollution, resulting in the following utility function: Ui(f; d; t) = f + 16d − d2 − 6t=1000, where f is consumption of all goods but driving, d is the number of hours of driving Karraoker i does per day, and t is the total number of hours of driving all other Karraokers do per day. Assume that driving is free, that the unit price of food is $1, and that daily income is $40. (a) If an individual believes that the amount of driving he does wont affect the amount that others drive, how many hours per day will he choose to drive? (b) If everybody chooses this number of hours, then what is the total amount t of driving by other persons? (c) What will the utility of each resident be? (d) If everybody drives 6 hours a day, what will the utility level of each Karraoker be? (e) Suppose that the residents decided to pass a law restricting the total number of hours that anyone is allowed to drive.
    [Show full text]
  • Advantages & Disadvantages of Consequential Ethics
    CONSEQUENTIAL ETHICS: SUMMARY (c) 2019 www.prshockley.org Dr. Paul R Shockley What about Consequences? Significant Types of Utilitarianism: Utilitarianism: The right action is what brings about the greatest good Consequential Ethics (CE): An action is right iff it promotes the 1. Consequentialism = whether an act is morally to the greatest number in the long run. Here are different types of best consequences. The best consequences are those in which right depends only on consequences (not utilitarianism: “happiness” is maximized. Central question: what actions will circumstances, the intrinsic nature of the act, or 1. Hedonistic Utilitarianism: maximize Pleasure & minimalize pain. generate the best consequences? This family of outcome based anything that happens before the act). approaches are varied but two, in particular, heed our attention, 2. Act Utilitarianism: an act should be judged by its results. namely, the utilitarianism of Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) & John 2. Actual Consequentialism = whether an act is 3. Rule Utilitarianism: an act is right iff it follows the rules that promotes Stuart Mill (1806-1873) & egoism or objectivism of Ayn Rand morally right depends only on the actual the best consequences. Ethical rules are chosen in view of the anticipated (1905-1982). Consequential ethics is also referred to as teleological consequences (not foreseen, foreseeable, intended, results flowing from keeping those rules. ethics hence, Greek word teleos, meaning “having reached one’s or likely consequences). 4. Priority Utilitarianism: maximize the achievement of people’s priorities-it is for each person to decide what constitutes personal end” or “goal directed.” This summary centers on utilitarianism. 3. Direct Consequentialism = whether an act is happiness (R.M.
    [Show full text]
  • Utility with Decreasing Risk Aversion
    144 UTILITY WITH DECREASING RISK AVERSION GARY G. VENTER Abstract Utility theory is discussed as a basis for premium calculation. Desirable features of utility functions are enumerated, including decreasing absolute risk aversion. Examples are given of functions meeting this requirement. Calculating premiums for simplified risk situations is advanced as a step towards selecting a specific utility function. An example of a more typical portfolio pricing problem is included. “The large rattling dice exhilarate me as torrents borne on a precipice flowing in a desert. To the winning player they are tipped with honey, slaying hirri in return by taking away the gambler’s all. Giving serious attention to my advice, play not with dice: pursue agriculture: delight in wealth so acquired.” KAVASHA Rig Veda X.3:5 Avoidance of risk situations has been regarded as prudent throughout history, but individuals with a preference for risk are also known. For many decision makers, the value of different potential levels of wealth is apparently not strictly proportional to the wealth level itself. A mathematical device to treat this is the utility function, which assigns a value to each wealth level. Thus, a 50-50 chance at double or nothing on your wealth level may or may not be felt equivalent to maintaining your present level; however, a 50-50 chance at nothing or the value of wealth that would double your utility (if such a value existed) would be equivalent to maintaining the present level, assuming that the utility of zero wealth is zero. This is more or less by definition, as the utility function is set up to make such comparisons possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Negative Average Preference Utilitarianism Roger Chao*
