Emile Durkheim, the Categories, and the Origins of Social Constructionism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Emile Durkheim, the Categories, and the Origins of Social Constructionism Warren Schmaus. Rethinking Durkheim and His Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. xii + 195 pp. $70.00, cloth, ISBN 978-0-521-83816-0. Reviewed by Michael C. Behrent Published on H-Ideas (November, 2006) Few social theorists have been scrutinized as terpretative argument about Durkheim's theory of closely as Emile Durkheim. Yet while hundreds of the categories and a normative argument con‐ commentators have vetted his ideas over the past cerning the tenability of social constructionism, century, only in recent decades have the episte‐ Schmaus also makes an intriguing historical argu‐ mological dimensions of Durkheim's thought been ment concerning the origins of Durkheim's views extensively explored. As a number of new studies on the categories--or, to be precise, concerning the attest, this interest springs at least in part from error that he perceives lying at the origin of these the desire to assess an epistemological thesis so views. Schmaus's book is, in this sense, the fasci‐ influential that few working in the social sciences nating history of a misreading. As readers of The have not grappled with it at some level: namely, Elementary Forms of Religious Life (1912) know, the claim that reality is "socially constructed." Be‐ Durkheim, in his last major work, not only argued cause Durkheim argued that the most basic con‐ that religion is essentially a social phenomenon, cepts of human thought can best be explained so‐ but also that religion--and thus society?"are re‐ ciologically, he has often been considered as the sponsible for the very building blocks out of godfather of social constructionism. In Rethinking which human thought is formed. These blocks in‐ Durkheim and His Tradition, Warren Schmaus at‐ clude such notions as time, space, number, causal‐ tempts to weed out all that is untenable in social ity, and substance, which philosophers have tradi‐ constructionism through an examination of tionally labeled "the categories of the understand‐ Durkheim's thought. Contrary to what the title in‐ ing." (Unlike Immanuel Kant, Durkheim consid‐ dicates, Schmaus's book does not cover ered time and space to be categories, rather than Durkheim's oeuvre as a whole, but specifically what the German philosopher called "forms of in‐ considers his argument that the categories of hu‐ tuition."[1]) Schmaus's frst concern is purely his‐ man understanding are primarily social in char‐ torical: how did Durkheim come to think that the acter. What makes this book of interest to histori‐ categories of the understanding were social in ans of ideas is the fact that, while proposing an in‐ character? Schmaus addresses this question in H-Net Reviews two steps. In the frst place, he argues, we must through nineteenth-century French thought--ter‐ see Durkheim, who was trained as a philosopher ritory that, while increasingly familiar to intellec‐ before founding sociology as an autonomous dis‐ tual historians, remains largely uncharted in phi‐ cipline, as responding to a longer philosophical losophy departments. According to Schmaus, most tradition, which Schmaus considers in chapter 2. nineteenth-century French philosophers simply The frst philosopher to theorize categories was did not understand Kant: "many of Kant's subtle Aristotle. His categories referred to the highest distinctions were lost upon his earliest French in‐ genera, that is, the most general attributes that terpreters" (p. 52) who were "mystified by his no‐ could be predicated of an entity. Yet it was with tion of a transcendental logic" (p. 50). The source Immanuel Kant that modern thinking about the of this confusion lay in the exact meaning of categories truly began. For Kant, the categories re‐ Kant's transcendentalism: for many of his early ferred to the preconditions that logically had to readers, the contention that experience depends obtain for experience to be possible in the frst on necessary preconditions seemed to be an argu‐ place. However, as Schmaus explains in lucid and ment about the being in which those precondi‐ economical prose, Kant's theory is a response to tions were presumably located, making it a psy‐ the problem presented by David Hume's views on chological claim. Moreover, Kant's linking, in the the nature of causality. According to Hume, we transcendental deduction, of the categories to the never actually experience one thing causing an‐ essential unity of human consciousness, which he other: when we observe, for instance, two events called the "transcendental unity of apperception," occurring in rapid and regular succession, we in‐ appeared to justify this conclusion. Yet this read‐ fer a causal relationship that our senses have in ing of Kant, as Schmaus makes clear, is demon‐ fact never perceived. Kant responded to the chal‐ strably wrong. In the Prolegomena to Any Future lenge