<<

The Journal of Inquiry 20:125-136 (1986). @ t gA0 Martinus Niihoff Publishers, Dordrecht. Printed in the Netherlands.

THE PRINCIPLE OF AND MILL'S MINIMIZING *

REM B. EDWARDS Department of Philosophy, The University of Tennessee, Knoxville, TN 37996 I t,

I

In contemporary moral philosophy, there is considerable confusion not only about what meant by the Principle of Utiiity but also about the position which the Principle occupies in his moral philosophy. Many interpreters regard Mill as an act utilitarian whose Principle of Utility was identical with a qualitatively hedonisticl version of the first principle of which affirms that we are morally obligated to perform that relevant individual act which is most like- ly to have the best consequences for all persons or sentient beings affected by the act.2 Others regard him as a quaiitativeiy hedonistic rule utilitarian and take his Principle of Utility to say that we are morally obligated to perform that relevant act which falls under a general rule, universal obedience to which would have the best consequences for all persons or sentient beings affected.3 As a qualitative hedonist, Mill equated intrinsically good consequences with , defined as "an existence exempt as far as possibie from , and as rich as possible in enjoy- ments, both in point of quantity and quality."4 We are thus repeatedly informed that Mill's ultimate moral principle, the Principle of Utility itself, is that we are morally bound both to maximize happiness and minimize unhappiness either through each individual act that we perform or through the societal adoption and enforcement of general rules or behavior which would maximize happiness and minimize unhappiness for the greatest possible numbers if everyone acted on the rules. I hope to show that Mill offers us a third form of utilitarianism which I shall call minimizing utilitarianism. There are many things wrong with attempts to construe Mill as being either an act or a rule utilitarian. Both positions are maximizing utilitarianisms which main- tain that we are morally obligated to maximize goodness, but Mill's utilitarianism was actually a minimizing utilitarianism which claims only that we are morally obligated to abstain from inflicting harm, to actively prevent harm, to actively provide I for all persons or sentient beings certain minimal essentials of any sort of I positive well being whatsoever, such as life, liberty, security, individuality and self- I determination, food and shelter, basic education, equal opportunity to pursue "!

* Writing of this article was supported by a Summer Research Grant from the University of Tennessee.

125 126

happiness, etc., and beyond that to exercise a decent minimum of charity. This minimizing utilitarianism is far superior in many ways to what often passes for "the utilitarian position" in much of the literature. Mill did not formulate or advo- cate a maximizing utilitarianism at all. The assumption that he did has been based upon a careless or incomplete reading of what Mill had to say about the Principle of Utility, both with respect to its formulation and its position in his general theory of value and morality.

1. The meaning of the Principle of Utility

What did Mill mean by the Principle of Utility? Due to Mill's own carelessness about the matter, there is no simple answer and thus no simple identification of his ultimate normative position with act or . Mill often suggested that he accepted 's Principle of Utility.s If so, he may have been committed to the following formulation which Bentham presented rn hrs An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation: "By the principle of utility is meant that principle which approves or disapproves of every action what- soever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose is in question."6 Bentham then explained immediately that the "party" could be either a particular individual or the com- munity in general.T Bentham's Principle of Utility contained both a distinction between correct and incorrect acts and a theory of the end or the good consequent upon acts - approved acts are those which promote the end of happiness, dis- approved acts are those which diminish happiness. When we examine Mill's own characterizations of the Principle of Utility, which he frequently calls "the greatest happiness principle," it is by no means clear what he means by this. Definition I below, perhaps the most influential of Mill's formu- lations, seems to be very close to Bentham's containing both a reference to correct versus incorrect acts and a reference to the intrinsic good of happiness, but Defini- tions II through IV below have been interpreted to equate the Principle of Utility strictly with the ideal that happiness is the only thing desirable as an end in itself.

