The Provocations of Nihilism: Practical Philosophy and Aesthetics in Jacobi, Kant, and Schelling

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Provocations of Nihilism: Practical Philosophy and Aesthetics in Jacobi, Kant, and Schelling THE PROVOCATIONS OF NIHILISM THE PROVOCATIONS OF NIHILISM: PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY AND AESTHETICS IN JACOBI, KANT, AND SCHELLING Jeremy Proulx, H.B.A., M.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy McMaster University ©Copyright by Jeremy Proulx, October 2010 DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY (2010) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: The Provocations ofNihilism: Practical Philosophy and Aesthetics in Jacobi, Kant, and Schelling AUTHOR: Jeremy Proulx, H.B.A. (Trent), M.A. (Western) SUPERVISOR: Professor Brigitte Sassen NUMBER OF PAGES: viii; 195. 11 Abstract The purpose of the dissertation is to describe how Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi's diagnosis of nihilism at the heart of the rationalist metaphysics of the Enlightenment provokes a tum to practical philosophy and aesthetics as alternative areas of philosophical scrutiny. I divide my analysis into two basic parts, treating practical philosophy and aesthetics respectively. The first part argues that Jacobi's debate with Moses Mendelssohn provokes the development of two unique approaches to practical philosophy, Jacobi's and Kant's. I interpret Jacobi's famous salto mortale as a balance between passively accepting feeling as a legitimate revelation of truth and actively creating the practical context in which feeling can appear as meaningful in the first place. I also argue that in his practical response to the Jacobi-Mendelssohn debate, Kant is still susceptible to Jacobi's critique of Enlightenment rationalism. In the second part, I tum my attention to how Kant and the early Schelling both develop their aesthetic theories as a response to Jacobi's diagnosis of nihilism. I show that Schelling's reinterpretation of Kant's theory of the postulates subtlety introduces an aesthetic dimension to philosophy in the process of employing Jacobian ideas to address problems in Kant. I continue on to interpret Kant's Critique of Judgment as unified in its attempt to respond to Jacobi by accounting for the sensible elements of experience as legitimate domain for philosophers. But I also argue that Kant's unwillingness to see the world as a creative accomplishment of human reason ultimately condemns his project to failure. I conclude by showing that Schelling's System of Transcendental Idealism finally makes good on Jacobi's call to develop a philosophy that accounts for the active role that agents have in the constitution of a meaningful world of experience. iii Acknowledgements Several people contributed to the final form of this thesis. First and foremost, my PhD advisor, Brigitte Sassen, was as a constant source of support. I remember being intimidated by the sheer volume of material in the German philosophical tradition and Brigitte was a remarkably helpful guide through several complicated texts. Brigitte somehow managed to relentlessly push me to write while at the same time allowing me to find my own way. I would also like to acknowledge the efforts of my other committee members, John Russon and Richard T.W. Arthur. John's impressive knowledge of German philosophy helped me see problems in my interpretations and his own original work is an inspiration. Richard's knowledge of the Enlightenment and modem philosophy more generally helped me see connections between my own research and thinkers I would not have encountered otherwise. Richard's insightful comments on early versions helped avoid some problematic points. I also extend my gratitude to the Department of Philosophy at McMaster University for providing me with resources and a home in which to pursue my research. A CGS Grant from the SSHRC provided me with financial support that, among other things, made it possible for me to spend time in Germany. A seminar on philosophical anthropology taught by Prof. Dr. Gerald Hartung at the Philipps-Universitiit Marburg helped me to organize and deepen my understanding of Kant and Schelling. I also thank the ARPA, the CPA and the International Kant Congress for providing me