Distributivity, Maximality, and Floating Quantifiers

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Distributivity, Maximality, and Floating Quantifiers DISTRIBUTIVITY, MAXIMALITY, AND FLOATING QUANTIFIERS by CHRISTINE M. BRISSON A Dissertation submitted to the Graduate School-New Brunswick Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Program in Linguistics written under the direction of Veneeta Dayal and approved by New Brunswick, New Jersey October, 1998 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Distributivity, Maximality, and Floating Quantifiers by CHRISTINE BRISSON Dissertation Director: Veneeta Dayal This dissertation argues that the widely-accepted analysis of all and both as universal quantifiers is incorrect, and proposes instead that all/both are modifiers that place a boundary on the range of otherwise contextually-available interpretations allowed with definite plurals. It is argued that this proposal offers wider empirical coverage of the semantic and distributional properties of all/both than previous accounts. The range of meanings of sentences with definite plurals is examined, and it is argued that a theory of distributivity that assigns universal force to distributed plural noun phrases is empirically inadequate. A change to the theory of distributivity is proposed in which the context-sensitive variable in the domain of the distributivity operator (the D operator) can be assigned a value that weakens its universal force. It is further proposed that all/both interact with the D operator by restricting the range of values that can be assigned to the resource domain variable, ensuring that the universal force of the D operator is not weakened. This accounts for the "strengthening" effect of all/both on the quantification associated with definite plurals. Because all interacts with distributivity, it has the same "scope" as distributivity. This explains some differences between definite descriptions with all and quantified NP's with every that are unexplained if all is analysed as a universal quantifier. In particular, the different scopal possibilities of all and every in direct object position, and their differences in distribution with ii collectivizing adverbial phrases, are explained. In addition, the limited distribution of all with collective predicates is accounted for by the proposal that lexically collective predicates belonging to certain aktionsart classes can contain a "hidden" D operator. Finally, a theory of "floating" quantifiers in which movement does not play a central role is proposed, and argued to provide a better account for the distribution of floated all/both and for the relationship between all/both in their prenominal and floated positions. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS While in the midst of writing this dissertation, I imagined it would be great fun to finally get to the stage of writing the acknowledgments because not only would it mean that I was near the end, it would mean the chance to write about my mentors and friends and how much they mean to me. Now that I am in that stage, I am surprised to find out how hard it is to do justice to the debt I feel to the people who helped shape my work and my life as a graduate student. I could not have asked for a better dissertation advisor than Veneeta Dayal. From the first day that she saw that there might be a generals paper topic lurking in my interest in both, she always seemed to know what I wanted to say before I knew it myself. Her linguistic intuitions are unerring and I found that whenever I ignored or set aside her suggestions I did so at my own peril. In addition to her linguistic expertise, her guidance in navigating the intellectual journey of writing a dissertation is something every graduate student should have, and I am grateful to her. I always came away from my discussions with Viviane Déprez invigorated and excited about doing linguistics. Arguing with her was a lot of fun. Of course, most of the time she was right, but it seemed I always figured that out much later, and going through the process helped me immeasurably. I am grateful to her for improving this dissertation, and hopefully my future work, by among other things never getting tired of telling me to look at the idea behind the formalism or the rule. One of the things I liked most about working with Roger Schwarzschild is that whenever I handed him a draft, he always zeroed in on the core of it, and reframed what I was trying to get across in such a way that I could turn it over and examine it from a new perspective to see if it was what I really wanted to say. Needless to say, many times the answer was no. In addition, I wish to iv thank him for his insights and suggestions thared so many good suggestions on so many aspects of the dissertation that what I couldn't manage to incorporate in the dissertation will give me hearty food for thought in the years to come. I am also grateful for having had the opportunity to work with Angelika Kratzer. She generously