Definition 1: The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals "utili-, ty" or the "greatest happiness principle" holds that actions are right in pro- portion as they tend to produce happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended , and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure.E Definition /1: For instance, the principle of utility, - the doctrine that all things are good or evil, by virtue solely of the pleasure or the pain which they produce, - is as broadly stated, and as emphatically maintained against Pro- tagoras by Socrates, in the dialogue, as it ever was by or Bentham.e Definition III: The utiiitarian doctrine is that happiness is desirable, and the only thing desirable as an end; all other things being only desirable as a means to that end.lo 127

Definition IV: lt (the Principle of Utility) *uy be more correctly de- scribed as supposing that equal amounts of happiness are equally desirable, whether felt by the same or different persons. This, however, is not a pre- supposition, not a premise needful to support the principle of utility, but the very principle itself ; for what is the principle of utility if it be not that "hap- piness" and "desirable" are synonymous terms?11 DeJinition Z: I merely declare my conviction, that the general principle to which all rules of practice ought to conform, and the test by which they should be tried, is that of conduciveness to the happiness of mankind, or rather, of all sentient beings: in other words, that the promotion of happiness is the ultimate principle of Teleology.r2

Two of Mill's most astute recent interpreters, D.G. Brown and David Lyons, have insisted that Miil's Principle of Utility is merely a theory of the good and not a theory of desirable action or obligation at all. Brown found at least fifteen dif- ferent wordings of the Principle of Utility in Mill's writings which Mill apparently regarded as equivalent.13 He insisted that they all reduce to the idea that "Happi- ness is the only thing desirable as an end."14 Similarly, David Lyons, who relies too uncritically I think on Brown's work, has recently advanced the view that Mill's "Principle of Utility says that happiness is the ultimate good, and thus it represents a theory of value - not of obligation."ls Elsewhere, Lyons admitted that the Principle could at least be used to rank actions with respect to desirability,l6 but he sees this ranking function as extraneous to the meaning of the Principle itself. It is tempting to agree with the Brown/Lyons thesis that the Principle of Utility as such did not incorporate a distinction between correct versus incorrect action at all, for if they are right it is at once apparent that neither a maximizing act or rule utilitarianism is identical with Mill's Principle of Utility since both in- volve normative theories of moral action. I am convinced, however, by the fol- lowing reasons that the Principle did contain some sort of prescriptive element in its very conception, despite what Brown and Lyons have to say. In the first place, as in Definition I, Mill frequently referred to the Principle of Utility as the "greatest happiness principle." Mill got it from Bentham, who got it from Helvetius and/or Hume,l7 who got it from older thinkers in the Moral Sense tradition of Scottish moral philosophy. As this principle was introduced into modern ethical theory by Francis Hutcheson, it clearly contained an action- guiding element: "...that Action is best, which procures the greatest Happiness for the greatest Numbers: and that, worst, which, in like manner, occasions Mise- rY,"rE The Principle had changed little by the time it got to Bentham. In a later footnote to his own definition of the Principle of Utility quoted above, Bentham himself defined the greatest happiness principle as follows:

This for shortness, instead of saying at length that principle whichstates the greatest happiness of all those whose interest is in question, as being the right and proper, and only right and proper and univerially deiirabie, Jnd of f,u- 128

man action: of human action in every situation, and in particular in that of a functionary or set of functionaries exercising the powers^of government:1e