with the opportunity to present my research. I would like to thank my parents Diane Sebastian and David Proulx and my grandparents George and Betty Proulx for supporting me from the beginning. I also acknowledge my friend Michael Hyman, whose remarkable creativity is an inspiration. Finally, I cannot imagine having been able to complete this work without the constant, unwavering support of my loving wife Barbara Slim. IV Table of Contents Abstract m Acknowledgments IV Table of Contents v Abbreviations and Primary Sources vu Introduction: The Aesthetic Question 1 Part 1: Practical Philosophy 14 Chapter I: Theory and Practice in the Jacobi-Mendelssohn Debate 15 1. Jacobi's Saito Mortale 19 2. Feeling as Orientation in Philosophy 28 3. Mendelssohn's Common Sense 34 4. Concluding Remarks 39 Chapter II: Rational Faith and Practical Postulates 41 1. On Orientation in Thinking 42 2. Kant's Theory ofthe Postulates 50 3. Concluding Remarks 60 Chapter III: Jacobi's Philosophy of Action 62 1. Jacobi on Kant 65 2. Consciousness and Action 69 3. The Life ofReason 74 4. Concluding Remarks 78 Part 2: From Practice to Aesthetics 79 Introductory 80 Chapter IV: Schelling's Philosophical Letters 89 1. Precarious Postulates: The Tiibingen Interpretation ofKant 92 2. Creativity in the Early Schelling 98 3. The "Proper Principle ofAesthetics" 102 4. How to Read Kant, or Schelling's Theory ofthe Postulates 105 5. Schelling's Jacobian ism 112 6. Concluding Remarks on Greek Tragedy 117 Excursus: On the Letter form in Philosophy 120 v Chapter V: Freedom, Beauty and Destination in Kant's third Critique 122 1. Kant's Critique ofSpinoza 127 2. The Miracle ofBeauty 134 3. Art and the Fecundity of Nature 141 4. Sublime Impotence 149 5. Concluding Remarks 151 Chapter VI: The Art of Self 153 1. Transcendental Idealism and Natural Prejudice 155 2. Activity and Passivity in the Self 165 3. Practical Philosophy and the Moral Order ofthe World 169 4. Art as Keystone 17 5 5. Concluding Remarks 181 Conclusion 184 Bibliography 188 VI Abbreviations and Primary Sources F.H Jacobi References to Jacobi are to: Jacobi, F.H. 1812-25. Werke, 6 volumes. Edited by F.H. Jacobi and F. Koppen. Leipzig: Fleischer. 1815 Preface Preface to David Hume iiber den Glauben, oder Idealismus und Realismus. Ein Gesprach (1815) DH David Hume iiber den G/auben, oder Idealismus und Realismus. Ein Gesprach SB Uber die Lehre des Spinoza in Briefen an den Herrn Moses Mendelssohn (1785) SB2 Uber die Lehre des Spinoza in Briefen an den Herrn Moses Mendelssohn (1 789) Immanuel Kant References to Kant are to the standard Akademie edition of Kant's works: Kant, Immanuel. 1968. Werke. 8 volumes. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. CPR Critique ofPure Reason CPrR Critique ofPractical Reason CJ Critique ofJudgment Orientation Was heipt: sich in denken orientieren? Moses Mendelssohn AFL An die Freunde Lessings Morgenstunden Morgenstunden, oder Vorlesungen iiber das Daseyn Gottes Vll F. W.J. Schelling References to Schelling are to: Schelling, F. W.J. 1927. Schellings Werke. Edited by Manfred Schroter. Munich: Beck. DC Philosophical Letters on Dogmatism and Criticism I Of the I as the Principle ofPhilosophy SP Das A"ltestes System Programme des deutschen Idealismus System System ofTranscendental Idealism TE Treatise Explicatory of the Idealism in the Science of Knowledge Vlll Introduction: The Aesthetic Question These earnest ones may be informed of my conviction That art is the highest task And the proper metaphysical activity of this life. -Friedrich Nietzsche, Forward to Richard Wagner How is it that the world has meaning for us? This is a large question, too large indeed for a doctoral thesis. But it is precisely questions of this sort that motivated the classical German philosophers. This period of the history of philosophy, running for about fifty years from the late eighteenth to the early-mid nineteenth century, was an immensely rich period that witnessed the meteoric rise of several leading figures in the West. And the continuing influence of this period is due precisely to the bold risks it takes, its ambitious projects, lofty ideals and ostentatious claims. Beginning with such a large question, then, is part of what is involved in writing about classical German philosophy. Indeed, it is this very question