of Hume's skepticism by arguing, in a sec‐ Metaphysics (1783) and the second edition of the tion of his Critique of Pure Reason (1781) known First Critique (1787), Kant left no doubt that his as the transcendental deduction, that for an expe‐ was a purely logical argument concerning how rience even to occur, a number of concepts must universally valid judgments about experience are be presupposed. He dubbed these concepts "cate‐ possible. However, as Schmaus explains, the accu‐ gories of the understanding," and claimed there rate interpretation of Kant's transcendentalism as were twelve of them, among which was causality. a logical claim lagged behind the inaccurate un‐ While Hume had been right, Kant suggested, to derstanding of it as a psychological theory. Only say that we never perceive causes, he failed to re‐ with the German philosopher Hermann Cohen alize that they are logical prerequisites of experi‐ (1842-1918), in the latter part of the nineteenth ence. In this way, Kant's categories were critical to century, did a better reading begin to prevail. the Copernican Revolution that he effectuated in This particular misreading of Kant, Schmaus philosophy: henceforth, the main epistemological claims, had a decisive impact on Durkheim's problem would no longer be that of how the mind thought, via the influence of two prominent gains access to the external world, but that of how French thinkers examined in chapter 3--Victor the knowing mind shapes the external world. Cousin (1792-1867), the founder of a spiritualist Schmaus readily acknowledges that Kant's doctrine known as Eclecticism, and Pierre Maine thought harbored a number of ambiguities that de Biran (1766-1824), who was retroactively asso‐ would befuddle his readers. In chapter 3, ciated with Cousin's school. That Schmaus takes Schmaus begins to examine the history of the con‐ Cousin seriously at all, rather than confining him fusion that Kant's arguments engendered. To con‐ to his role as an intellectual power-broker (as his‐ nect Kant to Durkheim, Schmaus takes a detour torians, until recently, have done), is in itself re‐ 2 H-Net Reviews markable. More importantly, Schmaus demon‐ that would occupy a place of honor in his philo‐ strates with considerable skill why we should see sophical lexicon: that of representation. Cousin Cousin's psychological interpretation of Kant as had subscribed to Scottish "common sense" phi‐ something other than a "willful misreading" of losophy, which maintained that we perceive ex‐ him (p. 63). Like some of Kant's early German crit‐ ternal objects directly, rather than through the ics, Cousin believed that, rather than placing phi‐ mediations of a mental picture. Janet, an influen‐ losophy on a more secure basis, Kant had tial thinker who also wrote a philosophy textbook strengthened skepticism's hand. In Cousin's eyes, assigned by Durkheim, rehabilitated the older the apparent victory that the German thinker had view that, in addition to directly perceived ob‐ secured in claiming that the preconditions of ex‐ jects, the mind is also inhabited by representa‐ perience were not located in experience itself was tions, which make general ideas possible. Reject‐ won at the cost of declaring philosophy impotent ing realism (the belief that general ideas exist as to speak about what lay beyond the realm of ex‐ beings in their own right) as well as nominalism perience--the hazy world of what Kant called the (the claim that general ideas have no other con‐ noumena, or the "thing-in-itself." In particular, creteness than the particular objects to which Cousin feared the skeptical implications of Kant's they refer), Janet endorsed a form of conceptual‐ claim that we even experience our own selves as ism, the doctrine proposed by the twelfth-century mere appearances, rather than as things-in-them‐ philosopher Pierre Abelard, which holds that gen‐ selves. "I am conscious of the power to resist to a eral ideas exist, but only as representations ap‐ certain extent the forces external to mine," Cousin pearing in the minds of individuals. Janet's under‐ insisted. "What are all the arguments in the world standing of how general ideas work, according to in opposition to a fact like this?" (quoted, p. 67). Schmaus, inspired Durkheim to appeal to the idea Thus Cousin, Schmaus argues, ignored Kant's of representation to explain the function of collec‐ transcendentalism, offering in its place an "apper‐ tive beliefs. ception of willed effort" (p. 67), which maintains The central contention of Schmaus's historical that the self, through effortful activity and a ca‐ argument is that Durkheim appropriated the pacity to resist its surroundings, has immediate Eclectics' psychological framework for himself, knowledge of itself. Another exponent of the self yet transposed it onto the study of collective as willed effort was Maine de Biran, who invoked rather than individual phenomena. Schmaus it to explain how the mind frst comes to under‐ identifies two moments in this process, each cor‐ stand causality.
