Modes of Argumentation in Aristotle's Natural Science

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Modes of Argumentation in Aristotle's Natural Science Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 11-19-2019 2:30 PM Modes of Argumentation in Aristotle's Natural Science Adam W. Woodcox The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Henry, Devin The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Adam W. Woodcox 2019 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Woodcox, Adam W., "Modes of Argumentation in Aristotle's Natural Science" (2019). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 6769. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/6769 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Abstract Through a detailed analysis of the various modes of argumentation employed by Aristotle throughout his natural scientific works, I aim to contribute to the growing scholarship on the relation between Aristotle’s theory of science and his actual scientific practice. I challenge the standard reading of Aristotle as a methodological empiricist and show that he permits a variety of non-empirical arguments to support controversial theses in properly scientific contexts. Specifically, I examine his use of logical (logikôs) argumentation in the discussion of mule sterility in Generation of Animals II 8, rational (kata ton logon) argumentation in his discussion of cardiocentrism throughout the biological works, and the method of division in Posterior Analytics II 13. Summary for Lay Audiences The ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle relied on information gained through the senses to guide his scientific theorizing about many subjects, including the motions of the heavenly bodies and the behaviour of animals. Focusing on a few examples drawn from a variety of Aristotle's scientific works, I argue that he also relied on reason. We see perception and reason at play in Aristotle's investigations of reproduction, the role of the heart in animal life, and scientific definitions. Keywords Aristotle, natural philosophy, rationalism, empiricism, argumentation, cardiocentrism, scientific method, epistemology, scientific inquiry, Plato i For Mary ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank first and foremost my supervisor, Dr. Devin Henry, for his encouragement and guidance throughout this project. From our early meetings on the Posterior Analytics to more recent discussions of the Metaphysics, I have always been challenged to think for myself and develop my own views independently of the orthodoxy—so long as those views can be supported by the text. Thanks also to my supervisory committee, Dr. John Thorp and Dr. Lorne Falkenstein. A special thanks is due to Dr. Thorp, whose reading groups and “Greek Gang” meetings were foundational to the community of ancient scholarship during my time at Western. I am grateful to Dr. Mariska Leunissen, Dr. C. D. C. Reeve, and the Department of Philosophy at UNC–Chapel Hill for hosting me during the Winter of 2018. I received helpful comments on earlier drafts of this material from Dr. Leunissen, Dr. Reeve, Dr. Joseph Karbowski, and audiences at meetings of the Canadian Philosophical Association, the Classical Association of Canada, and the Canadian Colloquium for Ancient Philosophy. Thanks also to my colleagues and friends for discussions of much of this material: Cecilia Li, Justin Bzovy, Matt Watton, Dan Coren, Mike Korngut, Jamie Shaw, and many others; to my mother Carolyn, my father Bill, and my brother Nathan for their unconditional support and encouragement throughout this process; and to the lovely Joshuelle Solomon for her joyful disposition and enduring optimism. This project was funded by a fellowship from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. iii Table of Contents Abstract i Dedication ii Acknowledgements iii 0 Introduction 0.0 Introduction 1 0.1 The Dual Knowledge Criterion in the Early Commentators 6 0.2 Outline 10 1 Two Kinds of Proof in Aristotle’s Natural Science 1.0 Introduction 12 1.1 The Many Senses of Source 16 1.2 Cardiocentrism in De Iuventute 18 1.2.1 Perceptual Arguments in De Iuv. 20 1.2.2 Rational Arguments in De Iuv. 23 1.3 Cardiocentrism in Parts of Animals III 4 31 1.4 Cardiocentrism in Generation of Animals II 4-5 40 1.5 Perceptual Argumentation 44 1.5.1 De Caelo II 14: The Sphericity of the Earth 48 1.6 Conclusion 51 2 Logikôs Argumentation in Aristotle’s Natural Science 2.0 Introduction 55 2.1.1 Introducing the Problêmata 60 2.1.2 Explaining Sterility Generally 63 2.2 Explaining Sterility in Mules 64 2.3 Aristotle’s Logikôs Demonstration 71 2.4 Aristotle’s Preferred Explanation 82 2.5 Positive Uses of Logikôs Reasoning 86 2.6 Conclusion 94 2.7 Appendix 95 3 The Hunt for Definitions: Posterior Analytics II 13 3.0 Introduction 98 3.1 APo II 5 and the Critique of Division 100 3.2 The Context of The Hunt 102 3.3 The Method for Hunting the Infima Species 103 3.4 Division and Order: 96b26-97a6 105 3.5 Three Rules for Dividing: 97a23-b6 107 3.6 The Problem of Homonymy: 97b6-25 109 3.7 Conclusion 110 4 Conclusion 112 iv 0.0 INTRODUCTION There has been a longstanding debate about the relation between Aristotle’s theory of science and his actual scientific practice. This debate usually centers on the question of how Aristotle’s views on the nature of scientific knowledge, as presented in the Posterior Analytics, line up with the his