that is at issue in one of the most captivating and enigmatic documents of the classical German tradition, the fragmentary, so-called "A./testes System-Programme des deutschen Idealismus/The Oldest System Program of German Idealism." Here, three central figures in late eighteenth-century Germany (Holderlin, Schelling and Hegel, all of them the fragment's putative authors) propose a new direction for philosophy. The thematic thrust of the fragment - and the note on which it concludes - is the desire to find a philosophy that would be able to re-enchant the dead concepts of classical metaphysics with a renewed, an aesthetic meaning. Here is the relevant passage: Until we make the ideas aesthetic, i.e., mythological, they will have no interest for the people; and conversely, until the mythology is rational, the philosopher will perforce be ashamed of it. Thus the enlightened and the unenlightened must at long last clasp hands; mythology must become philosophical, and the people rational, while philosophy must become mythological, in order to make the philosophers sensuous. Then eternal unity will prevail among us. No more the contemptuous glance, no more the blind quaking of the people before their sages and priests. Only then can we expect the equal formation of all forces, in particular persons as well as in all individuals. No longer will any force be suppressed; universal freedom and equality of spirits will then prevail! - A higher spirit, sent from heaven, will Jeremy Proulx Philosophy have found this new religion among us; it will be the very last and the grandest of the works ofhumanity.
Recommended publications
  • Phil. 173: Metaethics Apr. 25, 2018 Lecture 27: Is Expressivism Nihilism? Is Relativism Nihilism? I
    Phil. 173: Metaethics Apr. 25, 2018 Lecture 27: Is Expressivism Nihilism? Is Relativism Nihilism? I. Lewis’ Argument That Quasi-Realism Is Fictionalism (and Hence a Form of Nihilism) Suppose Blackburn’s quasi-realist project has succeeded perfectly on its own terms. Then the quasi-realist can, and will, echo everything the moral realist says. Rosen’s question: So what, then, makes the quasi-realist not simply a realist? Lewis’ reply: We shouldn’t look for something the realist says that the quasi-realist will not echo. Rather, we should look for something the quasi-realist says that the realist will not echo. In particular, even though at the end of the day the quasi-realist apes everything the realist says, at the beginning of the day the quasi-realist starts by expressing his commitment to projectivism. According to Lewis, this statement of projectivism acts as a disowning preface that turns the quasi-realist’s later realist-sounding assertions into fictive assertions of the sort uttered by a moral fictionalist. It’s as if the quasi- realist started out by saying, “Let’s make believe that moral realism is true, though it isn’t.” More formally, Lewis argues as follows (see p. 319): 1. One aim of quasi-realism is (to earn the right) to say what the moral realist says. [premise] 2. To say what the moral realist says is either to be a moral realist or to make-believedly be a moral realist. [premise] 3. So, an aim of quasi-realism is either to be a moral realist or to make-believedly be a moral realist.
    [Show full text]
  • Fichte's Controversy with Reinhold
    Gunter Zoller 51 PIi 10 (2000), 50-76. lO'l"plion of his work in Jena in general and to his work from the last Yl';\IS in Jena in particular. I. Aut aut or transcendental philosophy and popUlar philosophy The Unpopularity of Transcendental Philosophy: Fichte's Controversy With Reinhold (1799-1801) Thc type of systematic philosophy which Kant and Fichte developed and prcsented under the titles "transcendental philosophy" and "Wissenschaftslehre" at the close of the eighteenth century marks a sharp GUNTER ZOLLER cacsura in the philosophical discourse of modernity. To be sure, the Kantian-Fichtean philosophical revolution shares in the general critical spirit of the Enlightenment. Yet the scientific rigor of Kant' sand Fichte' s philosophical work contrasts sharply with the essayistic manner of These days common sense thinking and writing to be found in European philosophy in the second is like the peasant who swallows half of the eighteenth century and especially in its German