Meanings of Determiners Heading Non-Topic Dps to the Meanings of the Corresponding Topics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Meanings of Determiners Heading Non-Topic Dps to the Meanings of the Corresponding Topics Acknowledgements First of all, I would like to thank my teachers and supervisors Manfred Bierwisch and Reinhard Blutner. Without their sympathetic help in a personally very difficult situation, I would have been unable even to start writing this dissertation. Besides this, they patiently supported me with their advice and experience in every stage of my work. The people that inspired me with discussions and comments are so numerous that there is no hope to mention all of them. Among them are Kai Alter, Daniel Büring, Johannes Dölling, Bernhard Drubig, Hans Martin Gärtner, Edward Göbbel, Michael Herweg, Caroline Heycock, Helen de Hoop, Inga Kohlhof, Manfred Krifka, Annette Lessmöllmann, Christine Maaßen, André Meinunger, Marga Reis, Michal Starke, Markus Steinbach, Wolfgang Sternefeld, Anatoli Strigin, Hubert Truckenbrodt, Enric Vallduví, Ralf Vogel, Chris Wilder, Susanne Winkler, Werner Wolff, Henk Zeevat, and Ede Zimmermann. I am indebted to the "Max-Planck-Gesellschaft" for its financial support. Special thanks go to Elena Demke, Annette Lessmöllmann, Anatoli Strigin, and Chris Wilder for correcting my English. All remaining mistakes are of course subject to my own responsibility. Last but not least, I thank my parents and my brother for everything. Table of Contents 1 Introduction . 1 2 The Dynamic Framework . 5 2.1 Donkey Sentences and Cross-sentential Anaphora . 5 2.2 Montague Semantics and File Change Semantics: A Comparison . 7 2.2.1 Montague Semantics: The General Picture . 7 2.2.2 File Change Semantics: An Overview . 11 2.2.2.1 The Strategy . 11 2.2.2.2 Files . 13 2.2.2.3 LF-Construal . 13 2.2.2.4 The Interpretation of LF . 18 2.2.2.5 Comparing MS and FCS . 24 2.3 Extensional Dynamic Predicate Logic . 26 2.3.1 The Syntax of EDPL . 26 2.3.2 Contexts . 27 2.3.3 The Semantics of EDPL . 31 2.3.4 Truth and Entailment in EDPL . 38 2.4 Dynamic Extensional Type Theory . 42 2.4.1 The Syntax of DETT . 43 2.4.2 Models, Domains and Contexts . 45 2.4.3 The Semantics of DETT . 46 2.4.4 DETT and DIL . 54 2.5 Interpreting English with DETT . 55 3 Topic-Comment-Articulation and Definiteness . 68 3.1 Definiteness = Familiarity? . 68 3.1.1 Heim's Theory of Definiteness . 68 3.1.2 Anaphoric and Referential Definites . 70 3.1.3 Topics and German Scrambling . 71 3.1.4 Associative Anaphoric Definites . 74 3.2 A Dynamic Approach to Definiteness . 75 3.2.1 Flexible Domains: The Peg System . 75 3.2.2 Referential Definites . 82 3.2.3 Unifying the Anaphoric and the Referential Reading . 83 3.3 DETT Augmented with a Peg System . 87 3.3.1 Contexts and Updates . 88 3.3.2 The Semantics of DITT . 92 3.4 A Compositional Treatment of Topicality and Bridging . 95 3.4.1 Indefinites and Pronouns . 95 3.4.2 Referential Definites . 96 3.4.3 Anaphoric Definites . 99 3.4.4 Donkey Sentences with Definite Descriptions and the E-Type Strategy . 102 3.4.5 Bridging without Accommodation . 107 3.5 Summary . 112 3.6 Loose Ends . 116 3.6.1 Pronouns . 116 3.6.2 Definite Descriptions and Bridging . 117 4 Indefinite Topics . 122 4.1 Partitive Readings . 122 4.1.1 Enç's Proposal . 122 4.1.2 Plural . 125 4.1.3 Weak Quantifiers . 129 4.1.3.1 Syntax . 129 4.1.3.2 Semantics . 130 4.1.3.3 Intonation and Focus . 133 4.1.4 Summary and Discussion . 137 4.1.5 Appendix . 140 4.2 The Proportion Problem . 143 4.2.1 Ambiguities in Donkey Sentences . 143 4.2.2 A Situation-based Approach: Berman['87] . 147 4.2.3 Selective Binding: Chierchia['92] . 149 4.2.4 A Synthesis: Proportions in DITT . 152 4.3 Conclusion and Desiderata . 159 Bibliograpy . 162 Chapter One: Introduction This dissertation deals with several phenomena usually subsumed under the category of (in)definiteness. There are nearly as many proposals on how to describe this category semantically as there are semantic frameworks. In traditional truth-conditional semantics from Russell to Montague, it is assumed that indefinites express an existential statement, while definites additionally carry some uniqueness requirement. More recent approaches like Discourse Representation Theory (Kamp['81], Kamp & Reyle['93]) or File Change Semantics (Heim['82]) prefer to assume that definites and indefinites perform different actions on some discourse model. As a common integrator, most influential semantic