Thus, the utiiitarian tradition to which Mill belonged clearly meant more by the greatest happiness principle than that happiness is the sole intrinsic good. It meant also that desirable actions are those which promote happiness and that undesirable actions are those which reduce happiness or permit or produce unhappiness. More decisively, however, Mill's Definitions II and III above both contain references to the meons of happiness, and Mill repeatedly insisted that certain kinds of human actions are effective means to that end. What cannot be ignored in these two definitions is that Mill defined the Principle of Utility in such a way that it included both a reference to the good and to the means to the good. Both references are essential parts of the definitions and cannot be ignored without distortin$ Mill's position. When D.G. Brown made his case for construing the Principle as being merely a theory of the good, he quoted only the first part of Definition III and ignored the phrase "all other things being desirable as a means to that end."20 Definition II has means rather than end as its very subject, good things being those which produce pleasure and evil things those which produce pain. Thus, the Principie of Utility seems to incorporate both a theory of intrinsic and of instrumental good and evil as essential features of itself. Since actions are instrumental and ills, they are not exchtded from Definitions II and III as the Brown/Lyons thesis requires. It is Definition IV which most clearly supports the Brown/Lyons thesis that the Principle of Utility is merely a theory of the good, not a normative theory of ac- tion. I do not claim that all of Mill's references to the Principle are perfectly con- sistent, but Definition IV is unquestionably atypical in omitting all reference to oction and the means to happiness, for all the remaining definitions contain such a reference. As a final consideration, such references are required by Mill's classifying the Principle of Utility in Book VI of his Logic as the first principle of the Art of Life or Teleology, and in his defining art as being "in the imperative mood."21 Definition V, taken from the Logic, does not say merely that happiness is the ultimate principle of Teleology but that the promotion of happiness is that prin- ciple, this being tacitly understood as 'oin the imperative mood." In a parallel discussion in Utilitorianism, Mill again emphasized promotion as well as happiness, writing that according to the principle "happiness is the sole end of Human action, and the promotion of it the test by which to judge all human conduct;from whence it necessarily follows that it must be the criterion of morality, since a part is in- cluded in the whole ."22 Here the promotion of happiness is not a mere implica- tion, application or corollary of the Principle, but an integral part of its very meaning. I conclude that what Mill meant usually by the Principle of Utility would be best paraphrased as follows: Actions, virtues, rules and other instrumental goods are desirable (and in that sense correct or right) to the extent that they tend to promote the intrinsic good of the happiness of the greatest number of persons or sentient beings;and they are undesirable to the extent that they tend to permit or r29 promote the reverse of happiness. A more generalized form of the Principle that would make a place for pluralistic or non-hedonistic intrinsic goods could simply substitute "well-being" for "happiness." This formula still bears a striking resem- blance to the first principle of act utilitarianism; and since Mill called his prin- ciple the "foundation," "test," "source," and the "criterion" of morality, it is very understandable that so many have thought him to be an act utilitarian. There are still many important but subtle differences, however. Even as thus formulated, the Principle of Utility did not commit Mill to any sort of maximizing moral philosophy, primarily because in his view the Principle was not as such a moral principle at all. Also "desirable" in this formula cannot be equated with "morally obligatory," because special conceptual and empirical considerations about the very nature of moral obligation must be introduced to distinguish moral from non- moral norms.

2,. The contrast between utility and morality

When Mill called the Principle of Utility the "foundation" or 'ocriterion" of morals, what did he mean? Traditional interpretations of Mill as an act or rule utilitarian construe these phrases to mean the same thing as "first principle of morality." In other words, these views assume that the Principle was Mill's most basic moral principle, but this misconstrues the position which the Principle actually occupies in his moral philosophy. Brown and Lyons are on much firmer ground when they point out that the Principle was not as such a moral principle at all. Rather it was what we today might call the axiom of Mill's general theory of value or his general . Mill was willing to cail it the first principle of "Teleology, or the Doc- trine of Ends," though he preferred the expression "the Art of Life"23 or "the theory of life."2a This fut of Ufe has "three departments, Morality, Prudence or policy, and Aesthetics; the Right, the Expedient, and the Beautiful."2s Mill did little to fill out the details of his general axiology, but he did elaborate considerably on his understanding of the "province"26 of morality especially in l'tts On Liberty and in Chapter V on "The Connection between Utility and Justice" in his Utilitarianism. Mil1 held that moral right and wrong, moral rules, moral obligation, and moral virtue are identifiable by reference to "the promotion of happiness,"21 bttt the reference is clearly not one of simple identity. Supplemental considerations are required to mark out the province of the moral and distinguish it from the provinces of prudence, aesthetic taste, politics, etc., all of which also have the Principle of Utility as their proper "foundation" or "criterion." None of them have it without qualifications as their inherent first principle, however. Ad- ditional conceptual features must be introduced to differentiate the first prin- ciple of general axiology from the first principles of the particular provinces there- of. To say that the promotion of happiness is desirable is not to say that it is moral- ly obligatory. If we use "the first principle of morality" to refer to Mill's most 130 basic principle of moral obligation, this will not be identical with the Principle of Utility. Mill introduced at least two additional conceptual elements to differentiate the moral domain from that of prudence, taste, politics, etc. These are not mere empirical considerations, for Mill conceived of the province of the moral as in- volving them. First of all, Mill held that a kind of action should count as moral if and only if it is of such great social importance that would be justified in requiring and enforcing an obligation to perform it by negative sanctions or motiva- tors such as adverse public opinion, legel coercion, and guilty conscience. In dis- cussing the topic of "moral obligation in general," Mill explained in some detail that there are many things that it might be desirable for people to do but which they are not morally bound to do. He insisted that:

We do not call anything wrong unless we mean to imply that a person ought to be punished in some way or other for doing it - if not by law, by the opinion of his fellow creatures; if not by opinion, by the reproaches of his own conscience. This seems the real turning point of the distinction be- tween morality and simple expediency. It is a part of the notion of duty in every one of its forms that a person may rightfully be compelled to fuifill it. Duty is a thing which may be exacted from a person, as one exacts a debt. Unless we think that it may be exacted from him. we do not call it his du- ty."

Next, Mill insisted that the domain of moral obligation always involves action- guiding rules which identify and publicize those duties which society is justified in enforcing. These action-guiding rules must be much more specific than the Prin- ciple of Utility itself. Mill asserted that "Whatever we adopt as the fundamental principle of morality, w0 require subordinate principles to apply it,"" and that "There is no case of moral obligation in which some secondary principle is not involved."30 In determining which rules and which acts falling under them are to count as morally obligatory, the cost of teaching and learning the rules as well as the cost of enforcing them by negative sanctions must be considered. Rules count as moral when the evil they prevent or the benefits they provide would clearly exceed the evil they cost. They are thus grounded in but not identical with the Principle of Utility. Unlike the rules of prudence, moral rules are those which it is "for the good of mankind that (we) be held accountable."3r Yet, none of these moral or socially enforceable rules aim at the maximization of good for mankind. For Mill, moral rules are for the most part those which would minimze harm for mankind if everyone acted in accord with them. Mill clearly delineated non-moral domains of value and behavior, grounded in the kinciple of Utility, but distinct from morality. Prudence, for example, re- quires that as individuals we should act to promote our own happiness or well being. However, we have no such moral duty to ourselves, Mill thought, mainly because the of moralizing the whole of life would be too high. Others may positively encourage us to promote our own good, but societal coercion through the sanctions of law, public opinion, or bad conscience would be too costly. Uber- 131

ty is always the best rule in matters of self-interest, Miil believed, (though I am not sure that I agree with him about this). As Mil1 explained in on Liberty,

In each person's own concerns, his individual spontaneity is entitled to free exercise. Considerations to aid his judgment, exhortations to strengthen his will, may be offered to him, even obtruded on him, by others; but"he, him- seif, is the final judge. All errors which he is likely to commit against advice and warning, are far outweighed^by the evil of ailowing others io constrain him to what they deem his good.32

Again, Mill refused to classify exceptionally virtuous saintly and heroic acts as morally obligatory even though they make their obvious contribution to the greatest happiness of the greatest number. Rather, he classified them as what we today wouid call supererogatory, not as morally obligatory. Acts which go far beyond the requirements of moral duty are desirable in light of the Principle of Utility, but not all desirable actions are worth the price of enforcement by moral sanctions. Mill recognized no moral duty of general benevolence. He castigated o'a Auguste Comte as morality-intoxicated man" because Comte wanted to make morally obligatory all acts that would promote human well-being. His own posi- tion, Mill explained, is that