Recommended publications
  • Taking Social Constructionism Seriously
    Taking Social Constructionism Seriously Gergen, K. J. (1999). An Invitation to Social Construction. London: Sage (248 p.) Gergen, K.J. (2001). Social Construction in Context. London: Sage (223 p.) Reviewed by: Svend Brinkmann, cand. psych. email-adresse: [email protected] I Social constructionism (SC) has emerged as a significant paradigm in psychology and other social sciences during the last twenty years or so. Kenneth Gergen can be considered a found- ing father and currently one of the leading exponents of SC as theory and practice. Gergen wrote about the social construction of self-knowledge as early as 1977 (Gergen, 1977), and in 1985 SC was already a “movement” as witnessed in Gergen’s often cited “The social construc- tionist movement in modern psychology” (1985) published in American Psychologist. SC has developed from a heretic partisan theory to a widely recognised paradigm, and it must be con- sidered one of the most interesting frameworks in contemporary psychology. For example, the renowned journal Theory and Psychology devotes two whole issues to SC in 2001 and 2002, “Social Constructionism and Its Critics” (June 2001) and the forthcoming “Varieties of Social Constructionism” (October 2002). Kenneth Gergen is a prolific writer, who has published in many different areas within psychol- ogy and related fields. His major works are The Saturated Self (1991) and Realities and Rela- tionships (1994). His two new books An Invitation to Social Construction (ISC) and Social Construction in Context (SCC) continue the line of thought that was developed in earlier works, and while these new books contain few new perspectives, they seek to clarify the basic tenets of SC, while at the same time providing more concrete and practical illustrations of SC’s theoretical points.
    [Show full text]
  • Durkheim Lulu4 Defdefdef QUATTRO Watermerk
    Chapter 1. A century of commentary and debate around Durkheim and Les Formes Élémentaires de la Vie Religieuse 1.1. Introduction As is to be expected in regard of a ‘Founding Father’ of the social sciences, the international literature around Durkheim is enormous. I cannot be expected to present here a full discussion even of the religiously relevant aspects of that literature. However, some selective treatment is imperative so as to provide the necessary background for the chapters that are to follow. I shall first briefly situate Durkheim in his time and age, with special emphasis on his political views and his ethnic identity as a secularised Jew. Then we turn to Durkheim’s relation with the discipline in which he was originally trained, philosophy, and articulate his transition to sociology. Our focus in the present book is upon Les Formes Élémentaires de la Vie Religieuse , and we shall have a look at that book’s contents and method, before turning to its specific commentators, both shortly after its publication, and then in the course of the 20th c. CE and up to the present. We will conclude with a brief indication of where we will go after this first chapter. 47 1.2. Durkheim against the background of his time and age 1.2.1. Durkheim’s political views Durkheim had a keen eye for the political developments in his native country, France, at the time. During his lifetime (1858-1917) that country went through a period of restored monarchy under Napoleon III, was defeated in the war with Prussia (1870), knew internal turmoil (the Commune de Paris ) which ended in the Third Republic, and after a period of relative prosperity, bliss and colonial expansion in Africa and Asia, was drawn into World War I (1914-1918).
    [Show full text]
  • Bourdieu's Habitus, Critical Theory, and Social Philosophy Civitas - Revista De Ciências Sociais, Vol
    Civitas - Revista de Ciências Sociais ISSN: 1519-6089 [email protected] Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio Grande do Sul Brasil de Oliveira, Nythamar The normative claims of Brazil's democratic ethos: Bourdieu's habitus, critical theory, and social philosophy Civitas - Revista de Ciências Sociais, vol. 12, núm. 1, 2012, pp. 70-87 Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio Grande do Sul Porto Alegre, Brasil Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=74223603005 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative The normative claims of Brazil’s democratic ethos: Bourdieu’s habitus, critical theory, and social philosophy As exigências normativas do ethos democrático brasileiro: O habitus em Bourdieu, teoria crítica e filosofia social Nythamar de Oliveira* Abstract: This paper argues for an interdisciplinary interlocution between social theory and social philosophy in order to recast the problem of normativity in social practices, especially within Brazil’s democratic ethos. By resorting to insights from critical theory and social epistemology, the essay proposes to reexamine Bourdieu’s conception of habitus so as to contribute to a moderate social constructionism that cannot be reduced to a postmodernist discourse or to a variant of relativism. Keywords: critical theory; democratic ethos; habitus; normativity; social philosophy Resumo: O artigo defende uma interlocução interdisciplinar entre teoria social e filosofia social, com o fito de reformular o problema da normatividade nas práticas sociais, especialmente no contexto de um ethos democrático brasileiro.