frameworks consider definiteness to be a central issue of semantic theory. One might wonder whether this dichotomy is really that important after all. There is a considerable number of languages that do well without any marking of definiteness, and even in languages such as English and German, where the contrast is expressed morphologically, it is highly redundant. (I was once told a very illuminating story1 about a Japanese woman living in Germany who knew German superficially very well. She never used any articles. Her German colleagues not only failed to miss them, they even failed to notice it at all.) Of course the communicative redundancy of definiteness does not suffice to prove its theoretical marginality. There are quite many widespread phenomena in different languages that are prima facie related to definiteness. They are usually covered with the notion of "Definiteness Effect". We do not intend to investigate these systematically here, but it is questionable whether this term is really appropriate. As an example, the most prominent instance, English there-constructions, is obviously not related to definiteness at all. (1) a. There is only John in the garden. b. There was the biggest car I've ever seen in front of his house. (Chris Wilder, p.c.) I am not aware of any definition of indefiniteness that covers only John or the biggest car I©ve ever seen. Whatever the category is the coda of there-sentences is sensitive for, it is not definiteness. Similar considrations arise when we consider scrambling in German2 , another alleged 1by Manfred Pinkal (p.c.) 2To be precise, there are (at least) two kinds of scrambling in German. One is very similar to I- topicalization, i.e. the scrambled item receives a heavy rising accent, and if scope-bearing items are involved, we have an inverted interpretation. All kinds of maximal projections, including remnant VPs can be affected by (continued...) I P Chapter 1. Introduction instance of the Definiteness Effect. Several authors (Lenerz['77], Reis['87], and, more recently, Büring['94]) have proposed that in German, the surface position of arguments inside or outside VP is largely determined by definiteness. Provided that no focus- or animacy- effects intervene, definite subjects and objects have to occur in a VP-external position, while indefinites remain in situ. Most data support this view. (2) a. Peter hat gestern ein Buch gekauft. Peter has yesterday a book bought b.??? Peter hat ein Buch gestern gekauft Peter has a book yesterday bought 'Yesterday, Peter bought a book' (3) a.??? Peter hat gestern das Buch gekauft. Peter has yesterday the book bought b. Peter hat das Buch gestern gekauft Peter has the book yesterday bought 'Peter bought the book yesterday' If we assume that the adverb gestern 'yesterday' marks the VP-boundary, the indefinite object is preferred in the VP-internal position and the definite one in the VP-external position. Nevertheless, there are counterexamples. Name-like definites like die Bibel 'the Bible' are allowed in both positions equally well, and specific indefinites occur in scrambled positions. (4) a. Peter hat gestern die Bibel gekauft. Peter has yesterday the Bible bought b. Peter hat die Bibel gestern gekauft Peter has the Bible yesterday bought 'Yesterday, Peter bought the Bible' (5) a. Hans hat einen bestimmten Studenten noch nie gesehen. 2(...continued) this process. (i) (weil) das [ FREIwillig] / NIEmand \ t tun würde AP i i (since) this voluntarily nobody do would 'Since nobody would do this voluntarily' (ii) weil mit SIcherheit / NIEmand \ t die Wahrheit kennt i i since with security nobody the truth knows 'Since nobody knows the truth for sure' We are only interested in the second kind of scrambling which is restricted to DPs and some PPs, involves only deaccentuation of the scrambled item and does not give rise to scope inversion. Q Hans has a certain student still never seen b.