As a rule of conduct, to be enforced by morai sanctions, we think no more should be attempted than to prevent people from doing harm to others, or omitting to do such good as they have undertaken...Buiabove this standard there is an unlimited range of moral worth, up to the most exalted heroism, which should be.fostered,py every positive encouragement, though not con- verted into an obligation.ss

If they do not conflict with moral requirements, desirable prudential, artistic, saintly and heroic acts may be positively promoted by education, commendation and encouragement, but they may not be socially required and enforced by nega- tive sanctions. The price of coercing some desirable acts is too high, and they fail into the domain of the nonmoral. We thus have only minimal moral obligations to one another. Mill did not recognize a moral obligation to maximize happiness, either for oneself or for others, and for this reason both maximizing utilitarian and rule utilitarian interpretations of Mill have all been mistaken. Mill's was not a maximizing utilitarianism at all, for it takes the Principle of Utility only as the first principle of axiology or the "Art of Life" but not as the first principle of the province of morality proper.

3. Mill's basic moral principle

Can we identify and formulate the first principle of morality as such, even though Mill himself never seems to have made it quite explicit? Whatever it is, it cannot be identical with the Principle of Utility. Too many of Miil's interpreters have ignored 132 the sentence which he wrote just after formulating the version of the Principle that appears in Chapter II of Utilitarianism, r.e. "to give a clear view of the moral stan- daiA set up by the theory, much more requires to be Said."34 We must remember the conceptual restraints we have found. Action guiding rules count as moral if and only if they would be worth the price of negative social enforcement. We must also note that an empirical element enters into the determination that any particu- lar rule satisfies these conceptual restraints. To determine that any given rule would provide more benefits or prevent more harms than the evil it costs, it must be estab- lished (a) that disobedience to the rule would in fact have predictable harmful or non-beneficial effects, (b) that enforcing the rule with sanctions would in fact have predictable harmful effects, and (c) that the harmful or non-beneficial effects of disobedience are greater than the harmful effects of enforcement. Factual, causal knowledge enters into the determination of (a) and (b). Of course, there is room for disagreement with Mill at every one of these points. After taking all these conceptual and empirical constraints into account, Mill seemed to assume throughout his whole moral corpus the following first principle of moral obligation: We are morally obligated only to abstain from inflicting harm, to actively prevent harm, to actively provide for any other persons or sentient beings who are affected by what we do certain minimum essentials of any sort of well being whatsoever, and to make occasional contributions to nonspecific chari- ties that are not too costly to us. Only this rule and its corresponding duties are worth the price of social enforcement. Any other more concrete secondary rules and obligations in our working morality such as those of veracity and promise- keeping must be derivable from this first principle of moral obligation. Even our theory of human rights must be derivable from it. Mil1 thought that rights, i.e., obligatory societal provision or protection for everyone of those things funda- mental to our well being, correlate with such minimal essential goods as 1ife.liberty, security, individuality and self-development, food and shelter, basic education, equality of opportunity, the pursuit of happiness, etc.3s If he had iived in an age of effective medicine, I think he would have regarded basic health care as an es- sential good which society ought to provide for all, but that too is another story. To summaize my argument thus far, I have claimed that there is an action guiding element as well as a theory of intrinsic good in Mill's Principle of Utility and that the Brown/Lyons thesis which treats it merely as a theory of the good ignores too many texts in Mill's writings that also emphasize conduct. I have at- tempted to formulate and distinguish between the Principle of Utility as the first principle of Mil1's general axiology and his implicit but derivative first principle of morality, pointing out that the province of the moral by definition involves only those action-guiding rules that are worth the price of social enforcement. I have shown that Mill recognized many types of desirable actions which are non- moral because not worth the price of negative constraint. I have conciuded from this that Mill recognized only minimal moral obligations and was neither a maxi- mizing act nor ruie utilitarian. 133