variant, that the prescription instead of the medicine.' eclecticism in which Leibnizian heritage mixes comfortably with English, Scottish and French inspirations. In this regard, the German philosophy of the Enlightenment, chiefly represented by Moses Mendelssohn and The following essay examines the account of the relation between Christian Garve, with its aim of a widely comprehensible treatment of philosophy and life which Fichte developed at the end of his years in Jena philosophical issues, can rightly be considered to remain more faithful to and at the beginning of his time in Berlin in response to contemporary the spirit of the age than the Kantian-Fichtean movement with its criticisms and attacks of his earlier work.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Dualism and Immanentism Sacramental Ontology and History
    religions Article Between Dualism and Immanentism Sacramental Ontology and History Enrico Beltramini Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, Notre Dame de Namur University, Belmont, CA 94002, USA; [email protected] Abstract: How to deal with religious ideas in religious history (and in history in general) has recently become a matter of discussion. In particular, a number of authors have framed their work around the concept of ‘sacramental ontology,’ that is, a unified vision of reality in which the secular and the religious come together, although maintaining their distinction. The authors’ choices have been criticized by their fellow colleagues as a form of apologetics and a return to integralism. The aim of this article is to provide a proper context in which to locate the phenomenon of sacramental ontology. I suggest considering (1) the generation of the concept of sacramental ontology as part of the internal dialectic of the Christian intellectual world, not as a reaction to the secular; and (2) the adoption of the concept as a protection against ontological nihilism, not as an attack on scientific knowledge. Keywords: sacramental ontology; history; dualism; immanentism; nihilism Citation: Beltramini, Enrico. 2021. Between Dualism and Immanentism Sacramental Ontology and History. Religions 12: 47. https://doi.org/ 1. Introduction 10.3390rel12010047 A specter is haunting the historical enterprise, the specter of ‘sacramental ontology.’ Received: 3 December 2020 The specter of sacramental ontology is carried by a generation of Roman Catholic and Accepted: 23 December 2020 Evangelical historians as well as historical theologians who aim to restore the sacred dimen- 1 Published: 11 January 2021 sion of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • An Argument for Moral Nihilism
    Syracuse University SURFACE Syracuse University Honors Program Capstone Syracuse University Honors Program Capstone Projects Projects Spring 5-1-2010 An Argument for Moral Nihilism Tommy Fung Follow this and additional works at: https://surface.syr.edu/honors_capstone Part of the Other Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Fung, Tommy, "An Argument for Moral Nihilism" (2010). Syracuse University Honors Program Capstone Projects. 335. https://surface.syr.edu/honors_capstone/335 This Honors Capstone Project is brought to you for free and open access by the Syracuse University Honors Program Capstone Projects at SURFACE. It has been accepted for inclusion in Syracuse University Honors Program Capstone Projects by an authorized administrator of SURFACE. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 An Argument for Moral Nihilism What if humans were just mere animals, and that we react to certain stimuli in a certain, lawful manner, and thus change in the appropriate way. It is debatable how much free will the average person would grant to say- a dog, but the average person doesn’t doubt that humans exercise free will. What if instead it could be shown that we are no different than a robot? That we are nothing but just an input-output mechanism for our programming to determine how to react to certain stimuli? I don’t know how many people who would claim that a robot exercises free will, or could be held morally responsible for their actions. “Science is more than the mere description of events as they occur. It is an attempt to discover order, to show that certain events stand in lawful relation to other events..