* Hans hat noch nie einen bestimmten Studenten gesehen. Hans has still never a certain student seen 'There is a certain student that Hans never saw' As it turns out, there are other factors scrambling is sensitive to that usually coincide with definiteness, but sometimes the distinctions are orthogonal to each other. There is a lot of recent crosslinguistic work that shows that this property of scrambling is not a pure idiosyncrasy of German. Comparable observations can be made for Dutch (de Hoop['93]) and - more unexpectedly - Cashmerese (Rajesh Bhatt, p.c.). Meinunger['95] shows convincingly that for instance case alternation phenomena in Finnish and Russian and clitic doubling in Romance and Bantu-languages should be treated on a par with scrambling. This enables us to assume that there is another dichotomy besides (in)definiteness that is responsible for the mentioned contrasts. I decided to call those items that are marked by scrambling/ structural case/ clitic doubling Topic, but the nomenclature is of minor importance. Probably, there is a kind of feature specification default that requires definites to be Topics and indefinites to be non-Topics, but there are exceptions in both directions. It is very likely that the category Topic is universally present, while there is no need to assume that languages that do not express definiteness morphologically have that category at all.
Recommended publications
  • Anaphoric Reference to Propositions
    ANAPHORIC REFERENCE TO PROPOSITIONS A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Todd Nathaniel Snider December 2017 c 2017 Todd Nathaniel Snider ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ANAPHORIC REFERENCE TO PROPOSITIONS Todd Nathaniel Snider, Ph.D. Cornell University 2017 Just as pronouns like she and he make anaphoric reference to individuals, English words like that and so can be used to refer anaphorically to a proposition introduced in a discourse: That’s true; She told me so. Much has been written about individual anaphora, but less attention has been paid to propositional anaphora. This dissertation is a com- prehensive examination of propositional anaphora, which I argue behaves like anaphora in other domains, is conditioned by semantic factors, and is not conditioned by purely syntactic factors nor by the at-issue status of a proposition. I begin by introducing the concepts of anaphora and propositions, and then I discuss the various words of English which can have this function: this, that, it, which, so, as, and the null complement anaphor. I then compare anaphora to propositions with anaphora in other domains, including individual, temporal, and modal anaphora. I show that the same features which are characteristic of these other domains are exhibited by proposi- tional anaphora as well. I then present data on a wide variety of syntactic constructions—including sub- clausal, monoclausal, multiclausal, and multisentential constructions—noting which li- cense anaphoric reference to propositions. On the basis of this expanded empirical do- main, I argue that anaphoric reference to a proposition is licensed not by any syntactic category or movement but rather by the operators which take propositions as arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Situations and Individuals
    Forthcoming with MIT Press Current Studies in Linguistics Summer 2005 Situations and Individuals Paul Elbourne To my father To the memory of my mother Preface This book deals with the semantics of the natural language expressions that have been taken to refer to individuals: pronouns, definite descriptions and proper names. It claims, contrary to previous theorizing, that they have a common syntax and semantics, roughly that which is currently associated by philosophers and linguists with definite descriptions as construed in the tradition of Frege. As well as advancing this proposal, I hope to achieve at least one other aim, that of urging linguists and philosophers dealing with pronoun interpretation, in particular donkey anaphora, to consider a wider range of theories at all times than is sometimes done at present. I am thinking particularly of the gulf that seems to have emerged between those who practice some version of dynamic semantics (including DRT) and those who eschew this approach and claim that the semantics of donkey pronouns crucially involves definite descriptions (if they consider donkey anaphora at all). In my opinion there is too little work directly comparing the claims of these two schools (for that is what they amount to) and testing them against the data in the way that any two rival theories might be tested. (Irene Heim’s 1990 article in Linguistics and Philosophy does this, and largely inspired my own project, but I know of no other attempts.) I have tried to remedy that in this book. I ultimately come down on the side of definite descriptions and against dynamic semantics; but that preference is really of secondary importance beside the attempt at a systematic comparative project.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 5. Formal Semantics and the Lexicon. Meaning Postulates And