shared with me some of her insights into event semantics, and provoked me with her questions, and the dissertation emerged much the better for it. For discussion of various parts of this dissertation, in various stages of its evolution, I wish to thank Eric Bakoviü, Olga Babko-Malaya, Maria Bittner, Tom Ernst, Bill Ladusaw, Fred Landman, Peter Lasersohn, Jason Merchant, Susan Rothstein, Yael Sharvit, Colin Wilson,Yoad Winter, my fellow students at Rutgers, and audiences at SALT VII, the CUNY syntax lunch, and Johns Hopkins. The graduate program in linguistics at Rutgers began the year my classmates and I arrived. From the beginning, the faculty were committed to doing their part to make it a challenging, bustling, and fun place to be. In particular, I want to thank Jane Grimshaw and Alan Prince for their constant attention to, and understanding of, the many intellectual, administrative, financial, etc. etc. needs of graduate students, and for always bringing good beer. I want to thank my friends and fellow students in the linguistics department for helping make Rutgers such a good place to be a grad student. Special thanks to Strang Burton and Vieri Samek- Lodovici for going first, toYael Sharvit for coffee talk on linguistics and life, to Ed Keer and Kris Jaeger for great dinner parties, and to Eric Bakoviü for making everything so much fun. While I was working on my linguistics degree, all the while I had a secret other life as a residence counselor at Douglass College. Although at times it was difficult, I'm glad I had the chance to work with the great women who work for, and attend, Douglass. I think it helped keep v me grounded to work so closely with smart, interesting people who don't know or care what a D operator is. In particular I want to thank Kim Owens for always understanding exactly how things are. Finally, I wish to thank my family. First my parents, who gave me innumerable gifts but perhaps the most relevant here being determination and self confidence. My brothers, Mike and Danny, and my sister Nancy, make this world a better place. And I thank Marc Meola for sharing the journey with me. He always told me things would be ok, even when I didn't want him to, and he was right. vi Table of Contents Chapter 1: Floating Quantifiers 1 Introduction. ..............................................1 1.1 The distribution of all, both, and each .......................................2 1.2 The category of floating quantifiers .........................................4 1.2.1 Arguments that all is not a determiner-quantifier ............................6 1.2.1.1 Evidence from its distribution: prenominal all .......................6 1.2.1.2 Evidence from discourse anaphora ................................9 1.2.1.3 Evidence from questions........................................9 1.2.1.4 "Semantic" evidence..........................................13 1.2.2 Both. ................................................16 1.2.2.1 Arguments that both is not a determiner-quantifier...................17 1.2.3 Possible problems for the modifier proposal ...............................18 1.2.3.1 Both + CN. .................................................18 1.2.3.2 Partitive constructions .........................................20 1.3 The Syntax of all/both and the phenomenon of "floating" .......................21 1.4 The semantics of all. 22 1.4.1 The maximizing effect................................................22 1.4.2 Taub's discussion of distributive subentailments............................25 1.4.3 A problem with the maximizing effect....................................27 1.5 An outline of things to come ..............................................29 Chapter 2: Plurality and Nonmaximality 2 Introduction. .. .................................................31 2.1 Distributivity and collectivity .............................................32 2.2 Nonmaximality. 37 2.2.1 Nonmaximality and reciprocals .........................................38 2.2.1.1 Williams, and Heim, Lasnik, and May ............................42 2.2.2 Yoon's theory of the lexicon and weak distributivity .........................45 2.2.3 Taking stock of nonmaximality .........................................50 2.2.3.1 Nonmaximality is affected by lexical meaning ......................50 2.2.3.2 Nonmaximality is affected by the size of the plurality ................50 2.2.3.3 Nonmaximality affects collectives and distributives ..................50 2.2.3.4 Nonmaximality is quantificational ...............................51 vii 2.2.3.5 The form of the DP interacts with nonmaximality ...................51 2.2.3.6 All is incompatible
Recommended publications
  • Anaphoric Reference to Propositions