    [Show full text]
  • Online Islamic Da'wah Narratives in the UK: the Case of Iera
    Online Islamic Da'wah Narratives in the UK: The Case of iERA by MIRA A. BAZ A thesis submitted to the University of Birmingham for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Religion and Theology College of Arts and Law University of Birmingham September 2016 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. ABSTRACT This thesis is an in-depth study into two of the UK charity iERA's da'wah narratives: the Qura'nic embryology 'miracle' and the Kalam Cosmological Argument. While the embryo verses have received scholarly attention, there is little to no research in the da'wah context for both narratives. Berger and Luckmann's social constructionism was applied to both, which were problematic. It was found that iERA constructed its exegesis of the embryo verses by expanding on classical meanings to show harmony with modern science. Additionally, it developed the Cosmological Argument by adapting it to Salafi Islamic beliefs. The construction processes were found to be influenced by an online dialectic between iERA and its Muslim and atheist detractors, causing it to abandon the scientific miracles and modify the Cosmological Argument.
    [Show full text]
  • A Social Constructionist Lens
    Identity, Old(er) Age and Migrancy A Social Constructionist Lens Laura Machat-From Linköping Studies in Arts and Science No. 716 Faculty of Arts and Sciences Norrköping 2017 Linköping Studies in Arts and Science • No. 716 At the Faculty of Arts and Sciences at Linköping University, research and doctoral studies are carried out within broad problem areas. Research is organized in interdisciplinary research environments and doctoral studies, mainly in graduate schools. Jointly, they publish the series Linköping Studies in Arts and Science. This thesis comes from the Division Ageing and Social Change (formerly National Institute for the Study of Ageing and Later Life) at the Department of Social and Welfare Studies. Distributed by: Department of Social and Welfare Studies Linköping University SE-601 74 Norrköping Laura Machat-From Identity, Old(er) Age and Migrancy: A Social Constructionist Lens Edition 1:1 ISBN: 978-91-7685-515-7 ISSN 0282-9800 © Laura Machat-From, 2017 Printed in Sweden by: LiU-Tryck, Linköping ii ABSTRACT Identity research in relation to ethnicity and migration has tended to focus on younger people whilst identity research in relation to ageing and old(er) age has not focused on migrants. This inadvertent mutual neglect has led to a lack of identity research that examines the identity categories of old(er) age and migrancy together, a lacuna that this dissertation aims to redress. This dissertation departs from a social constructionist understanding of identity as situationally accomplished in the interplay between how
    [Show full text]
  • Sociology 4111 (Uggen): Deviant Behavior Midterm Review, Spring 2004
    Sociology 4111 (Uggen): Deviant Behavior Midterm Review, Spring 2004 PART I: BASIC CONCEPTS -- DEVIANCE, CONTROL, AND CAREERS I. Social Facts and Social Constructions II. Defining Deviance a. Clinard’s Definitions of Deviance (Statistical, Absolutist, Reactivist, Normative) b. Adlers’ definition’s i. Deviance as violation of social norms (Attitudes, Behaviors, Conditions, Prescriptive norms, Proscriptive norms) ii. Role iii. Subcultures iv. Power v. Moral entrepreneurs c. Kai Erikson (1966) III. Differences between Criminology and Deviance a. Piece in The Criminologist: b. Heckert: positive deviance i. Altruism (hero) ii. Charisma (dictator) iii. Innovation (artist) iv. Supra-Conformity (4.0) v. Innate/Ascribed (beauty) vi. Ex-Deviant (saved) c. Middle Class norms - Typology of Deviance IV. Social Controls and the Hobbesian Problem of Order a. Thomas Hobbes i. “Hobbesian problem of order” ii. How can we create a society in which self-interested people don’t use force and fraud to satisfy their (criminal, sexual, substance-abusing …) wants? iii. 3 “solutions” to Hobbesian dilemma 1. Normative 2. Exchange 3. Conflict iv. Informal social controls v. Formal social controls b. social controls and constructions i. Clinard: Deviant Events in Context ii. Joel Best: Social Constructionism c. Race and formal control i. Anderson on police as social control ii. Local perspective/Why focus on police? V. Introduction to Deviant Careers (of people, firms, nations…) a. Becoming Deviant b. Phases of the Deviant Career 1 VI. Subcultures, Power, and “Unconventional Sentimentality” (5 min. video: The Wall) a. Chambliss: Saints and Roughnecks b. Sanchez Jankowski: Joining a Gang c. Fox: Real Punks and Pretenders PART II: THEORIES OF DEVIANCE AND SOCIETAL REACTION VII.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphor and Monophony in the Twentieth-Century Psychology of Emotions