    Topics in Formal Semantics, Lecture 5 Topics in Formal Semantics, Lecture 5 B.H. Partee, MGU, March 22, 2005 B.H. Partee, MGU, March 22, 2005 Lecture 5. Formal semantics and the lexicon. Ideally, this abstraction should mirror a “real” abstraction which our “language faculty” Meaning postulates and the lexicon. Adjective meanings. imposes on the real world, “natural language metaphysics” or “naïve picture of the world” (naivnaja kartina mira in the terminology of Moscow semantic school). We will discuss this later when considering the integration of formal and lexical semantics. 1. The Lexicon in Model-theoretic Semantics. .................................................................................................1 1.1. Languages, world, models. Axioms.............................................................................................................1 In Montague’s formal semantics the simple predicates of the language of intensional 1.2. Axioms and theories. ..................................................................................................................................2 logic (IL), like love, like, kiss, see, etc., are regarded as symbols (similar to the “labels” of 2. Integrating formal semantics, lexical semantics, natural language metaphysics ...............................................4 PC) which could have many possible interpretations in many different models, their “real 2.1. Formal semantics in the broader setting of natural language use. ...............................................................4
    [Show full text]
  • Donkey Anaphora Is In-Scope Binding∗
    Semantics & Pragmatics Volume 1, Article 1: 1–46, 2008 doi: 10.3765/sp.1.1 Donkey anaphora is in-scope binding∗ Chris Barker Chung-chieh Shan New York University Rutgers University Received 2008-01-06 = First Decision 2008-02-29 = Revised 2008-03-23 = Second Decision 2008-03-25 = Revised 2008-03-27 = Accepted 2008-03-27 = Published 2008- 06-09 Abstract We propose that the antecedent of a donkey pronoun takes scope over and binds the donkey pronoun, just like any other quantificational antecedent would bind a pronoun. We flesh out this idea in a grammar that compositionally derives the truth conditions of donkey sentences containing conditionals and relative clauses, including those involving modals and proportional quantifiers. For example, an indefinite in the antecedent of a conditional can bind a donkey pronoun in the consequent by taking scope over the entire conditional. Our grammar manages continuations using three independently motivated type-shifters, Lift, Lower, and Bind. Empirical support comes from donkey weak crossover (*He beats it if a farmer owns a donkey): in our system, a quantificational binder need not c-command a pronoun that it binds, but must be evaluated before it, so that donkey weak crossover is just a special case of weak crossover. We compare our approach to situation-based E-type pronoun analyses, as well as to dynamic accounts such as Dynamic Predicate Logic. A new ‘tower’ notation makes derivations considerably easier to follow and manipulate than some previous grammars based on continuations. Keywords: donkey anaphora, continuations, E-type pronoun, type-shifting, scope, quantification, binding, dynamic semantics, weak crossover, donkey pronoun, variable-free, direct compositionality, D-type pronoun, conditionals, situation se- mantics, c-command, dynamic predicate logic, donkey weak crossover ∗ Thanks to substantial input from Anna Chernilovskaya, Brady Clark, Paul Elbourne, Makoto Kanazawa, Chris Kennedy, Thomas Leu, Floris Roelofsen, Daniel Rothschild, Anna Szabolcsi, Eytan Zweig, and three anonymous referees.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantic and Metasemantic Notions of Analyticity