    ANAPHORIC REFERENCE TO PROPOSITIONS A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Todd Nathaniel Snider December 2017 c 2017 Todd Nathaniel Snider ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ANAPHORIC REFERENCE TO PROPOSITIONS Todd Nathaniel Snider, Ph.D. Cornell University 2017 Just as pronouns like she and he make anaphoric reference to individuals, English words like that and so can be used to refer anaphorically to a proposition introduced in a discourse: That’s true; She told me so. Much has been written about individual anaphora, but less attention has been paid to propositional anaphora. This dissertation is a com- prehensive examination of propositional anaphora, which I argue behaves like anaphora in other domains, is conditioned by semantic factors, and is not conditioned by purely syntactic factors nor by the at-issue status of a proposition. I begin by introducing the concepts of anaphora and propositions, and then I discuss the various words of English which can have this function: this, that, it, which, so, as, and the null complement anaphor. I then compare anaphora to propositions with anaphora in other domains, including individual, temporal, and modal anaphora. I show that the same features which are characteristic of these other domains are exhibited by proposi- tional anaphora as well. I then present data on a wide variety of syntactic constructions—including sub- clausal, monoclausal, multiclausal, and multisentential constructions—noting which li- cense anaphoric reference to propositions. On the basis of this expanded empirical do- main, I argue that anaphoric reference to a proposition is licensed not by any syntactic category or movement but rather by the operators which take propositions as arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Situations and Individuals
    Forthcoming with MIT Press Current Studies in Linguistics Summer 2005 Situations and Individuals Paul Elbourne To my father To the memory of my mother Preface This book deals with the semantics of the natural language expressions that have been taken to refer to individuals: pronouns, definite descriptions and proper names. It claims, contrary to previous theorizing, that they have a common syntax and semantics, roughly that which is currently associated by philosophers and linguists with definite descriptions as construed in the tradition of Frege. As well as advancing this proposal, I hope to achieve at least one other aim, that of urging linguists and philosophers dealing with pronoun interpretation, in particular donkey anaphora, to consider a wider range of theories at all times than is sometimes done at present. I am thinking particularly of the gulf that seems to have emerged between those who practice some version of dynamic semantics (including DRT) and those who eschew this approach and claim that the semantics of donkey pronouns crucially involves definite descriptions (if they consider donkey anaphora at all). In my opinion there is too little work directly comparing the claims of these two schools (for that is what they amount to) and testing them against the data in the way that any two rival theories might be tested. (Irene Heim’s 1990 article in Linguistics and Philosophy does this, and largely inspired my own project, but I know of no other attempts.) I have tried to remedy that in this book. I ultimately come down on the side of definite descriptions and against dynamic semantics; but that preference is really of secondary importance beside the attempt at a systematic comparative project.
    [Show full text]
  • Meanings of Determiners Heading Non-Topic Dps to the Meanings of the Corresponding Topics
    Acknowledgements First of all, I would like to thank my teachers and supervisors Manfred Bierwisch and Reinhard Blutner. Without their sympathetic help in a personally very difficult situation, I would have been unable even to start writing this dissertation. Besides this, they patiently supported me with their advice and experience in every stage of my work. The people that inspired me with discussions and comments are so numerous that there is no hope to mention all of them. Among them are Kai Alter, Daniel Büring, Johannes Dölling, Bernhard Drubig, Hans Martin Gärtner, Edward Göbbel, Michael Herweg, Caroline Heycock, Helen de Hoop, Inga Kohlhof, Manfred Krifka, Annette Lessmöllmann, Christine Maaßen, André Meinunger, Marga Reis, Michal Starke, Markus Steinbach, Wolfgang Sternefeld, Anatoli Strigin, Hubert Truckenbrodt, Enric Vallduví, Ralf Vogel, Chris Wilder, Susanne Winkler, Werner Wolff, Henk Zeevat, and Ede Zimmermann. I am indebted to the "Max-Planck-Gesellschaft" for its financial support. Special thanks go to Elena Demke, Annette Lessmöllmann, Anatoli Strigin, and Chris Wilder for correcting my English. All remaining mistakes are of course subject to my own responsibility. Last but not least, I thank my parents and my brother for everything. Table of Contents 1 Introduction . 1 2 The Dynamic Framework . 5 2.1 Donkey Sentences and Cross-sentential Anaphora . 5 2.2 Montague Semantics and File Change Semantics: A Comparison . 7 2.2.1 Montague Semantics: The General Picture . 7 2.2.2 File Change Semantics: An Overview . 11 2.2.2.1 The Strategy . 11 2.2.2.2 Files . 13 2.2.2.3 LF-Construal . 13 2.2.2.4 The Interpretation of LF .