    Journal of Philosophy of Life Vol.2, No.1 (March 2012):55-66 [Discussion Paper] Negative Average Preference Utilitarianism * Roger Chao Abstract For many philosophers working in the area of Population Ethics, it seems that either they have to confront the Repugnant Conclusion (where they are forced to the conclusion of creating massive amounts of lives barely worth living), or they have to confront the Non-Identity Problem (where no one is seemingly harmed as their existence is dependent on the “harmful” event that took place). To them it seems there is no escape, they either have to face one problem or the other. However, there is a way around this, allowing us to escape the Repugnant Conclusion, by using what I will call Negative Average Preference Utilitarianism (NAPU) – which though similar to anti-frustrationism, has some important differences in practice. Current “positive” forms of utilitarianism have struggled to deal with the Repugnant Conclusion, as their theory actually entails this conclusion; however, it seems that a form of Negative Average Preference Utilitarianism (NAPU) easily escapes this dilemma (it never even arises within it). 1. Introduction For many philosophers working in the area of Population Ethics, it seems that either they have to confront the Repugnant Conclusion, or they have to confront the Non-Identity Problem. To them it seems there is no escape, they either have to face one problem or the other. What I will try to show in this paper however, is that there is a way around this, allowing us to escape the Repugnant Conclusion, by using what I will call Negative Average Preference Utilitarianism (NAPU) – which though similar to anti-frustrationism, has some important differences in practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Economic Evaluation Glossary of Terms
    Economic Evaluation Glossary of Terms A Attributable fraction: indirect health expenditures associated with a given diagnosis through other diseases or conditions (Prevented fraction: indicates the proportion of an outcome averted by the presence of an exposure that decreases the likelihood of the outcome; indicates the number or proportion of an outcome prevented by the “exposure”) Average cost: total resource cost, including all support and overhead costs, divided by the total units of output B Benefit-cost analysis (BCA): (or cost-benefit analysis) a type of economic analysis in which all costs and benefits are converted into monetary (dollar) values and results are expressed as either the net present value or the dollars of benefits per dollars expended Benefit-cost ratio: a mathematical comparison of the benefits divided by the costs of a project or intervention. When the benefit-cost ratio is greater than 1, benefits exceed costs C Comorbidity: presence of one or more serious conditions in addition to the primary disease or disorder Cost analysis: the process of estimating the cost of prevention activities; also called cost identification, programmatic cost analysis, cost outcome analysis, cost minimization analysis, or cost consequence analysis Cost effectiveness analysis (CEA): an economic analysis in which all costs are related to a single, common effect. Results are usually stated as additional cost expended per additional health outcome achieved. Results can be categorized as average cost-effectiveness, marginal cost-effectiveness,
    [Show full text]
  • Which Consequentialism? Machine Ethics and Moral Divergence
    MIRI MACHINE INTELLIGENCE RESEARCH INSTITUTE Which Consequentialism? Machine Ethics and Moral Divergence Carl Shulman, Henrik Jonsson MIRI Visiting Fellows Nick Tarleton Carnegie Mellon University, MIRI Visiting Fellow Abstract Some researchers in the field of machine ethics have suggested consequentialist or util- itarian theories as organizing principles for Artificial Moral Agents (AMAs) (Wallach, Allen, and Smit 2008) that are ‘full ethical agents’ (Moor 2006), while acknowledging extensive variation among these theories as a serious challenge (Wallach, Allen, and Smit 2008). This paper develops that challenge, beginning with a partial taxonomy ofconse- quentialisms proposed by philosophical ethics. We discuss numerous ‘free variables’ of consequentialism where intuitions conflict about optimal values, and then consider spe- cial problems of human-level AMAs designed to implement a particular ethical theory, by comparison to human proponents of the same explicit principles. In conclusion, we suggest that if machine ethics is to fully succeed, it must draw upon the developing field of moral psychology. Shulman, Carl, Nick Tarleton, and Henrik Jonsson. 2009. “Which Consequentialism? Machine Ethics and Moral Divergence.” In AP-CAP 2009: The Fifth Asia-Pacific Computing and Philosophy Conference, October 1st-2nd, University of Tokyo, Japan, Proceedings, edited by Carson Reynolds and Alvaro Cassinelli, 23–25. AP-CAP 2009. http://ia-cap.org/ap-cap09/proceedings.pdf. This version contains minor changes. Carl Shulman, Henrik Jonsson, Nick Tarleton 1. Free Variables of Consequentialism Suppose that the recommendations of a broadly utilitarian view depend on decisions about ten free binary variables, where we assign a probability of 80% to our favored option for each variable; in this case, if our probabilities are well-calibrated and our errors are not correlated across variables, then we will have only slightly more than a 10% chance of selecting the correct (in some meta-ethical framework) specification.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is the Difference Between Weak Negative and Non-Negative Ethical