    Asian Social Science; Vol. 10, No. 22; 2014 ISSN 1911-2017 E-ISSN 1911-2025 Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education Semantic and Metasemantic Notions of Analyticity Artur Ravilevich Karimov1 & Valentina Alexandrovna Kazakova2 1 Kazan Federal University, Russian Federation 2 Kazan State University of Architecture and Engineering, Russian Federation Correspondence: Artur Ravilevich Karimov, Kazan Federal University, 420008, Kremlevskaya 18, Kazan, Russian Federation. E-mail: [email protected] Received: August 1, 2014 Accepted: August 18, 2014 Online Published: October 30, 2014 doi:10.5539/ass.v10n22p285 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.5539/ass.v10n22p285 Abstract In this article the evolution of main conceptions of analyticity is analyzed. Kant’s criteria for analytic/synthetic distinction are discussed. Frege and Carnap notions of analyticity are set out. It is shown that Frege and Carnap shifted the criteria of analyticity to the justificatory status of judgments. The notion of truth in virtue of meaning and its criticism is exposed. Critical arguments against analyticity by W. V. O. Quine are discussed. Williamson’s arguments against traditional notions of analyticity are formulated. Williamson maintains that analytic truths are reduced to truths of other base classes-necessary, semantic or logical. It is shown that the stipulative definition of analyticity is vulnerable to Williamson’s argument. Russell’s conception of truth in virtue of reference determiner is exposed and evaluated. It is defended that the notion of truth in virtue of reference determiner is immune to many standard objections against analyticity. Keywords: analyticity, meaning, stipulation, reference 1. Introduction Analyticity is one the most controversial concepts in the history of analytic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • E-Type Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora
    IRENE HElM E-TYPE PRONOUNS AND DONKEY ANAPHORA 0. INTRODUCTION Kamp and Heim intended this proposal to compete with and replace us earlier treatments of the same phenomena, including a family of related proposals by Evans (1977, 1980), Cooper (1979), and others, which in contrast to (i)-(iv) made the following more traditional assumptions: (i) a non-existential, quantifier-free treatment of indefinites, (ii) a treatment of anaphoric pronouns as plain bound variables, (iii) a treatment of quantificational determiners and the conditional operator as capable of binding multiple variables, and (iv) a provision for default existential generalization of free vari- ables. Kamp and Heim intended this proposal to compete with and replace various earlier treatments of the same phenomena, including a family of related proposals by Evans (1977, 1980), Cooper (1979), and others, which in contrast to'(i)-(iv) made the following more traditional assumptions: (i') Indefinites are existential quantifiers. (ii') Anaphoric pronouns are semantically equivalent to (possibly complex) definite descriptions. (iii'.) Quantificational determiners, frequency adverbs, and the hidden operator of generality in conditionals bind just one variable each-. (iv') There is no need for default existential generalization of free variables. (i'), (iii'), and (iv') are, of course, just the standard assumptions from which (i), (iii), and (iv) departed. For the sake of brevity, I will refer to Kamp and Heim's proposal and variants thereof as 'DRT analyses', and to Evans's, Cooper's, and similar proposals as 'E-Type analyses'. ('DRT' abbreviates 'Discourse Represent- ation Theory'; the term 'E-Type' is loosely borrowed from Evans.) Let me caution, however, against unintended interpretations of these labels, especially the first one.
    [Show full text]
  • Compositionality Reconsidered: with Special Reference to Cognition
    Compositionality Reconsidered: With Special Reference to Cognition Chungmin Lee∗y Seoul National University Chungmin Lee. 2012. Compositionality Reconsidered: With Special Reference to Cognition. Language and Information 16.2 , 17{42. The is- sues of compositionality, materialized ever since Frege (1982), are critically re-examined in language first mainly and then in all other possible represen- tational systems such as thoughts, concept combination, computing, gesture, music, and animal cognition. The notion is regarded as necessary and sug- gested as neurologically correlated in humans, even if a weakened version is applicable because of non-articulated constituents and contextuality. Compo- sitionality is crucially involved in all linguistically or non-linguistically mean- ingful expressions, dealing with at-issue content, default content, and even not- at-issue meanings such as implicatures and presuppositions in discourse. It is a constantly guiding principle to show the relation between representation and mind, still posing tantalizing research issues. (Seoul National University) Key words: compositionality, representational systems, contextuality, mind, cognition, thoughts, concept