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche and Problem of Nihilism Zahra Meyboti University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee
    University of Wisconsin Milwaukee UWM Digital Commons Theses and Dissertations August 2016 Nietzsche and Problem of Nihilism Zahra Meyboti University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.uwm.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Meyboti, Zahra, "Nietzsche and Problem of Nihilism" (2016). Theses and Dissertations. 1389. https://dc.uwm.edu/etd/1389 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by UWM Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of UWM Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. NIETZSCHE AND PROBLEM OF NIHILISM by Zahra Meyboti A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy at The University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee August 2016 ABSTRACT NIETZSCHE AND PROBLEM OF NIHILISM by Zahra Meyboti The University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee, 2016 Under the Supervision of Professor William Bristow It is generally accepted that life-affirmation is central to Nietzsche’s philosophy. Nietzsche’s aim is to affirm life despite all miseries for human beings conscious of the horror and terror of existence and avoid nihilism. He is concerned with life affirmation almost in all of his works, In my thesis I will consider how he involved with avoiding nihilism to affirm life according to his two books The Birth of Tragedy and Genealogy of Morals. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract .......................................................................................................................................ii
    [Show full text]
  • Albert Camus' Dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky Sean Derek Illing Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected]
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2014 Between nihilism and transcendence : Albert Camus' dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky Sean Derek Illing Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Illing, Sean Derek, "Between nihilism and transcendence : Albert Camus' dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky" (2014). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 1393. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/1393 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. BETWEEN NIHILISM AND TRANSCENDENCE: ALBERT CAMUS’ DIALOGUE WITH NIETZSCHE AND DOSTOEVSKY A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by Sean D. Illing B.A., Louisiana State University, 2007 M.A., University of West Florida, 2009 May 2014 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This dissertation is the product of many supportive individuals. I am especially grateful for Dr. Cecil Eubank’s guidance. As a teacher, one can do no better than Professor Eubanks. Although his Socratic glare can be terrifying, there is always love and wisdom in his instruction. It is no exaggeration to say that this work would not exist without his support. At every step, he helped me along as I struggled to articulate my thoughts.
    [Show full text]
  • Predetermination and Nihilism in W. B. Yeats's Theatre
    Revista Alicantina de Estudios Ingleses 5 (1992): 143-53 Predetermination and Nihilism in W. B. Yeats's Theatre Francisco Javier Torres Ribelles University of Alicante ABSTRACT This paper puts forward the hypothesis that Yeats's theatre is affected by a determinist component that governs it. This dependence is held to be the natural consequence of his desire to créate a universal art, a wish that confines the writer to a limited number of themes, death and oíd age being the most important. The paper also argües that the deter- minism is positive in the early stage but that it clearly evolves towards a negative kind. In spite of the playwright's acknowledged interest in doctrines related to the occult, the necessity of a more critical analysis is also put forward. The paper goes on to suggest that underlying the negative determinism of Yeats's late period there is a nihilistic view of life, of life after death and even of the work of art. The paper concludes by arguing that the poet may have exaggerated his pose as a response to his admitted inability to change the modern world and as a means of overcoming his sense of impending annihilation. The attitude underlying Yeats's earliest plays is radically opposed to what we find in the final ones. In the first stage, the determinism to which the subject matter inevitably leads is given a positive character by being adapted to the author's perspective. There is an emphasis on the power of art and a celebration of the Nietzschean-romantic valúes defended by the poet.
    [Show full text]
  • JG Fichte and the Atheism Dispute
    J.G. FICHTE AND THE ATHEISM DISPUTE (1798–1800) This page has been left blank intentionally J.G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute (1798–1800) Translated by CURTIS BOWMAN Independent Scholar, USA Commentary by YOLANDA ESTES Mississippi State University, USA First published 2010 by Ashgate Publishing Published 2016 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017, USA Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business Copyright © 2010 Yolanda Estes and Curtis Bowman Yolanda Estes and Curtis Bowman have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the editors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data J.G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute (1798–1800). 1. Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 1762–1814. 2. Atheism – History – 18th century. 3. Atheism – History -- 18th century – Sources. I. Estes, Yolanda. II. Bowman, Curtis. 211.8’092–dc22 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Estes, Yolanda. [Selections. English. 2010] J.G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute, 1798–1800 / Yolanda Estes and Curtis Bowman. p. cm. Includes index. 1. Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 1762–1814.