    Swarthmore College Works Psychology Faculty Works Psychology 1996 Metaphor And Monophony In The Twentieth-Century Psychology Of Emotions Kenneth J. Gergen Swarthmore College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-psychology Part of the Psychology Commons Let us know how access to these works benefits ouy Recommended Citation Kenneth J. Gergen. (1996). "Metaphor And Monophony In The Twentieth-Century Psychology Of Emotions". Historical Dimensions Of Psychological Discourse. 60-82. DOI: 10.1017/ CBO9780511571329.004 https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-psychology/843 This work is brought to you for free by Swarthmore College Libraries' Works. It has been accepted for inclusion in Psychology Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Works. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Metaphor and monophony in the twentieth-century psychology of emotions Kenneth J. Gergen Attempts to define the emotions and elucidate their character have orna- mented the intellectual landscape for over two thousand years. Two charac- teristics of this continuing colloquy are particularly noteworthy: first, the presumption of palpability and, second, the interminability of debate. In the former case, until the present century there has been little doubting the obdurate existence of the emotions. In the second book of the Rhetoric, Aristotle distinguished among 15 emotional states; Aquinas's Summa Theo- logiae enumerated 6 "affective" and 5 "spirited" emotions; Descartes distin- guished among 6 primary passions of the soul; the eighteenth-century moral- ist, David Hartley, located 10 "general passions of human nature"; and the major contributions by recent theorists, Tomkins (1962) and Izard (1977), describe some 10 distinctive emotional states.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Classical Sociology
    Journal of Classical Sociology http://jcs.sagepub.com/ This is social science: A 'patterned activity' oriented to attaining objective knowledge of human society Eric Malczewski Journal of Classical Sociology 2014 14: 341 originally published online 22 August 2013 DOI: 10.1177/1468795X13495124 The online version of this article can be found at: http://jcs.sagepub.com/content/14/4/341 Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com Additional services and information for Journal of Classical Sociology can be found at: Email Alerts: http://jcs.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://jcs.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Citations: http://jcs.sagepub.com/content/14/4/341.refs.html >> Version of Record - Oct 21, 2014 OnlineFirst Version of Record - Aug 22, 2013 What is This? Downloaded from jcs.sagepub.com by guest on October 21, 2014 JCS14410.1177/1468795X13495124Journal of Classical SociologyMalczewski 4951242013 Article Journal of Classical Sociology 2014, Vol. 14(4) 341 –362 This is social science: © The Author(s) 2013 Reprints and permissions: A ‘patterned activity’ sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/1468795X13495124 oriented to attaining objective jcs.sagepub.com knowledge of human society Eric Malczewski Harvard University, USA Abstract The aim of this article is to demonstrate that approaching social science as a ‘patterned activity’ draws attention both to the distinctive nature of social science and to its central subject matter – meaningful (symbolically oriented) behavior and theoretical entities based on it – enabling therefore a constructive perspective on the major debate regarding social science’s organizing principles.
    [Show full text]
  • Front Matter
    Cambridge University Press 052165145X - Epistemology and Practice: Durkheim’s The Elementary Forms of Religious Life Anne Warfield Rawls Frontmatter More information Epistemology and Practice In this original and controversial book Professor Rawls argues that Durkheim’s The Elementary Forms of Religious Life is the crowning achievement of his sociological endeavour and that since its publica- tion in English in 1915it has been consistently misunderstood. Rather than a work on primitive religion or the sociology of knowledge, Rawls asserts that it is an attempt by Durkheim to establish a unique epistemo- logical basis for the study of sociology and moral relations. By privileging social practice over beliefs and ideas, it avoids the dilemmas inherent in philosophical approaches to knowledge and morality that are based on individualism and the tendency to treat concepts as the limit of knowl- edge, both tendancies that dominate western thought. Based on detailed textual analysis of the primary text, this book will be an important and original contribution to contemporary debates on social theory and philosophy. Anne Warfield Rawls is Associate Professor of Sociology at Bentley College, Waltham, Massachusetts. She has a background in both sociol- ogy and philosophy and has published extensively on social theory and social justice. © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 052165145X - Epistemology and Practice: Durkheim’s The Elementary Forms of Religious Life Anne Warfield Rawls Frontmatter More information