4. Minimizing versus negative utilitariarusm

I suggest that the most appropriate label for Mill's version of utilitarianism is "minimizing utilitarianism," not only to distinguish his position from maximizing act and rule utilitarianism but also to distinguish it from any merely negative utili- tarianism. A affirms that we are morally obligated directly or indirectly only to prevent intrinsic evil but not to promote intrinsic good or positive well being. A negative utilitarian doctrine of rights would affirm that all rights are negative rights, i.e. rights which require only that we abstrain from harming; but there are no positive rights, i.e. rights to which there correspond obligations to promote positive well being or the essentiai means to such. Since the means for avoiding evil usually coincide extensionally with the means for promoting minimal well being, a negative utilitarianism might go so far as to affirm that we are obligated only to protect those negative rights which are already estab- lished or recognized in a given society but not to lobby for the recognition of any new rights to minimai essential goods. In formulating what I take to be Mill's funda- mental moral principle, I have included four forms of duty. The third and fourth of these have been included expressly to forestall interpreting Mill as a merely negative utilitarian. We are morally obligated only (a) to abstain from inflicting harm, (b) to actively prevent harm, (c) to actively provide and protect certain minimal essentials of any sort of well being whatsoever to those other persons or sentient beings who are affected by what we do, and (d) to make occasional limited and nonspecific contributions to charity which still fall far short of maximizing anyone's well being. Usually there is no way to fulfill obligation (b) without also fulfilling obligation (c) over the long run. A negative utilitarianism which teils us that we are morally obligated directly or indirectly to prevent intrinsic evil but not to promote intrinsic good is extreme- ly unattractive, mainly because the most obvious way to do this is to kill all sen- tient beings quickly and painlessly, assuming as Mill did that pain and are the only relevant forms of intrinsic evil. Non-existence is presumably painless. Extinct entities cannot suffer or experience any other form of intrinsic evil. Phy- sicians might readily fulfill this negative obligation by administering a lethal dose of medication to perfectly h"ppy and healthy persons during sleep and without any warning that might cause anxiety. Quite apart from its adverse side effects on others, such an act is directly wrong for some reason. Yet, a purely negative utili- tarianism cannot give the reason. Mill was clearly not a negative utilitarian in this sense. Why not? The main reason why Mil1 was not a purely negative utilitarian is that his notion of "inflicting harm" is much broader than the notions of causing or not preventing intrinsic euils such as pain and suffering. Indeed, it is so broad that a failure to provide the minimal essential conditions for intrinsic well being counts as harming. MilI's notion of "inflicting harm" clearly extends beyond "inflicting suffering" when he explains that: t34

The most marked cases of injustice, and those which give the tone to the feeling of repugnance which characterizes the sentiment, are acts of wrongful aggression or wrongful exercise of power over someone; the next are those which consist in wrongfully withholding from him something which is his due - in both cases inflicting on him a positive hurt, either in the form of direct suffering or the privation of some good which he had reasonabie ground either of a physical or of a social kind, for counting upon.36

