On the Semantics of Propositional Attitude Reports

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On the Semantics of Propositional Attitude Reports GOTHENBURG MONOGRAPHS IN LINGUISTICS 13 ON THE SEMANTICS OF PROPOSITIONAL ATTITUDE REPORTS Mats DahllofÈ ¡¢ £ ¤ Department of Linguistics GoteborÈ g University, Sweden 1995 ABSTRACT This is a study on the truth-conditional semantics of propositional attitude attribution statements. It is suggested that attitude contents should be characterized in terms of abstract concepts, which are connected by way of a number of basic logical relations derived from a version of Quinean predicate-functor logic. This allows us to handle all logical relationships de®nable by ®rst-order predicate calculus in a way that does not exploit variable-like entities. Individual, predicate, and propositional concepts are recognized. These concepts provide the relata of various mental attitude relations and may denote (or may fail to denote) other kinds of object. The resulting framework is itself formalized in ®rst-order predicate calculus. This proposal is intended to give an account that is to a high degree independent of any particular view of the metaphysical, psychological or epistemological status of propositional attitude reports. An overview of different kinds of propositional and other conceptual attitude report constructions in English is given and it is suggested how the framework proposed can be applied to them. KEY WORDS: Meaning, Semantics, Logic, Propositional Attitudes, Truth Conditions, Intentions, Concepts, Reference, Predicate-Functor Logic, Intentionality Published by: The Department of Linguistics, GoteborÈ g University, 412 98 GoteborÈ g, Sweden. ¥ c 1995 Mats DahllofÈ ISBN 91-972408-7-7 CONTENTS PREFACE ¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦ vii 1 INTRODUCTION ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦ 1 1.1 Language and Propositional Attitudes ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦ 1 1.2 The Importance of Propositional Attitude Reports ¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 2 1.3 Goals ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 3 1.4 Outline of the Thesis ¦ ¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦ 3 2 TRUTH-CONDITIONAL SEMANTICS ¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 4 2.1 Introduction ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 4 2.2 Truth ¦ ¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 4 2.3 Ontology ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 7 2.4 Goals of Linguistics ¦¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 10 2.5 Linguistic Analysis ¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 11 2.6 Language as a System ¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 13 2.7 Truth-Conditional Analysis ¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦ 14 2.7.1 The Justi®cation of Semantic Analyses ¦ ¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 17 2.7.2 The Principle of Charity ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦ 18 2.7.3 Truth and Interpretation ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦ 19 2.7.4 BTC-meaning ¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 20 2.7.5 Non-Declarative Discourse ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 23 2.8 Concluding Remarks ¦¨¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 25 ii 3 APPROACHES TO PROPOSITIONAL ATTITUDE REPORT SEMANTICS ¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦ 26 3.1 Introduction ¦¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦ 26 3.2 Propositional Attitude Psychology ¦ ¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦ 27 3.3 Behaviourist Approaches to Propositional Attitude Attribution ¦¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 29 3.4 Propositional Attitudes as Involving Propositions ¦¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 30 3.4.1 Propositions ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 30 3.4.2 The Impersonal Nature of Propositions ¦¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 32 3.4.3 Truth, Falsity and Logical Properties ¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 33 3.4.4 Propositions and Reference to Objects ¦ ¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦ 33 3.4.5 Propositions and Their Independence from Attitudes ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦ 34 3.4.6 The Individuation of Propositions ¦ ¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 34 3.4.7 Different Conceptions of What a Proposition Is ¦ ¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 35 3.4.8 Non-Propositional Mental Attitudes ¦ ¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 36 3.5 The Semantic Features of Intensional Contexts ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 36 3.5.1 Failures of Substitutivity ¦¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦ 37 3.5.2 Readings De Dicto and De Re ¦¨¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 38 3.5.3 Speci®city ¦ ¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 41 3.5.4 Other Sources of Ambiguity ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 42 3.5.5 Internal and External Signi®cance of Content ¦ ¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦ 44 3.6 Non-Binary Analyses of Propositional Attitudes ¦ ¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 45 3.7 Frege's Gedanken ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 48 3.7.1 Frege's Platonism ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 49 3.7.2 Sinn and Bedeutung ¦ ¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦ 50 3.8 Sententialist Accounts of Propositional Attitudes ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦ 57 3.8.1 Intensional Isomorphism and Structured Meanings ¦ ¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 62 3.9 Davidson's Paratactic Approach ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 62 3.10 Facts and Situations ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦ 66 3.11 Possible Worlds ¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦ 71 3.12 Reference and Propositional Attitudes ¦¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦ 75 3.12.1 Names and Descriptions ¦ ¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 76 3.12.2 Causality and Indexicality ¦ ¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 78 3.13 Concluding Remarks ¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦ 82 iii 4 DERIVING SYSTEMS OF CONCEPTS FROM PREDICATE-FUNCTOR LOGIC ¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦ 86 4.1 Introduction ¦¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦ 86 4.2 Quanti®cation ¦ ¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 91 4.3 Predicate-Functor Logic ¦ ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦ 96 4.3.1 The Syntax of PFLST ¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦ 99 4.3.1.1 The Syntax of Singular Terms ¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 100 4.3.1.2 The Syntax of Predicate Terms ¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦ 100 4.3.1.3 The Syntax of Formulae ¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦ 101 4.3.2 The Semantics of PFLST ¦©¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 101 4.3.2.1 The Denotation of Predicate Terms ¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 101 4.3.2.2 The Denotation of Formulae ¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦ 102 4.3.3 The Elimination of Variables ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 103 4.4 The Concept System ¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦ 107 4.4.1 A Truth Theory for Propositional Concepts ¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦ 111 4.4.1.1 Combinatorial Constraints ¦ ¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦ 111 4.4.1.2 De®nitions of Auxiliary Predicates ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦ 114 4.4.1.3 Denotation and Truth ¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦¨¦§¦§¦§¦§¦©¦§¦§¦§¦
Recommended publications
  • Semantics and Pragmatics
    Semantics and Pragmatics Christopher Gauker Semantics deals with the literal meaning of sentences. Pragmatics deals with what speakers mean by their utterances of sentences over and above what those sentences literally mean. However, it is not always clear where to draw the line. Natural languages contain many expressions that may be thought of both as contributing to literal meaning and as devices by which speakers signal what they mean. After characterizing the aims of semantics and pragmatics, this chapter will set out the issues concerning such devices and will propose a way of dividing the labor between semantics and pragmatics. Disagreements about the purview of semantics and pragmatics often concern expressions of which we may say that their interpretation somehow depends on the context in which they are used. Thus: • The interpretation of a sentence containing a demonstrative, as in “This is nice”, depends on a contextually-determined reference of the demonstrative. • The interpretation of a quantified sentence, such as “Everyone is present”, depends on a contextually-determined domain of discourse. • The interpretation of a sentence containing a gradable adjective, as in “Dumbo is small”, depends on a contextually-determined standard (Kennedy 2007). • The interpretation of a sentence containing an incomplete predicate, as in “Tipper is ready”, may depend on a contextually-determined completion. Semantics and Pragmatics 8/4/10 Page 2 • The interpretation of a sentence containing a discourse particle such as “too”, as in “Dennis is having dinner in London tonight too”, may depend on a contextually determined set of background propositions (Gauker 2008a). • The interpretation of a sentence employing metonymy, such as “The ham sandwich wants his check”, depends on a contextually-determined relation of reference-shifting.
