<<

arXiv:1809.05147v2 [quant-ph] 11 Nov 2018 smc fteteeo h oki ul nit. the on of built is example the book the hand, of other theme the the On of much salt.” “Th as of endnotes, speaker’ the grain a in sizable of fo finds a tale one insubstantial riveting theory, are variable a hidden telling instances Bohm’s After Some example: notes. An only. the in switch and n te otiuost htHiebr oeatynmd“ named aptly more Heisenberg Heisenberg Bohr, what studied th to seriously “In contributors has declares invincibi cover other who the back anyone and Becker of the but destruction, on ,” because for . praise . intent . not Advance his is with subject. This taken the So him. th author: Copenhagen Becker, kill the so-called Adam not the by of does book architect Becker key first Bohr, written Niels vividly king, this In student. rmBh isl,btfo aePtre fe orsdeath Bohr’s after B Petersen l that [ to Aage learn were speaking from one q one would Bohr but abstract if sources, himself, an Only actual Bohr the only himself. from to is Bohr trail from There its were follow it world. if quantum as no presented is “There quote, odrwehrh vrral atdt know. to wanted a auth interpretation really an ever Copenhagen For he the whether what objects? over wonder quantum here?” about on realist going a is was Bohr which in p [ collected Folse Bohr’s Henry in essays two other from 36 come the e Bohr from of and material quotes Copenhageners, about substantial c the only on text—the of the any but in from items), writings (206 of sources collections with rich appears interpretations bibliography Copenhagen many are there xesv rtnso ´o oefl [ L´eon Rosenfeld of writings extensive I o tiea ig o utkl i, ap ad Emers Waldo Ralph him,” kill must you king, a at strike you “If hti evdisedo coal ko hn nm”i an is enemy” thine “know scholarly a of instead served is What h e diini h eeec list. in reference appear the to is review addition a key of version The extended slightly a is This Review: alnegRsac ete aasSre,Selnoc 7 Stellenbosch Street, Marais Centre, Research Wallenberg oehgnItrrtto eed Est? Delenda Interpretation Copenhagen 8 ,Akd ltisy[ Plotnitsky Arkady ], hti el h nnse us o h enn fQatmP Quantum of Meaning the for Quest Unfinished The Real? is What 13 , eateto hsc,Uiest fMsahstsBoston Massachusetts of University Physics, of Department 14 .Ti htrcltcnqei ato agrpteno ba of pattern larger a of part is technique rhetorical This ]. tlebshIsiuefrAvne td (STIAS) Study Advanced for Institute Stellenbosch 0 orse olvr,Bso A015 USA 02125, MA Boston Boulevard, Morrissey 100 yAa ekr BscBos e ok 2018). York, New Books, (Basic Becker, Adam by hitpe .Fuchs A. Christopher 9 ,Jh onr[ Honner John ], 6 n .F o Weizs¨acker [ von F. C. and ] ilqikydtc htti ssml o re The true. not simply is this that detect quickly will ) and 1 10 ,adohr [ others and ], a ramn pnrprigDavid reporting upon treatment bad s nepeaino unu mechanics. quantum of interpretation ce nw etr h ut snot is quote The better: knows ecker ioohclppr [ papers hilosophical e hs eentpriual used particularly not were these ven oe xmnto n nsjs five just finds one examination loser tal asaotraiy n might one reality, about says ctually ssoyms,a et etknwith taken be best, at must, story is elce od uhhmwr on homework much do to neglected edrwosesentertainment seeks who reader a r al,vnWeizs¨acker, Rosenfeld, von Pauli, , simneywl-eerhdbook well-researched immensely is mrcnJunlo Physics of Journal American sasada neve.Btwhat But interview. an and essays eolcighwh remembered he how recollecting , o notebo’ nntsand endnotes book’s the into ook vr neto st tiea a at strike to is intention overt e eesnqoei oeinsidious, more is quote Petersen iyo or u ekesof weakness a but Bohr, of lity rwocisot“httehell the “What out cries who or h oehgnsii”[ spirit” Copenhagen the atmpyia description,” physical uantum xeddtkdw fasingle a of takedown extended noc die aoslaw famous a advised once on 0,SuhAfrica South 600, 7 ,o n fteaaye of analyses the of any or ], 11 , 12 xliigteways the explaining ] 2 , 3 ti h text the in it hysics , 4 , 5 ,o the or ], 1 . (for ] “There is no quantum world”—what might Bohr or Petersen have meant by this? Without much context for how the words were meant to be used, one is essentially free to fantasize. And that the author certainly does. The Bohr and other Copenhageners Becker constructs tip close to believing in no reality at all. They are solipsists . . . or positivists . . . or idealists . . . or operationalists . . . or, well it doesn’t really matter, as Becker doesn’t much bother to recognize distinctions between these positions anyway. (He even calls the noted pragmatist philosopher Charles Morris [15] a positivist.) More often than not though, his explicit target is a supposed connection between the Copenhagen interpretation and , viz. “the overthrow of logical positivism and the rise of scientific realism radically changed philosophy of science—and ultimately struck a major blow at the root of the Copenhagen interpretation itself.” But if so, why would Heisenberg write in Physics and Philosophy [16], “It should be noticed . . . that the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum theory is in no way positivistic.” Or again, this time paraphrasing Pauli in Physics and Beyond [17], “The positivists have gathered that describes atomic phenomena correctly, and so they have no cause for complaint. What else we have had to add—complementarity, interference of probabilities, uncertainty relations, separation of subject and object, etc.—strikes them as just so many embellishments, mere relapses into prescientific thought . . . .” To be fair, Becker does recognize a weakness in his identification of the Copenhagen interpre- tation with positivism. But as per the larger pattern, one will only see his confident exposition wane if one troubles to plumb the endnotes. In a remarkable passage, Becker writes, “Whether Bohr himself was a positivist was and is a subject of much debate. . . . But the particulars of Bohr’s views are far less significant, historically, than the fact that his views were obscure [and] that positivist reasoning was ubiquitously deployed in defense of the Copenhagen interpretation, and such defenses were often presented as the views of Bohr himself.” If everyone else does it, I can do it too? Would Bohr accept the ways Becker tries to speak for him: “There is no problem with reality in quantum physics because there is no need to think about reality in the first place.” “The theory needs no interpretation, because the things that the theory describes aren’t truly real.” “Quantum physics tells us nothing whatsoever about the world.” Surely not! As Bohr related to Thomas Kuhn in his final interview [18], “I felt . . . that philosophers were very odd people who really were lost, because they have not the instinct that it is important to learn something and that we must be prepared really to learn something of very great importance. . . . [I] think it would be reasonable to say that no man who is called a philosopher really understands what one means by the complementary description.” Bohr certainly thought we learned something deep and profound about nature with the discovery of quantum theory. In one of the endnotes Becker marvels that Kuhn in his historical work and the philosopher Norwood Russell Hanson— two thinkers he clearly respects—could be philosophically anti-positivistic, yet fairly keen on the Copenhagen interpretation. Reflection on the idea that maybe they knew what he didn’t, i.e., that the issues might be more subtle than he imagined, does not appear to be in his list of options. Perhaps Pauli of all the Copenhageners described best the distinction between what they aimed for (no matter what their errors) and the way Becker portrays them [19]: “[I] invariably profited very greatly even when I could not agree with Einstein’s views. ‘Physics is after all the description of reality,’ he said to me, continuing, with a sarcastic glance in my direction, ‘or should I perhaps say physics is the description of what one merely imagines?’ This question clearly shows Einstein’s concern that the objective character of physics might be lost through a theory of the type of quantum mechanics, in that as a consequence of its wider conception of objectivity of an explanation of nature the difference between physical reality and dream or hallucination become blurred. . . . Einstein however advocated a narrower form of the reality concept.” [Emphasis added.] The Copenhageners saw in quantum theory not a less robust reality than in classical physics, but one that was more than