Cleariy, the notion of harming here extends to the inflicting of suffering and to both withholding from and depriving of those essential positive goods which one is due, i.e. to which one has a right. Now, withholding a good means more than just taking away a good already possessed;it involves failing to provide an essential good not already possessed as well. Here it becomes most obvious that Mill's theory of moral obligation has only a very loose relationship with his qualitative . Just what counts as "harm" and "well being" could be interpreted in either he- donistic or ideal utilitarian terms. His moral theory is consequentialist without necessarily being hedonistic, but this should make his minimizing utilitarianism even more attractive to those who might think that some of Miil's essential goods are also intrinsic goods and entitled to promotion and protection for their own sake. Mill defined "rights" as things which are so essential to well being that society should "protect" and "defend" them. In his formal definitions of the concept of a "right" he did not use the word "provide."3? Yet, his examples expressly take "providing" into account, for he says that the right to security is like the right to physicai nutriment in that it "cannot be had unless the machinery for providing it is kept unintermittently in active play."3u Mill did in fact recognize societal obligations to provide as well as to protect at least some minimal essentials of well being such as liberty, security, nutriment, basic education, etc. Furthermore, as a social, political and philosophical reformer, Mill clearly made a place for the active promotion of both negative and positive rights for the oppressed, for slaves, for child laborers, for women, etc. even where these have not yet been recognized by society. Despite his emphasis on not harming, Mill was not a negative utilitarian. His was a minimizing utilitarianism. A finai reason why Mill's utilitarianism cannot be regarded as purely negative is that he did recognize an "imperfect" duty of charity, which he sometimes ca11ed generosity or beneficence. As "imperfect," no rights correlate with such duties, and we are not obligated to practice them with respect to any specific person at any specific time.3e Mill's position here seems to be that charity comes into play only after rights to minimum essentials of well being have been guaran- teed, and only if not execessively costly to ourselves. Since some charity is morally obligatory, the sanctions of conscience and public opinion have some bearing but not the strong relevance that they have where rights are concerned. Our conscience should hurt us, and our acquaintances should condemn us if we are never chari- table; but conscience and complaining acquaintances should not reproach when we fail to honor most of the innumerable requests for charity with which we are constant- 135 ly bombarded. Such a limited and nonspecific obligation to "do good" through charity still fal1s far short of an obligation to "maximize good." When charity is too costly, it may be encouraged as supererogation, but it cannot be required as duty. As Mill indicated in his critique of Comte, "There is a standard of altruism to which all should be required to come up, and a degree beyond it which is not obligatory, but meritorious."40 Once more, Mill's was only a minimizing but not a maximizing or a purely negative utilitarianism.

NOTES

1. I have tried to rvork out the details of Mill's theory of qualitative hedonism in: Rem B. Edr.vards, and : A Theory of Qualitative Hedonism (Ithaca: Cornell Uni- versity Press,1979). 2. To cite a few examples, Mill is interpreted as an act utilitarian by the following: J.B. Schneewind , Mill's Ethical Writings (Nerv York: Collier Books, 1965), pp. 1 -39 . especial- ly pp. 3t-34; D.G. Brorvn, "Mill's Act-Utilitarianism," Philosophical Quarterly 24 (I974), pp. 67-68; Jan Narveson, Morolity and Utility (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press, 1967), p. I24, n. 2; Robert M. Veatch,A Theory of Medicol Ethics (New York: Basic Books,Inc., 1981), pp. 146,258. 3. Mill is interpreted as a rule utilitarian by: J.O. Urmson, "The Interpretation of the Moral Philosophy of J.S. Mill," The Philosophical Quorterly,Vol.3 (1953), pp. 33-39:Richard B. Brandt, "Some Merits of One Form of Rule Utilitarianism," in University of Colorado Studies Series in Philosopfty, No. 3 (Denver: University of Colorado Press, 1967) especial- ly section XII. More recently, Brandt has construed Mi1l as "roughly" a rule utilitarian in his "The Real and Alleged Problems of Utilitarianism," The Hostings Center Report 13 (1983), p. 38. 4. J.S. Mill, Utilitorianism,Ch.II, par. 10. 5. For example, see: J.S. Mill, "Bentham," in J.M. Robson (Ed.) (Collected lilorks of John Stuort Mill) X, p. 110. 6. Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Ch.I, par. J. 7. Bentham, Ch. I, pars. 4 & 5. 8. Mill, Utilitarianism, Ch. II, par. 2. 9. Mill, 1834 essay on "The Protagoras," par.4l. 10. Mill, Utilitorianism, Ch. IV, par.2. This was the doctrine to be "proved" in MilI's discus- sion "Of What Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility is Susceptible."