combination, computing, gesture, music, animal cognition 1. Issues on Compositionality This paper purports to be a review but a critical review of issues related to com- positionality, putting forward some direction of more flexible thinking in investi- gations and pointing out subtle cross-linguistic differences in application of com- positionality with Korean examples where relevant. The meaning of an expression is determined by \a function of the meanings of its parts and of the way they are syntactically combined." This is the principle of compositionality in semantics, which largely started from Frege (1892). It can be regarded as \a condition on ∗ We thank Barbara Partee, Wilfrid Hodges and James Pustejovsky for their kind explanation of parts of their papers and comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Functional Structure(S), Form and Interpretation
    FUNCTIONAL STRUCTURE(S), FORM AND INTERPRETATION The issue of how interpretation results from the form and type of syntactic structures present in language is one which is central and hotly debated in both theoretical and descriptive linguistics. This volume brings together a series of eleven new cutting-edge essays by leading experts in East Asian languages which show how the study of formal structures and functional morphemes in Chinese, Japanese and Korean adds much to our general understanding of the close connections between form and interpretation. This specially commissioned collection will be of interest to linguists of all backgrounds working in the general area of syntax and language change, as well as those with a special interest in Chinese, Japanese and Korean. Yen-hui Audrey Li is Professor of Linguistics and East Asian Languages and Cultures at the University of Southern California. Her research focuses on the comparison of grammatical properties in English, Chinese and other East Asian languages. Recent work has considered issues of order and constituency, scope interaction of quantificational expressions, as well as the distribution, structure and interpretation of different types of nominal expressions and relative constructions. Andrew Simpson is a Senior Lecturer at the School of Oriental and African Studies, the University of London. His research interests centre on the comparative syntax of East and Southeast Asian languages, and his work addresses issues relating to processes of language change, DP-structure, the syntax of question formation and the interaction of syntax with phonology. ROUTLEDGECURZON ASIAN LINGUISTICS SERIES Editor-in-Chief: Walter Bisang, Mainz University Associate Editors: R.
    [Show full text]
  • Three Approaches of Word Sentence Meaning in Translation of English Slang Word Into Indonesian in the Novel “The Adventure of Oliver Twist”
    THREE APPROACHES OF WORD SENTENCE MEANING IN TRANSLATION OF ENGLISH SLANG WORD INTO INDONESIAN IN THE NOVEL “THE ADVENTURE OF OLIVER TWIST” Ni Putu Wintia Sunny Kumara Sakti Villa Jln. Suweta Banjar Sambahan Ubud Phone: +62 361 437806 , Celular Phone: +62 89685689099 [email protected] ABSRACT The slang expression means coming to democratic atmosphere in language since the meaning embodied is not absolute. It depends upon who uses it, in which group the users belong to, and in what situation slang word occur. Having knowledge of slang, it means the user is bilingual, or even multilingual. The question emerged is how the user of slang employ slang in their daily communication. Their choice of certain slang replacing the standard may have a certain purposes. Therefore, it is really difficult to translate it in Indonesian. How to transfer the meaning of slang that contains senses about culture, habit, and identity of specific group of people is a complex undertaking. The form of English slang used in the novel "The Adventure of Oliver Twist” by Charles Dickens is generally in the form of primary slang. There were sixteen primary slang words uttered by the character in the novel. However, there was only four secondary slang words found in the novel. So the primary slang more common used by the character in novel. There are three approaches that can be used to find the conceptual meaning of word in the process of translation. There are reference theory, componential analysis, and meaning postulate. Keywords: slang word, reference theory, componential analysis, meaning postulate. ABSTRAK Kata Slang merupakan expresi demokratis dalam bahasa yang menganduk makna tidak mutlak.