    What Is the Difference Between Weak Negative and Non-Negative Ethical Views? Simon Knutsson Foundational Research Institute [email protected] June 2016 Abstract Weak negative views in ethics are concerned with both reducing suffering and pro- moting happiness, but are commonly said to give more weight to suffering than to happiness. Such views include weak negative utilitarianism (also called negative- leaning utilitarianism), and other views. In contrast, non-negative views, including traditional utilitarianism, are typically said to give equal weight to happiness and suffering. However, it is not obvious how weak negative and non-negative views differ, and what it means to give happiness and suffering equal weight, or to give suffering more weight. Contents 1 Introduction2 2 Terminology3 3 The views under consideration3 4 Weak negative utilitarianism and consequentialism3 5 The Weak Negative Doctrine4 6 Weak negative axiology4 7 The difference between weak negative and non-negative views assuming hap- piness and suffering are objectively highly measurable5 8 If statements about magnitudes of happiness versus suffering involve value judgements 7 9 Weak negative and non-negative views are equally affected 10 10 When is it accurate to describe non-negative and weak negative views as symmetric vs. asymmetric? 10 Foundational Research Institute Acknowledgments 12 References 12 Appendix: Value for an individual versus value for the world—where does the negativity set in? 12 List of Figures 1 Common illustrations of non-negative
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 4 Utility
    Chapter 4 Utility Preferences - A Reminder x y: x is preferred strictly to y. x y: x and y are equally preferred. x ~ y: x is preferred at least as much as is y. Preferences - A Reminder Completeness: For any two bundles x and y it is always possible to state either that xyx ~ y or that y ~ x. Preferences - A Reminder Reflexivity: Any bundle x is always at least as preferred as itself; iei.e. xxx ~ x. Preferences - A Reminder Transitivity: If x is at least as preferred as y, and y is at least as preferred as z, then x is at least as preferred as z; iei.e. x ~ y and y ~ z x ~ z. Utility Functions A preference relation that is complete, reflexive, transitive and continuous can be represented by a continuous utility function . Continuityyg means that small changes to a consumption bundle cause only small changes to the preference level. Utility Functions A utility function U(x) represents a preference relation ~ if and only if: x’ x” U(x’)>U(x) > U(x”) x’ x” U(x’) < U(x”) x’ x” U(x’) = U(x”). Utility Functions Utility is an ordinal (i.e. ordering) concept. E.g. if U(x) = 6 and U(y) = 2 then bdlibundle x is stri ilctly pref erred to bundle y. But x is not preferred three times as much as is y. Utility Functions & Indiff. Curves Consider the bundles (4,1), (2,3) and (2,2). Suppose (23)(2,3) (41)(4,1) (2, 2). Assiggyn to these bundles any numbers that preserve the preference ordering; e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Moral Utility in Decision Making: an Interdisciplinary Framework
    Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience 2008, 8 (4), 390-401 doi:10.3758/CABN.8.4.390 INTERSECTIONS AMONGG PHILOSOPHY, PSYCHOLOGY, AND NEUROSCIENCE The role of moral utility in decision making: An interdisciplinary framework PHILIPPE N.TOBLER University of Cambridge, Cambridge, England ANNEMARIE KALIS Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands AND TOBIAS KALENSCHER University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands What decisions should we make? Moral values, rules, and virtues provide standards for morally acceptable decisions, without prescribing how we should reach them. However, moral theories do assume that we are, at least in principle, capable of making the right decisions. Consequently, an empirical investigation of the methods and resources we use for making moral decisions becomes relevant. We consider theoretical parallels of economic decision theory and moral utilitarianism and suggest that moral decision making may tap into mechanisms and pro- cesses that have originally evolved for nonmoral decision making. For example, the computation of reward value occurs through the combination of probability and magnitude; similar computation might also be used for deter- mining utilitarian moral value. Both nonmoral and moral decisions may resort to intuitions and heuristics. Learning mechanisms implicated in the assignment of reward value to stimuli, actions, and outcomes may also enable us to determine moral value and assign it to stimuli, actions, and outcomes. In conclusion, we suggest that moral capa- bilities cancan employemploy andand benefitbenefit fromfrom a varietyvariety of nonmoralnonmoral decision-makingdecision-making andand learninglearning mechanisms.mechanisms. Imagine that you are the democratically elected presi- save y people on the ground ( y x)? Or do not only hi- dent of a country and have just been informed that a pas- jackers, but also presidents, have an unconditional duty senger airplane has been hijacked.
    [Show full text]