11. Mill, Utilitarianism, Ch. V, footnote #, par . 7 . t2. J.S. Mill, A System of Logic, Bk. VI, Ch. XII, sect. 7, par.4. 13. D.G. Brown, "What Is Mill's Principle of Utility?" Canadian Journal of Phitosophl, 3 (197 3), pp . 2-5 . t4. Brorvn, 5. Claiming on p. 157 that the paper "has no room for" the topic, Brorvn added nothing new on the meaning of the Principle of Utility in his "Mill on Liberty and Mo- raiity," The Philosophical Review 8I (19'/2), pp. 133 158. 15. David Lyons, "Benevolence and Justice in Mill," in Harlan B. Miller and William H. Wil- liams (Eds.), The Limits of {ltilitarionism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 1982),p.45. 16. David Lyons, "Mill's Theory of Morality," Notts 10 (1976), pp. 13-14. 1'1. In one place, Mill says Bentham got it from Helvetius, Collected lilorks of John Stuart Mill X, p. 86. In the same volum e, p.497 , he says Bentham derived it from Hume. 1 8. Francis Hutcheson, An Inquiry Concerning Moral Good and Evil, sect.III, sub-sect. VIIL t36

19. Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morols and Legislotion, footnote to Ch.I, par. 3. 20. Brown, 4,par. 2. 21. Mill.,4 System of Logic , Bk. VI, Ch. XII, sect. 1. 22. Mill, Utilitarianism, Ch. IV, par. 8. Other formulations which emphasize action as well as happiness may be found in Ch.I, par. 4 and Ch.II, pars. 1, 9, 10, 18,20,24. )1 Mill,,4 System of Logic, Bk. VI, Ch. XII, sect. 1 ,par.2 and sect. 7 ,par.4. 24. Mill, Utilitorianism, Ch. II, par. 2. Mill does speak of the Principle of Utility as the "fun- damental" or "first" principle of morals in Utilitarianism, Ch. 1, par. 4 and Ch. Y , par. 26. This only means that it is the "foundation" or "source" from which morality derives, however. 25. Mill,,4 System of Logic, Bk. VI, Ch. XII, sect. 6, par.2. 26. Mill used this term in Utilitarionism,Ch. V, par. 15. 2'7 . Mill,,4 System of Logic, Bk. VI, Ch. XII, sect. 7, par.4. 28. Mill, Utilitorianism, Ch. V, par. 14. 29. Mill, Utilitarianism, Ch. II, par.24. 30. Mill, Utilitarianism, Ch. II, par.26. 3 1 . MilL, On Liberty , Ch . 4, par . 6 . 32. Mill,OnLiberty,Ch.4,par.4. SeealsoCh. 1,pars.9, 12,13 andCh.4,pars 4and6. 33. J.S. Mill, "The Later Speculations of M. Comte," par.9. 34. Mill, Utilitarionism, Ch. II, par.2.I must confess that I ignored this sentence myself and made the mistake of interpreting Mill as a maximizing moral utilitarian in my Pleasures and Poins, A Theory of Quolitative Hedonism, pp. 24, I20, I27, 143-144. However, that book deals primarily with Mill's qualitatively hedonistic theory of and disvalue. It contains only incidental remarks about his theory of moral obligation. 35. Mill would have had no great difficulty in accepting the items in John Rawls'list of "pri- mary goods" as being essential conditions of any human well being or happiness. An ideal or pluralistic utilitarian might want to classify some of these items as intrinsic goods. Even Mill thought that they have such an intimate connection with happiness, involving many qualities of pleasure, that in effect they become essential parts of happiness itself. If pleasure is an intentional concept, as I have suggested in my Pleasures and Pains, A Theory of Qualitative Hedonism,pp.T4-82,87-92, then this claim may not be as im- plausible as it appears to be on the surface. 36. Mill, Utilitaianism, Ch. V, par. 33. 37 . Mill, Utilitarianism, Ch. V, pars. 24, 25. 38. Mill, Utilitarianism, Ch. V, par.25. 39. MiLl,Utilitarianism,Ch. V, par. 15. 40. Mill, "The Later Speculations of M. Comte," par. 12. The fact that Mill recognized "im- perfect" moral duties of charity, benevolence, or altruism is one of the main reasons why D.G. Brown was mistaken in attributing to Mill the view that "Conduct is prima facie morally wrong if and only if it is harmful to others." See his "Mill on Liberty and Morali- ty," p. 150. Some failures to promote positive well being can be morally wrong on Mill's view, so Brown's "only if" is too strong.