2 can be captured in classical-style terms. It is this idea that most modern philosophers of physics and apparently Becker himself have a hard time getting their heads around [20]. And thus perhaps their reaction is no wonder: When something cannot be expressed in the limited vocabulary native to their ears, what else could follow but frustration? But, this is no excuse to flub the very basics of the debate. There are a number of historical errors in the book, most of them minor. For instance, Wigner did not introduce the term “the problem of measurement” in 1963; it goes back at least to a 1949 paper of Jordan [22]. The Nobel prize of 1938 was not valued at $1,000,000, even in 2017 dollars [21]. And Kramers, Gamow, von Weizs¨acker, Peierls, and Wheeler were not Bohr’s students, but his postdoctoral employees. However, one error is absolutely unforgivable given the subject of the book: Becker actually gets the Einstein, Podolsky, Rosen (EPR) argument wrong!1 In his scenario, starting with two entangled particles and the assumption of locality, he tries to establish that each particle simultaneously has a position and a momentum by supposing the one measurement on one and the other measurement on the other. But that is not what EPR consider: Their hypothetical measurements are made only on one particle, from which they draw inferences about what would happen if they were to perform the same measurement on the other. This change makes all the conceptual difference in the world [23]. When an author does not understand the argument himself, should he have the right to declare, “It’s unclear how [Bohr’s response] relates to the EPR argument,” and dismiss it as “muddled writing?” But I did say the book is vividly written, and indeed it is. It shines when it reports on those attempts to interpret quantum theory along the lines of what Pauli called a “narrower form of the reality concept”—technically speaking, those interpretations where nonlocality is a genuine feature of nature and/or quantum states are understood to represent actual attributes of quantum systems, not just information, knowledge, or beliefs. Becker’s sketches of , Hugh Everett III, John Bell, and others involved in those developments are compelling and humane. Many of these great names are his heroes, and it comes through in the care with which he tells their stories. In this review, however, I opted to focus on the side of the book critical to Copenhagen because I know there will be many reviews positive on it through and through, such is the mood in the philosophy of physics community. It is only that there is a need for damage control with a book so disingenuous. I will be the first to admit that Bohr, Pauli, Heisenberg, and all the others were no oracles, no ultimate authorities. Their views did often contain inconsistencies. But, what this book leaves out is the spur to thought the Copenhagen interpretation has been for so many in the quantum information and computing communities. E. T. Jaynes put the challenge of how to right the wrongs of Copenhagen this way [24]: “[O]ur present [quantum mechanical] formalism is . . . a peculiar mixture describing in part realities of Nature, in part incomplete human information about Nature—all scrambled up together by Heisenberg and Bohr into an omelette that nobody has seen how to unscramble. Yet we think the unscrambling is a prerequisite for any further advance in basic physical theory.” From this point of view, the tools and concepts of quantum information are what were needed to make sense of the deeper elements of the Copenhagen interpretation all along [25, 26, 27]. Yet, this is an interpretative route hardly mentioned in Becker’s book, though it now commands a significant portion of quantum foundations research worldwide [28]. To quote from an essay of D. M. Appleby [29], one of the researchers in that community, “If I am asked to accept Bohr as the authoritative voice of final truth, then I cannot assent. But if his writings are approached in a more flexible spirit, as a source of insights which are not the less seminal for being obscure, they