    [Show full text]
  • Donkey Anaphora Is In-Scope Binding∗
    Semantics & Pragmatics Volume 1, Article 1: 1–46, 2008 doi: 10.3765/sp.1.1 Donkey anaphora is in-scope binding∗ Chris Barker Chung-chieh Shan New York University Rutgers University Received 2008-01-06 = First Decision 2008-02-29 = Revised 2008-03-23 = Second Decision 2008-03-25 = Revised 2008-03-27 = Accepted 2008-03-27 = Published 2008- 06-09 Abstract We propose that the antecedent of a donkey pronoun takes scope over and binds the donkey pronoun, just like any other quantificational antecedent would bind a pronoun. We flesh out this idea in a grammar that compositionally derives the truth conditions of donkey sentences containing conditionals and relative clauses, including those involving modals and proportional quantifiers. For example, an indefinite in the antecedent of a conditional can bind a donkey pronoun in the consequent by taking scope over the entire conditional. Our grammar manages continuations using three independently motivated type-shifters, Lift, Lower, and Bind. Empirical support comes from donkey weak crossover (*He beats it if a farmer owns a donkey): in our system, a quantificational binder need not c-command a pronoun that it binds, but must be evaluated before it, so that donkey weak crossover is just a special case of weak crossover. We compare our approach to situation-based E-type pronoun analyses, as well as to dynamic accounts such as Dynamic Predicate Logic. A new ‘tower’ notation makes derivations considerably easier to follow and manipulate than some previous grammars based on continuations. Keywords: donkey anaphora, continuations, E-type pronoun, type-shifting, scope, quantification, binding, dynamic semantics, weak crossover, donkey pronoun, variable-free, direct compositionality, D-type pronoun, conditionals, situation se- mantics, c-command, dynamic predicate logic, donkey weak crossover ∗ Thanks to substantial input from Anna Chernilovskaya, Brady Clark, Paul Elbourne, Makoto Kanazawa, Chris Kennedy, Thomas Leu, Floris Roelofsen, Daniel Rothschild, Anna Szabolcsi, Eytan Zweig, and three anonymous referees.
    [Show full text]
  • E-Type Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora
    IRENE HElM E-TYPE PRONOUNS AND DONKEY ANAPHORA 0. INTRODUCTION Kamp and Heim intended this proposal to compete with and replace us earlier treatments of the same phenomena, including a family of related proposals by Evans (1977, 1980), Cooper (1979), and others, which in contrast to (i)-(iv) made the following more traditional assumptions: (i) a non-existential, quantifier-free treatment of indefinites, (ii) a treatment of anaphoric pronouns as plain bound variables, (iii) a treatment of quantificational determiners and the conditional operator as capable of binding multiple variables, and (iv) a provision for default existential generalization of free vari- ables. Kamp and Heim intended this proposal to compete with and replace various earlier treatments of the same phenomena, including a family of related proposals by Evans (1977, 1980), Cooper (1979), and others, which in contrast to'(i)-(iv) made the following more traditional assumptions: (i') Indefinites are existential quantifiers. (ii') Anaphoric pronouns are semantically equivalent to (possibly complex) definite descriptions. (iii'.) Quantificational determiners, frequency adverbs, and the hidden operator of generality in conditionals bind just one variable each-. (iv') There is no need for default existential generalization of free variables. (i'), (iii'), and (iv') are, of course, just the standard assumptions from which (i), (iii), and (iv) departed. For the sake of brevity, I will refer to Kamp and Heim's proposal and variants thereof as 'DRT analyses', and to Evans's, Cooper's, and similar proposals as 'E-Type analyses'. ('DRT' abbreviates 'Discourse Represent- ation Theory'; the term 'E-Type' is loosely borrowed from Evans.) Let me caution, however, against unintended interpretations of these labels, especially the first one.
    [Show full text]
  • Compositionality Reconsidered: with Special Reference to Cognition
    Compositionality Reconsidered: With Special Reference to Cognition Chungmin Lee∗y Seoul National University Chungmin Lee. 2012. Compositionality Reconsidered: With Special Reference to Cognition. Language and Information 16.2 , 17{42. The is- sues of compositionality, materialized ever since Frege (1982), are critically re-examined in language first mainly and then in all other possible represen- tational systems such as thoughts, concept combination, computing, gesture, music, and animal cognition. The notion is regarded as necessary and sug- gested as neurologically correlated in humans, even if a weakened version is applicable because of non-articulated constituents and contextuality. Compo- sitionality is crucially involved in all linguistically or non-linguistically mean- ingful expressions, dealing with at-issue content, default content, and even not- at-issue meanings such as implicatures and presuppositions in discourse. It is a constantly guiding principle to show the relation between representation and mind, still posing tantalizing research issues. (Seoul National University) Key words: compositionality, representational systems, contextuality, mind, cognition, thoughts, concept combination, computing, gesture, music, animal cognition 1. Issues on Compositionality This paper purports to be a review but a critical review of issues related to com- positionality, putting forward some direction of more flexible thinking in investi- gations and pointing out subtle cross-linguistic differences in application of com- positionality with Korean examples where relevant. The meaning of an expression is determined by \a function of the meanings of its parts and of the way they are syntactically combined." This is the principle of compositionality in semantics, which largely started from Frege (1892). It can be regarded as \a condition on ∗ We thank Barbara Partee, Wilfrid Hodges and James Pustejovsky for their kind explanation of parts of their papers and comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Functional Structure(S), Form and Interpretation