    [Show full text]
  • Reference and Sense
    REFERENCE AND SENSE y two distinct ways of talking about the meaning of words y tlkitalking of SENSE=deali ng with relationshippggs inside language y talking of REFERENCE=dealing with reltilations hips bbtetween l. and the world y by means of reference a speaker indicates which things (including persons) are being talked about ege.g. My son is in the beech tree. II identifies persons identifies things y REFERENCE-relationship between the Enggplish expression ‘this p pgage’ and the thing you can hold between your finger and thumb (part of the world) y your left ear is the REFERENT of the phrase ‘your left ear’ while REFERENCE is the relationship between parts of a l. and things outside the l. y The same expression can be used to refer to different things- there are as many potential referents for the phrase ‘your left ear’ as there are pppeople in the world with left ears Many expressions can have VARIABLE REFERENCE y There are cases of expressions which in normal everyday conversation never refer to different things, i.e. which in most everyday situations that one can envisage have CONSTANT REFERENCE. y However, there is very little constancy of reference in l. Almost all of the fixing of reference comes from the context in which expressions are used. y Two different expressions can have the same referent class ica l example: ‘the MiMorning St’Star’ and ‘the Evening Star’ to refer to the planet Venus y SENSE of an expression is its place in a system of semantic relati onshi ps wit h other expressions in the l.
    [Show full text]
  • The Meaning of Language
    01:615:201 Introduction to Linguistic Theory Adam Szczegielniak The Meaning of Language Copyright in part: Cengage learning The Meaning of Language • When you know a language you know: • When a word is meaningful or meaningless, when a word has two meanings, when two words have the same meaning, and what words refer to (in the real world or imagination) • When a sentence is meaningful or meaningless, when a sentence has two meanings, when two sentences have the same meaning, and whether a sentence is true or false (the truth conditions of the sentence) • Semantics is the study of the meaning of morphemes, words, phrases, and sentences – Lexical semantics: the meaning of words and the relationships among words – Phrasal or sentential semantics: the meaning of syntactic units larger than one word Truth • Compositional semantics: formulating semantic rules that build the meaning of a sentence based on the meaning of the words and how they combine – Also known as truth-conditional semantics because the speaker’ s knowledge of truth conditions is central Truth • If you know the meaning of a sentence, you can determine under what conditions it is true or false – You don’ t need to know whether or not a sentence is true or false to understand it, so knowing the meaning of a sentence means knowing under what circumstances it would be true or false • Most sentences are true or false depending on the situation – But some sentences are always true (tautologies) – And some are always false (contradictions) Entailment and Related Notions • Entailment: one sentence entails another if whenever the first sentence is true the second one must be true also Jack swims beautifully.
    [Show full text]
  • Two-Dimensionalism: Semantics and Metasemantics
    Two-Dimensionalism: Semantics and Metasemantics YEUNG, \y,ang -C-hun ...:' . '",~ ... ~ .. A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Philosophy In Philosophy The Chinese University of Hong Kong January 2010 Abstract of thesis entitled: Two-Dimensionalism: Semantics and Metasemantics Submitted by YEUNG, Wang Chun for the degree of Master of Philosophy at the Chinese University of Hong Kong in July 2009 This ,thesis investigates problems surrounding the lively debate about how Kripke's examples of necessary a posteriori truths and contingent a priori truths should be explained. Two-dimensionalism is a recent development that offers a non-reductive analysis of such truths. The semantic interpretation of two-dimensionalism, proposed by Jackson and Chalmers, has certain 'descriptive' elements, which can be articulated in terms of the following three claims: (a) names and natural kind terms are reference-fixed by some associated properties, (b) these properties are known a priori by every competent speaker, and (c) these properties reflect the cognitive significance of sentences containing such terms. In this thesis, I argue against two arguments directed at such 'descriptive' elements, namely, The Argument from Ignorance and Error ('AlE'), and The Argument from Variability ('AV'). I thereby suggest that reference-fixing properties belong to the semantics of names and natural kind terms, and not to their metasemantics. Chapter 1 is a survey of some central notions related to the debate between descriptivism and direct reference theory, e.g. sense, reference, and rigidity. Chapter 2 outlines the two-dimensional approach and introduces the va~ieties of interpretations 11 of the two-dimensional framework.