    [Show full text]
  • Universidade Do Estado Do Rio De Janeiro Centro De Ciências Sociais Instituto De Filosofia E Ciências Humanas Gabriel Dirma De
    Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro Centro de Ciências Sociais Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Leitão Friedrich Jacobi sobre a crença, ou realismo e idealismo transcendental Rio de Janeiro 2017 Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Leitão Friedrich Jacobi sobre a crença, ou realismo e idealismo transcendental Tese apresentada como requisito parcial para a obtenção do título de Doutor em Filosofia, ao Programa de Pós-graduação em Filosofia, da Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro. Área de concentração: Filosofia Moderna e Contemporânea. Orientador: Prof. Dr. Ricardo José Corrêa Barbosa Rio de Janeiro 2017 CATALOGAÇÃO NA FONTE UERJ/REDE SIRIUS/ BIBLIOTECA CCS/A L533 Leitão, Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Friedrich Jacobi sobre a crença, ou realismo e idealismo transcendental / Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Leitão. – 2017. 291f. Orientador: Ricardo José Corrêa Barbosa.. Tese (Doutorado) - Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro. Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas. Bibliografia. 1. Filosofia alemã - Teses. 2. Idealismo alemão – Teses. 3. Realismo – Teses. I. Barbosa, Ricardo José Corrêa, 1961-. II. Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro. Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas. III. Título. CDU 1(430) Autorizo, apenas para fins acadêmicos e científicos, a reprodução total ou parcial desta tese, desde que citada a fonte. ______________________________ ___________________________ Assinatura Data Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Leitão Friedrich Jacobi sobre a crença, ou realismo e idealismo transcendental Tese apresentada, como requisito parcial para a obtenção do título de Doutor em Filosofia, ao Programa de Pós-graduação em Filosofia, da Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro. Área de concentração: Filosofia Moderna e Contemporânea.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume, Jacobi, and Common Sense
    1 HUME, JACOBI, AND COMMON SENSE AN EPISODE IN THE RECEPTION OF HUME IN GERMANY AT THE TIME OF KANT Jacobi's dispute with Mendelssohn over the alleged Spinozism of Lessing 0 was to be important for the development of subsequent German philosophy, especially because it quickly became intertwined with the reception of Kant's critical philosophy. So far as this paper is concerned, however, we are inter- ested in it only because in the course of it Jacobi appealed to Hume's authority to defend his use of the term "faith" or "belief" (both rendered in German as Glaube ). This appeal, as we shall see, set in motion as intricate a play of conflicting views as can be found in the history of philosophy. It forced hidden ambiguities to light, and exposed conceptual affinities and differences where none would have been suspected. Jacobi himself did not have Hume particularly in mind in his original attack on Mendelssohn. His concern was to publicize what he took to be the Spinozistic implications of Enlightenment philosophy. Yet one can understand why, in retrospect, Jacobi could have appealed to Hume's authority. For Jacobi's brief against Mendelssohn was based on the claim that, when divorced from its basis in sensations and left to its own devices, reason could quite consistently argue itself into conclusions untenable at the level of common experience. Jacobi had accordingly pleaded with Mendelssohn to abandon his rationalistic ways, and to heed to a more primordial authority than that of philosophy--namely to an innate certainty about what is real, a certainty that animates our experiences from the beginning and pervades all levels of language.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Practical Postulates and the Limits of the Critical System
    Kant’s Practical Postulates and the Limits of the Critical System Sebastian Gardner The topic that I wish to consider is the significance, both systematic and historical, for Kant’s system as a whole, of the postulates of pure practical reason, more specifically, of the two theological postulates concerning the existence of God and personal immortality which form the basis of Kant’s moral theology. My discussion will focus on the problems of Kant’s moral theology in the eyes of his early contemporaries, for whom it constituted a crux in Kant’s project. Different views were taken by Kant’s contemporaries of what exactly these problems signified regarding the future of Critical philosophy. For the thinkers I will be looking at here, the miscarriage of the moral theology constituted a fatal fault in the Kantian project. For the German Idealists, the moral theology instead provided a vital clue as to how the Kantian system could be transformed into a more radical idealism, while confirming that it needed to be. The role of the practical postulates in the development of German Idealism demands a separate treatment; what I will argue here is simply that the practical postulates do indeed represent a point at which Kant’s philosophical system displays a deep and interesting tension, in light of which both historical responses are prima facie intelligible. I. Kant on practical cognition Let me begin with some examples of Kant’s use, in connection with the moral theology and practical postulation, of the concept of practical cognition, praktische Erkenntnis. The following, key statements are taken from the second and third Critiques: [T]he concept of freedom, insofar as its reality is proved by an apodictic law of practical reason, constitutes the keystone of the whole structure of a system of pure reason, even of speculative reason; and all other concepts (those of God and immortality) ..
    [Show full text]