    FUNCTIONAL STRUCTURE(S), FORM AND INTERPRETATION The issue of how interpretation results from the form and type of syntactic structures present in language is one which is central and hotly debated in both theoretical and descriptive linguistics. This volume brings together a series of eleven new cutting-edge essays by leading experts in East Asian languages which show how the study of formal structures and functional morphemes in Chinese, Japanese and Korean adds much to our general understanding of the close connections between form and interpretation. This specially commissioned collection will be of interest to linguists of all backgrounds working in the general area of syntax and language change, as well as those with a special interest in Chinese, Japanese and Korean. Yen-hui Audrey Li is Professor of Linguistics and East Asian Languages and Cultures at the University of Southern California. Her research focuses on the comparison of grammatical properties in English, Chinese and other East Asian languages. Recent work has considered issues of order and constituency, scope interaction of quantificational expressions, as well as the distribution, structure and interpretation of different types of nominal expressions and relative constructions. Andrew Simpson is a Senior Lecturer at the School of Oriental and African Studies, the University of London. His research interests centre on the comparative syntax of East and Southeast Asian languages, and his work addresses issues relating to processes of language change, DP-structure, the syntax of question formation and the interaction of syntax with phonology. ROUTLEDGECURZON ASIAN LINGUISTICS SERIES Editor-in-Chief: Walter Bisang, Mainz University Associate Editors: R.
    [Show full text]
  • DOMAINS of QUANTIFICATION and SEMANTIC TYPOI.DGY* Barbara
    DOMAINS OF QUANTIFICATION AND SEMANTIC TYPOI.DGY* Barbara H. Partee University of Massachusetts/Amherst 1. Background and central issucsl The questions I am ~oncerned with here arise from the interaction of two broad areas of current research in syntax and semantics. One area, a very old one, concerns the systematic semantic import of syntactic categories, a question requiring a· combination of theoretical work and cross-linguistic study. The other area, only recently under active investigation, concerns the structure and interpretation of expressions of quantification, including not only quantification expressed by NP's with determiners like "every" and "no" but also what Lewis 1975 called "adverbs of quantification" ("always", "in most cases", "usually", etc.), "floated" quantifiers, and quantifiers expressed by verbal affixes and auxiliaries. At the intersection of these two areas are pressing questions which seem ripe for intensive investigation. Some key questions noted by Partee, Bach, and Kratzer 1987 are the following: (1) Is the use of NP's as one means of expressing quantification universal, as proposed by Barwlse and Cooper 1981? Does every language employ some other klnd(s) of quantification? Is there some kind of quantification that every language employs? Our current hypothesis ls that the answer to the first of these questions is llQ., to the second ~; the third ls still entirely open. One goal of current research ls the formulation of a finer-grained, possibly lmplicatlonal hypothesis in place of Barwlse and Cooper's categorical universal. (2) What are the similarities and differences, within and across language.s, in the structure and interpretation of quantification expressed with NP's and quantification expressed with "floated" quantifiers, sentence adverbs, verbal affixes, auxiliaries, or other non-NP means? 1.1 ~ semantics 2.f syntactic categories: background 1.1.1 Traditional linguistics YIL.
    [Show full text]
  • Articulated Definiteness Without Articles
    Articulated definiteness without articles Peter Jenks Abstract While it lacks a definite article, Mandarin makes a principled distinction between unique and anaphoric definites: unique definites are realized with a bare noun, anaphoric definites are realized with a demonstrative, except in subject position. The following proposals account for these facts: 1) bare nouns achieve definite interpretations via a last-resort type-shifting operator ι, which has a unique definite meaning, 2) demon- stratives can occur as anaphoric definiteness because they have a semantic argument beyond their nominal restriction that can be filled by an index, and 3) bare nominal subjects are topics. A principle called Index! requires that indexical expressions be used whenever possible. Mandarin is contrasted with Cantonese, which, like English, is shown to have access to a single, ambiguous, definite article.1 1 Introduction Many of the world’s languages lack definite articles. Instead, bare nouns or other nom- inal expressions are found in definite contexts. Because articles are taken to head a DP projection in languages that have them (Abney 1987; Szabolcsi 1994), a relatively obvious analysis of languages without definite articles is that they lack a DP projection altogether (Boskoviˇ c` 2008, 2012). Such ‘NP-analyses’ have been proposed to be generally appli- cable to numeral classifier languages like Mandarin (e.g. Chierchia 1998; Boskoviˇ c` and Hsieh 2012; Cheng 2013) and Japanese (e.g. Fukui and Takano 2000), languages where bare nouns can receive definite interpretations. But if there is no DP, an alternative source for definite interpretations must be proposed. One option has been a semantically supplied definite type-shifting operation, proposed to be universally available as a kind of repair (Chierchia 1998; Dayal 2004, 2011).