    [Show full text]
  • Durham E-Theses
    Durham E-Theses The Metaphysics of Mental Representation DE-BLACQUIERE-CLARKSON, RICHARD How to cite: DE-BLACQUIERE-CLARKSON, RICHARD (2011) The Metaphysics of Mental Representation, Durham theses, Durham University. Available at Durham E-Theses Online: http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/833/ Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in Durham E-Theses • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full Durham E-Theses policy for further details. Academic Support Oce, Durham University, University Oce, Old Elvet, Durham DH1 3HP e-mail: [email protected] Tel: +44 0191 334 6107 http://etheses.dur.ac.uk Abstract The representational theory of mind (RTM) explains the phenomenon of intentionality in terms of the existence and nature of mental representations. Despite the typical characterisation of mental representations in terms of their semantics, RTM is best understood as a metaphysical – more specifically formal ontological – theory whose primary defining feature is stipulating the existence of a class of mental particulars called representations. In this regard it is false, since mental representations do not exist. My argument is primarily methodological. Using an extended analysis of mereology and its variants as paradigmatic examples of a formal ontological theory, I argue for a ‘synthetic’ approach to ontology which seeks to form a sound descriptive characterisation of the relevant phenomena from empirical data, to which philosophical analysis is applied to produce a rigorous theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Situations and Individuals
    Forthcoming with MIT Press Current Studies in Linguistics Summer 2005 Situations and Individuals Paul Elbourne To my father To the memory of my mother Preface This book deals with the semantics of the natural language expressions that have been taken to refer to individuals: pronouns, definite descriptions and proper names. It claims, contrary to previous theorizing, that they have a common syntax and semantics, roughly that which is currently associated by philosophers and linguists with definite descriptions as construed in the tradition of Frege. As well as advancing this proposal, I hope to achieve at least one other aim, that of urging linguists and philosophers dealing with pronoun interpretation, in particular donkey anaphora, to consider a wider range of theories at all times than is sometimes done at present. I am thinking particularly of the gulf that seems to have emerged between those who practice some version of dynamic semantics (including DRT) and those who eschew this approach and claim that the semantics of donkey pronouns crucially involves definite descriptions (if they consider donkey anaphora at all). In my opinion there is too little work directly comparing the claims of these two schools (for that is what they amount to) and testing them against the data in the way that any two rival theories might be tested. (Irene Heim’s 1990 article in Linguistics and Philosophy does this, and largely inspired my own project, but I know of no other attempts.) I have tried to remedy that in this book. I ultimately come down on the side of definite descriptions and against dynamic semantics; but that preference is really of secondary importance beside the attempt at a systematic comparative project.
    [Show full text]
  • The Use-Mention Distinction
    The Use-Mention Distinction The use-mention distinction is traditionally understood as the distinction between using an expression (or phrase, etc.) and mentioning it. Quoting from Wikipedia encyclopedia: In written language, mentioned words or phrases often appear between quotation marks or in italics. Used words or phrases, being more common than mentioned ones, do not have any typographic distinction. Making a statement mention itself is an interesting way of producing logical paradoxes. Violation of the use-mention distinction can produce sentences that sound and appear similar to the original, but have an entirely different meaning. For example, "The use-mention distinction" is not "strictly enforced here". is literally true because the two phrases in it are not the same. The general property of terms changing their reference depending on the context was called suppositio (substitution) by classical logicians. It describes how one has to substitute a term in a sentence based on its meaning—that is, what referent the term has. In general, a term can be used in several ways. For nouns, they are: • Properly with a real referent: “That is my cow” (assuming it exists). • Properly with a generic referent: “Any cow gives milk.” • Properly but with a non-real referent: “Ulysses’s cow was big.” • Improperly by way of metaphor: “Your sister is a cow”. • As a pure term: “Cow has only three letters”. The last use is what gives rise to the use-mention distinction. However, a lot of misunderstanding and many paradoxes arise also from confusing different ways in which a meaningful expression can be used.