    [Show full text]
  • Problems in the Representation of the Logical Form of Generics, Plurals, and Mass Nouns
    12 Problems in the Representation of the Logical Form of Generics, Plurals, and Mass Nouns LENHART K. SCHUBERT FRANCIS JEFFRY PELLETIER Department of Computing Science University of Alberta INTRODUCTION We wish to discuss some problems involved in representing the 'logical form' of sentences whose subjects are generics, (bare) plurals and mass terms. We shall not here have much to say about the syntax of such sentences, except occasionally to refer to such (arguably) syntactic features as [ ±stative]. We shall also not get embroiled in such issues as exactly what information should be counted as part of the 'logical form' of a sentence in general. We will, for example, remain agnostic on the question of the proper place for (Montague-style) meaning postulates, the proper place for Quantifier Raising, and the proper place for the representation of certain ambiguities involving quantifiers and other logical operations. Instead, om concern is with the final representation of certain natural language sentences, a represe11tation which is immediately correlated with the truth conditions of the original sentence. We take this to be more-or-less first­ order quantification theory augmented with certain operators, but feel free to bring in Montagovian intensional logic, expecial!y when discussing those 385 NEW DIREcnONS IN SEMANTICS Copyright© 1987. by Academic Press Inc. (London) Ltd. A I! ..;~1.•~ ~f ••~•...,.1.,.-.;~n ;" ~nv fn~ ••~•~, • .-1 386 L. K. Schubert and F. J~ Pelletier theorists who make it central in their account. To give a feel for what level our concerns lie at, consider (1) (a) Whales are mammals Now, there are many 'levels of representation' that different theorists have proposed for such a sentence.
    [Show full text]
  • DOMAINS of QUANTIFICATION and SEMANTIC TYPOI.DGY* Barbara
    DOMAINS OF QUANTIFICATION AND SEMANTIC TYPOI.DGY* Barbara H. Partee University of Massachusetts/Amherst 1. Background and central issucsl The questions I am ~oncerned with here arise from the interaction of two broad areas of current research in syntax and semantics. One area, a very old one, concerns the systematic semantic import of syntactic categories, a question requiring a· combination of theoretical work and cross-linguistic study. The other area, only recently under active investigation, concerns the structure and interpretation of expressions of quantification, including not only quantification expressed by NP's with determiners like "every" and "no" but also what Lewis 1975 called "adverbs of quantification" ("always", "in most cases", "usually", etc.), "floated" quantifiers, and quantifiers expressed by verbal affixes and auxiliaries. At the intersection of these two areas are pressing questions which seem ripe for intensive investigation. Some key questions noted by Partee, Bach, and Kratzer 1987 are the following: (1) Is the use of NP's as one means of expressing quantification universal, as proposed by Barwlse and Cooper 1981? Does every language employ some other klnd(s) of quantification? Is there some kind of quantification that every language employs? Our current hypothesis ls that the answer to the first of these questions is llQ., to the second ~; the third ls still entirely open. One goal of current research ls the formulation of a finer-grained, possibly lmplicatlonal hypothesis in place of Barwlse and Cooper's categorical universal. (2) What are the similarities and differences, within and across language.s, in the structure and interpretation of quantification expressed with NP's and quantification expressed with "floated" quantifiers, sentence adverbs, verbal affixes, auxiliaries, or other non-NP means? 1.1 ~ semantics 2.f syntactic categories: background 1.1.1 Traditional linguistics YIL.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Semantics of Propositional Attitude Reports
    GOTHENBURG MONOGRAPHS IN LINGUISTICS 13 ON THE SEMANTICS OF PROPOSITIONAL ATTITUDE REPORTS Mats DahllofÈ ¡¢ £ ¤ Department of Linguistics GoteborÈ g University, Sweden 1995 ABSTRACT This is a study on the truth-conditional semantics of propositional attitude attribution statements. It is suggested that attitude contents should be characterized in terms of abstract concepts, which are connected by way of a number of basic logical relations derived from a version of Quinean predicate-functor logic. This allows us to handle all logical relationships de®nable by ®rst-order predicate calculus in a way that does not exploit variable-like entities. Individual, predicate, and propositional concepts are recognized. These concepts provide the relata of various mental attitude relations and may denote (or may fail to denote) other kinds of object. The resulting framework is itself formalized in ®rst-order predicate calculus. This proposal is intended to give an account that is to a high degree independent of any particular view of the metaphysical, psychological or epistemological status of propositional attitude reports. An overview of different kinds of propositional and other conceptual attitude report constructions in English is given and it is suggested how the framework proposed can be applied to them. KEY WORDS: Meaning, Semantics, Logic, Propositional Attitudes, Truth Conditions, Intentions, Concepts, Reference, Predicate-Functor Logic, Intentionality Published by: The Department of Linguistics, GoteborÈ g University, 412 98 GoteborÈ g, Sweden.
    [Show full text]