    [Show full text]
  • The Semantics of the Persian Object Marker –Râ
    The Semantics of the Persian Object Marker –râ by Maryam Hosseini Fatemi A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Affairs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Cognitive Science in The Institute of Cognitive Science Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario © 2013, Maryam Hosseini Fatemi Abstract This study presents an analysis of the semantics of the Persian object marker –râ. Semantically, –râ has been identified with definiteness marking (Sadeghi, 1970; Vazinpour, 1977), specificity marking (Browne, 1970; Karimi, 1989, 1990, 1996, 2003a, and 2005) and presupposition marking (Ghomeshi, 1996; Ganjavi, 2007). In this study, I challenge the assumptions presented in previous works and argue that while definiteness, specificity and presupposition capture important aspects of the meaning of –râ, none of them adequately characterize its semantics. Specifically, I argue that a unified account can be given if we assume that –râ is a maximality operator which picks out the maximal member of the denotation of its argument following Link (1983) and Beck and Rullmann (1999). The maximality proposal can account for the appearance of –râ on question words, contrastive topics, donkey sentences, plurals and indefinites which have remained unexplained in previous accounts of –râ. ii Acknowledgement I would like to express my deepest appreciation to my supervisor Professor Raj Singh for his help, guidance and insightful advice. This work would have not been completed without his support and generous help. I am also indebted to my committee members Professor Ida Toivonen, Professor Maria Biezma and Professor Andrés Pablo Salanova for their thoughtful comments and questions. I would also like to thank my fellow graduate friends Pegah Nikravan, Amir Ahmad Anvari and Ehsan Amjadian for their helpful comments and the discussion of data.
    [Show full text]
  • Intonation and Information Structure
    Intonation and Information Structure Klaus von Heusinger Intonation and Information Structure Klaus von Heusinger Habilitationsschrift, accepted by the Faculty of Philosophy, University of Konstanz, June 1999 Bolinger (1964, 282f) compares the complex of intonational features with the up and down motions of waves at the surface of the ocean: The surface of the ocean responds to the forces that act upon it in movements resembling the ups and downs of the human voice. If our vision could take it all in at once, we would discern several types of motion, involving a greater and greater expanse of sea and volume of water: ripples, waves, swells, and tides. It would be more accurate to say ripples on waves on swells on tides, because each larger movement carries the smaller ones on its back (...) In speech (...) the ripples are the accidental changes in pitch, the irrelevant quavers. The waves are the peaks and valleys that we call accent. The swells are the separations of our discourse into its larger segments. The tides are the tides of emotion. Preface This work is the slightly revised version of my Habilitationsschrift, which was accepted by the Faculty of Philosophy at the University of Konstanz in June 1999. The research was funded by a grant of the Dr. Meyer-Struckmann-Stiftung (Habilitation- stipendium der Studienstiftung des Deutschen Volkes). I started my research during 1997 as an affiliate at the Linguistics Research Center of the UC Santa Cruz and continued it as a researcher at the University of Konstanz. This work would not have been possible without the continuous support of my colleagues at Santa Cruz and Konstanz.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 6. Kamp-Heim I. Anaphora with Indefinite Antecedents; Donkey Anaphora
    Formal Semantics and Current Problems of Semantics, Lecture 6 Barbara H. Partee, RGGU, March 18, 2008 p. 1 Lecture 6. Kamp-Heim I. Anaphora with Indefinite Antecedents; Donkey Anaphora. 0. The context of Heim’s dissertation .......................................................................................................................... 1 1. Do indefinites refer?.................................................................................................................................................. 2 1.1. Russell’s view.................................................................................................................................................... 2 1.2. Anaphoric pronouns as bound variables............................................................................................................ 3 1.3. Anaphoric pronouns as picking up speaker’s reference. ................................................................................... 4 1.4. Anaphoric pronouns as disguised definite descriptions. ................................................................................... 6 1.5. Anaphoric pronouns and the ambiguity hypothesis. ......................................................................................... 7 1.6 Summary............................................................................................................................................................. 8 2. Problems with donkey sentences..............................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]