    [Show full text]
  • You and I Some Puzzles About ‘Mutual Recognition’
    You and I Some puzzles about ‘mutual recognition’ Michael Thompson University of Pittsburgh Slide 0 Predicating “ξ has a bruised nose” in speech NOMINALLY: “Hannah has a bruised nose” DEMONSTRATIVELY: “This girl has a bruised nose” FIRST PERSONALLY: “I have a bruised nose” Slide 1 Where these are made true by the same bruised nose, the first might be said by anyone, the second by anyone present, and the third by the injured party herself, Hannah. In particular, if Hannah is given to her own senses – in a mirror, for example – she herself might employ any of these three forms of predication. The inner basis of outward speech Outward Speech Hannah said “Hannah has a bruised nose” Hannah said “This girl has bruised nose” Hannah said “I have a bruised nose” Belief Knowlege Hannah believed she had a bruised nose Hannah knew that she had a bruised nose Hannah believed she had a bruised nose Hannah knew that she had a bruised nose Hannah believed she had a bruised nose Hannah knew that she had a bruised nose Slide 2 When Hannah does employ one of these sentences, she is not just saying words, but saying something,orclaiming something; she is perhaps also expressing a belief; and perhaps also manifesting knowledge and imparting knowledge to her hearers. co But whatever she says, it’s the same bruised nose that’s in question: her own, not Martha’s or Solomon’s. There is, as we might say, just one fact in question, one content available, and it pertains to her. We might thus represent the more intellectual states of affairs as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege: “On Sense and Denotation”
    Frege: “On Sense and Denotation” TERMIOLOGY • ‘On Sense and Nominatum’ is a quirky translation of ‘ Über Sinn und Bedeutung’. ‘On Sense and Denotation’ is the usual translation. • ‘Sameness’ is misleading in stating the initial puzzle. As Frege’s n.1 makes clear, the puzzle is about identity . THE PUZZLE What is identity? Is it a relation? If it is a relation, what are the relata? Frege considers two possibilities: 1. A relation between objects. 2. A relation between names (signs). (1) leads to a puzzle; (2) is the alternative Frege once preferred, but now rejects. The puzzle is this: if identity is a relation between objects, it must be a relation between a thing and itself . But everything is identical to itself, and so it is trivial to assert that a thing is identical to itself. Hence, every statement of identity should be analytic and knowable a priori . The “cognitive significance” of ‘ a = b ’ would thus turn out to be the same as that of ‘a = a’. In both cases one is asserting, of a single object, that it is identical to itself. Yet, it seems intuitively clear that these statements have different cognitive significance: “… sentences of the form a = b often contain very valuable extensions of our knowledge and cannot always be justified in an a priori manner” (p. 217). METALIGUISTIC SOLUTIO REJECTED In his Begriffschrift (1879), Frege proposed a metalinguistic solution: identity is a relation between signs. ‘ a = b’ thus asserts a relation between the signs ‘ a’ and ‘ b’. Presumably, the relation asserted would be being co-referential .
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1908.09658V1 [Cs.MA] 26 Aug 2019 Sdfrtescn Ups.I General, in Purpose
    Dynamic Term-Modal Logic for Epistemic Social Network Dynamics (Extended Version) Andrés Occhipinti Liberman1 and Rasmus K. Rendsvig2 1 DTU Compute [email protected] 2 Center for Information and Bubble Studies, University of Copenhagen [email protected] Abstract. Logics for social networks have been studied in recent liter- ature. This paper presents a framework based on dynamic term-modal logic (DTML), a quantified variant of dynamic epistemic logic (DEL). In contrast with DEL where it is commonly known to whom agent names refer, DTML can represent dynamics with uncertainty about agent iden- tity. We exemplify dynamics where such uncertainty and de re/de dicto distinctions are key to social network epistemics. Technically, we show that DTML semantics can represent a popular class of hybrid logic epis- temic social network models. We also show that DTML can encode pre- viously discussed dynamics for which finding a complete logic was left open. As complete reduction axioms systems exist for DTML, this yields a complete system for the dynamics in question. Keywords: social networks, term-modal logic, dynamic epistemic logic 1 Introduction Over recent years, several papers have been dedicated to logical studies of social networks, their epistemics and dynamics [2,10–14,18–22,24,25]. The purpose of this literature typically is to define and investigate some social dynamics with respect to e.g. long-term stabilization or other properties, or to introduce formal logics that capture some social dynamics, or both. This paper illustrates how dynamic term-modal logic (DTML, [1]) may be arXiv:1908.09658v1 [cs.MA] 26 Aug 2019 used for the second purpose.