1Note added in proof: The error was corrected at the book’s fourth printing, after being pointed out by David Albert and N. David Mermin. See Errata for What Is Real.

3 suggest some interesting questions. I do not know if this line of thought will be fruitful. But I feel it is worth pursuing.” The worry to my mind is what if a young student encounters Adam Becker’s book, with its tale of the Copenhagen interpretation being a “mishmash of solipsism and poor reasoning” before she has a chance to read any of the Copenhageners herself? She may never follow the pursuit Appleby suggested, and physics could be impoverished for it.

Christopher A. Fuchs is a Professor of Physics at the University of Massachusetts Boston and a Fellow of the Stellenbosch Institute for Advanced Study in South Africa. Notwithstanding the irony of it, he once compiled a list of every sentence in Bohr’s philosophical writings that started with the word “notwithstanding.” He found 39.

References

[1] W. Heisenberg, The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory, (Dover, New York, 1930).

[2] N. Bohr, The Philosophical Writings of , Volume I: Atomic Theory and the Descrip- tion of Nature, (Ox Bow Press, Woodbridge, CT, 1987).

[3] N. Bohr, Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge, (Dover, New York, 2010).

[4] N. Bohr, The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Volume III: Essays 1958–1962 on Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge, (Ox Bow Press, Woodbridge, CT, 1987).

[5] N. Bohr, The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Volume IV: Causality and Complementar- ity, edited by J. Faye and H. J. Folse, (Ox Bow Press, Woodbridge, CT, 1998).

[6] L. Rosenfeld, Selected Papers of L´eon Rosenfeld, edited by R. S. Cohen and J. J. Stachel, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume XXI, (D. Riedel, Dordrecht, 1979).

[7] C. F. von Weizs¨acker, The Unity of Nature, (Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, New York, 1980).

[8] H. J. Folse, The Philosophy of Niels Bohr: The Framework of Complementarity, (North Hol- land, Amsterdam, 1985).

[9] A. Plotnitsky, Niels Bohr and Complementarity: An Introduction, (Springer Scientific Pub- lishers, Berlin, 2012).

[10] J. Honner, The Description of Nature: Niels Bohr and the Philosophy of Quantum Physics, (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1987).

[11] D. Murdoch, Niels Bohr’s Philosophy of Physics, (Cambridge University Press, 1987).

[12] C. A. Hooker, “The Nature of Quantum Mechanical Reality: Einstein Versus Bohr,” in Paradigms & Paradoxes: The Philosophical Challenge of the Quantum Domain, edited by R. G. Colodny, (University of Pittsburgh Press, 1972), pp. 67–302.