    [Show full text]
  • Race in Early Modern Philosophy
    Introduction I.1. Nature In 1782, in the journal of an obscure Dutch scientific society, we find a relation of the voyage of a European seafarer to the Gold Coast of Africa some decades earlier. In the town of Axim in present- day Ghana, we learn, at some point in the late 1750s, David Henri Gallandat met a man he describes as a “hermit” and a “soothsayer.” “His father and a sister were still alive,” Gallandat relates, “and lived a four- days’ journey inland. He had a brother who was a slave in the colony of Suriname.”1 So far, there is nothing exceptional in this relation: countless families were broken up by the slave trade in just this way. But we also learn that the hermit’s soothsaying practice was deeply informed by “philosophy.” Gal- landat is not using this term in a loose sense, either. The man he meets, we are told, “spoke various languages— Hebrew, Greek, Latin, French, High and Low German; he was very knowledgeable in astrology and as- tronomy, and a great philosopher.”2 In fact, this man, we learn, “had been sent to study at Halle and in Wittenberg, where in 1727 he was promoted to Doctor of Philosophy and Master of Liberal Arts.”3 On a certain understanding, there have been countless philosophers in Africa, whose status as such required no recognition by European institu- tions, no conferral of rank.4 On a narrower understanding, however, Anton Wilhelm Amo may rightly be held up as the first African philosopher in modern history. Gallandat tells us that after the death of Amo’s “master,” Duke August Wilhelm of Braunschweig- Wolfenbüttel, the philosopher- slave grew “melancholy,” and “decided to return to his home country.” 1 Verhandelingen uitgegeven door het Zeeuwsch Genootschap der Wetenschappen te Vlissingen, Negende Deel, Middelburg: Pieter Gillissen, 1782, 19– 20.
    [Show full text]
  • Stakeholder Expectations of Islamic Education
    Portland State University PDXScholar Dissertations and Theses Dissertations and Theses 6-8-2018 Stakeholder Expectations of Islamic Education Julia Marie Ahmed Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: https://pdxscholar.library.pdx.edu/open_access_etds Part of the Educational Leadership Commons, and the Islamic Studies Commons Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Ahmed, Julia Marie, "Stakeholder Expectations of Islamic Education" (2018). Dissertations and Theses. Paper 4395. https://doi.org/10.15760/etd.6279 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of PDXScholar. Please contact us if we can make this document more accessible: [email protected]. Stakeholder Expectations of Islamic Education by Julia Marie Ahmed A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Education in Educational Leadership: Curriculum and Instruction Dissertation Committee: Susan Lenski, Chair Swapna Mukhopadhyay Dannelle Stevens Sharon Carstens Portland State University 2018 © 2018 Julia Marie Ahmed STAKEHOLDER EXPECTATIONS OF ISLAMIC EDUCATION i Abstract Teachers and parents make considerable sacrifices to affiliate themselves with Islamic schools. As they commit to Islamic education, they acquire certain expectations that they want their school to fulfill. The purpose of this study was to explore the academic, social, and cultural expectations
    [Show full text]
  • Page Numbers Followed by N Refer to Notes, with Note Number
    Index Note: page numbers followed by n refer to notes, with note number. Aarhus University. See Religion, Cognition astonishing hypothesis, Crick on 178 and Culture Group Atta, Mohamed 1 Abrahamic mystic traditions, recognition of Augustine of Hippo 27 language’s contingency in 145, Averroës 29–30, 31 147–48, 150 Avicenna 29 Academy of Athens 26, 28 Ayer, A.J. 80 Advaita Vedanta 133 agency, as concept Bagger, Matthew 136 computational leverage provided by 184 Bartkowski, John 69–70 evolutionary emergence of 184–85 Baudrillard, Jean 169, 170 See also free will; mind, theory of behaviorism, vs. social science approach Albert the Great 31 157–58, 159 Alston, William P. 228 beliefs Althusser, Louis 63 importance of taking seriously 139–42 analysis. See explanation normative framework of, as essential for Anaxagoras 25 human action 193 Anaximines 25 scholars’ reasons for discounting 139, 141 Antiochus of Ascalon 26 Bell, Catherine 2–3, 4, 9 apophatic tradition, revival of 107 Bellah, Robert 117n21 a posteriori methodological naturalism. Bentley, Richard 37n24 See provisional (a posteriori) Berger, Peter L. methodological naturalism on functionalist approaches to religion Appleby, Peter 142 237–39 a priori methodological naturalism. on global methodological agnosticism See intrinsic (a priori) methodological 244–47 naturalism influence of personal beliefs on work of Aquinas. See Thomas Aquinas 248 Arbib, Michael 185 and methodological agnosticism Aristotelian naturalism 24 239–40, 242–43 and medieval synthesis of Aquinas on mixed forms of supernatural
    [Show full text]