    [Show full text]
  • Concrete Possible Worlds (Final)
    CONCRETE POSSIBLE WORLDS Phillip Bricker 1. INTRODUCTION. Open a book or article of contemporary analytic philosophy, and you are likely to find talk of possible worlds therein. This applies not only to analytic metaphysics, but to areas as diverse as philosophy of language, philosophy of science, epistemology, and ethics. Philosophers agree, for the most part, that possible worlds talk is extremely useful for explicating concepts and formulating theories. They disagree, however, over its proper interpretation. In this chapter, I discuss the view, championed by David Lewis, that philosophers’ talk of possible worlds is the literal truth.1 There exists a plurality of worlds. One of these is our world, the actual world, the physical universe that contains us and all our surroundings. The others are merely possible worlds containing merely possible beings, such as flying pigs and talking donkeys. But the other worlds are no less real or concrete for being merely possible. Fantastic? Yes! What could motivate a philosopher to believe such a tale? I start, as is customary, with modality.2 Truths about the world divide into two sorts: categorical and modal. Categorical truths describe how things are, what is actually the case. Modal truths describe how things could or must be, what is possibly or 1 The fullest statement of Lewis’s theory of possible worlds is contained in his magnum opus, Lewis (1986), On the Plurality of Worlds. Lewis’s view is sometimes called “modal realism.” 2 Historically, it was the attempt to provide semantics for modal logic that catapulted possible worlds to the forefront of analytic philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS
    INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS Volume 173 Robert Ginsberg Founding Editor Peter A. Redpath Executive Editor Associate Editors G. John M. Abbarno Matti Häyry Mary-Rose Barral Steven V. Hicks Gerhold K. Becker Richard T. Hull Raymond Angelo Belliotti Mark Letteri Kenneth A. Bryson Vincent L. Luizzi C. Stephen Byrum Alan Milchman H. G. Callaway George David Miller Robert A. Delfino Alan Rosenberg Rem B. Edwards Arleen L. F. Salles Andrew Fitz-Gibbon John R. Shook Francesc Forn i Argimon Eddy Souffrant William Gay Tuija Takala Dane R. Gordon Anne Waters J. Everet Green John R. Welch Heta Aleksandra Gylling Thomas F. Woods a volume in Cognitive Science CS Francesc Forn i Argimon, Editor INTENTIONALITY Past and Future Edited by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Cover Design: Studio Pollmann The paper on which this book is printed meets the requirements of “ISO 9706:1994, Information and documentation - Paper for documents - Requirements for permanence”. ISBN: 90-420-1817-8 ©Editions Rodopi B.V., Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Printed in the Netherlands CONTENTS Preface vii List of Abbreviations ix ONE The Necessity and Nature of Mental Content 1 LAIRD ADDIS TWO Reading Brentano on the Intentionality of the Mental 15 PHILIP J. BARTOK THREE Emotions, Moods, and Intentionality 25 WILLIAM FISH FOUR Lockean Ideas as Intentional Contents 37 GÁBOR FORRAI FIVE Normativity and Mental Content 51 JUSSI HAUKIOJA SIX The Ontological and Intentional Status of Fregean Senses: An Early Account of External Content 63 GREG JESSON
    [Show full text]