[13] A. Petersen, “The Philosophy of Niels Bohr,” Bull. Atom. Sci. 19(7), 8 (1963).

[14] N. D. Mermin, “What’s Wrong With This Quantum World?” Phys. Tod. 52(2), 10 (2004).

[15] See “Charles William Morris, 1901-1979” at the Pragmatism Cybrary.

4 [16] W. Heisenberg, Physics and Philosophy: The Revolution in Modern Science, (Harper & Row, New York, 1958).

[17] W. Heisenberg, Physics and Beyond: Encounters and Conversations, (Harper & Row, New York, 1971).

[18] N. Bohr, with T. S. Kuhn, L. Rosenfeld, A. Petersen, and E. Rudinger, “Niels Bohr: Session V,” American Institute of Physics Oral History Interviews (1962).

[19] W. Pauli, “ and the Development of Physics,” in Writings on Physics and Philosophy, edited by C. P. Enz and K. von Meyenn, (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1994), pp. 117– 123.

[20] C. A. Fuchs, “On Participatory Realism,” in Information and Interaction: Eddington, Wheeler, and the Limits of Knowledge, edited by I. T. Durham and D. Rickles, (Springer, Berlin, 2016), pp. 113–134. arXiv:1601.04360.

[21] “The Nobel Prize Amounts,” NobelPrize.org. Nobel Media AB 2018. Tue. 11 Sep 2018.

[22] P. Jordan, “On the Process of Measurement in Quantum Mechanics,” Phil. Sci. 16, 269 (1949).

[23] B. C. Stacey, “Misreading EPR: Variations on an Incorrect Theme,” arXiv:1809.01751.

[24] E. T. Jaynes, “Probability in Quantum Theory,” in Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information, edited by W. H. Zurek, (Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA, 1990), pp. 381–404.

[25] C. A. Fuchs, “Quantum Foundations in the Light of Quantum Information,” in Decoherence and its Implications in Quantum Computation and Information Transfer, edited by A. Gonis and P. E. A. Turchi (IOS Press, Amsterdam, 2001), pp. 38–82. arXiv:quant-ph/0106166.

[26] C. A. Fuchs, Coming of Age with Quantum Information: Notes on a Paulian Idea, (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 2010).

[27] C. A. Fuchs, “Notwithstanding Bohr, the Reasons for QBism,” Mind and Matter 15, 245 (2017). arXiv:1705.03483. [28] There are too many scientific papers to cite here, but perhaps a sense of the amount of activity in the last 15 years can be given by a small sampling of conferences devoted predominantly to the subject:

• Seven Pines Symposium VIII: Quantum Mechanics, Quantum Information, and Quantum Computation (5–9 May 2004); • Quantum Information, Computation and Logic: Exploring New Connections (17–22 July 2005); • Information Primitives and the Laws of Nature (13–17 May 2008); • Reconstructing Quantum Theory (9–15 August 2009); • Nagoya Winter Workshop on Quantum Information, Measurement, and Foundations (18–24 February 2010); • Fundamentals of Physics and Information (8–11 June 2010); • Quantum Physics in Higher-Dimensional Hilbert Spaces (25–29 July 2010); • NORDITA Workshop on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics (27 September–1 October 2010); • Conceptual Foundations and Foils for Quantum Information Processing (9–13 May 2011);

5 • Quantum States: Ontic or Epistemic? (25–26 June 2011); • Workshop on Quantum Correlations, Contextuality and All That (9–13 December 2013); • Workshop on Quantum Foundations at the ETH Institute for Theoretical Studies (13–17 October 2014); • International Workshop: What is Quantum Information? (18–22 May 2015); • Hong Kong Workshop on Quantum Information and Foundations (4–7 May 2016); • AQP2016: Conference on Agency and (quantum) Physics (20–23 September 2016); • Workshop on Participatory Realism (6–8 June 2017); • Solstice of Foundations – ETH Zurich, Contextuality Workshop (22–23 June 1017); • Hong Kong Workshop on Quantum Information and Foundations: Focus on Physics of the Observer (8–12 January 2018), • and not to forget its significant showing at the major yearly V¨axj¨o, Sweden conference organized by Andrei Khrennikov.

I suspect it would be difficult for pursuers of hidden-variable theories, spontaneous collapse models, and many-worlds interpretations to exhibit a similar quantity of research activity in their own fields.

[29] D. M. Appleby, “Facts, Values and Quanta,” Found. Phys. 35, 637 (2005). quant-ph/0402015.

6