natural-scientific works. For instance, scholars raise many issues surrounding the role of demonstration, which is front and centre in Book One of APo. but almost absent elsewhere in the corpus. Similar questions are raised about Aristotle’s theory of definition, which is presented in Book Two of APo. and seems to guide much of his enquiry into nature. I aim to contribute to the debate surrounding the relation between Aristotle’s theory and practice, but I take a less comparative approach than most. On the comparative approach, we take the theory presented in the Posterior Analytics to represent Aristotle’s theory of science, and then see how it applies (or fails to apply) to other parts of the corpus, namely the natural-scientific works wherein we find Aristotle practicing science. Although the comparative approach can be very valuable, it is not the only way to address the question of the relation between Aristotle’s theory and practice of science. We often find Aristotle declaring his commitment to certain theoretical standards or ideals in his natural-scientific works, or indeed employing a certain standard without ever explicitly defending it—as we find, for instance, in his use of rational and perceptual argumentation in his defence of cardiocentrism and elsewhere. Through a detailed analysis of the various modes of argumentation employed by Aristotle throughout his natural scientific works, I aim to contribute to the scholarship on the relation between Aristotle’s theory of science and his actual scientific practice. 1 Specifically, I consider what kinds of argumentation are permissible in scientific contexts, focusing especially on his use of, rational (kata ton logon) argumentation in his discussion of cardiocentrism throughout the biological works, logical (logikôs) argumentation in the discussion of mule sterility in Generation of Animals II 8, and the method of division in Posterior Analytics II 13. I challenge the standard reading of Aristotle as a thoroughgoing methodological empiricist and show that he permits a variety of non-empirical arguments to support controversial theses in properly scientific domains. Throughout his natural-scientific works, Aristotle repeatedly emphasizes that we should give pride of place to empirical evidence when we are constructing scientific theories. He admonishes the Platonists for relying on arguments in the absence of observation and argues that theories ought to conform to the facts. This attitude is apparent in a number of texts. For instance, Aristotle begins his investigation in De Motu Animalium by invoking the principle that movement requires something at rest. The necessity of something being at rest for movement on a cosmic scale has already been established in the discussion of eternal motion in Physics VIII with reference to the Prime Mover. But Aristotle now aims to establish that this principle holds too in the case of animal motion, where the role of the unmoved mover is filled by the joint, so that as the limb moves the joint remains at rest. [T1] “And we must grasp this not only generally in theory, but also by reference to individuals in the world of sense; for with these in view we seek general theories, and with these we believe that general theories ought to harmonize.” (De Motu 1, 698a11-14)1 δεῖ δὲ τοῦτο μὴ μόνον τῷ λόγῳ λαβεῖν, ἀλλὰ καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν καθ’ ἕκαστα καὶ τῶν αἰσθητῶν, δι’ ἅπερ καὶ τοὺς καθόλου ζητοῦμεν λόγους, καὶ ἐφ’ ὧν ἐφαρμόττειν οἰόμεθα δεῖν αὐτούς. 1 Trans. A. S. L. Farquharson (1984). 2 The discussion of the Prime Mover in Physics VIII allowed us to grasp the principle in question ‘by reason’ (τῷ λόγῳ). Presumably, Aristotle would identify the argument offered in support of this conclusion as an instance of rational argumentation. Since the investigation in De Motu turns to the common cause of all kinds of animal motion (whether flying, swimming, or walking), the same principle is now shown to hold of animal motion via perceptual argumentation (the nature of which will be discussed in Chapter 1). Importantly, Aristotle here claims that we should seek general theories that are in harmony with the perceptual phenomena; we should not allow our antecedent theories to bias our observations, but rather should let the facts lead us to our theories.
Recommended publications
  • Science Standards
    SCIENCE It is the policy of the Oklahoma State Department of Education (OSDE) not to discriminate on the basis of race, color, religion, gender, national origin, age, or disability in its programs or employment practices as required by Title VI and VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, and Section 504 of the Rehabilitation Act of 1973. Civil rights compliance inquiries related to the OSDE may be directed to the Affirmative Action Officer, Room 111, 2500 North Lincoln Boulevard, Oklahoma City, Oklahoma 73105-4599, telephone number (405) 522-4930; or, the United States Department of Education’s Assistant Secretary for Civil Rights. Inquires or concerns regarding compliance with Title IX by local school districts should be presented to the local school district Title IX coordinator. This publication, printed by the State Department of Education Printing Services, is issued by the Oklahoma State Department of Education as authorized by 70 O.S. § 3-104. Five hundred copies have been prepared using Title I, Part A, School Improvement funds at a cost of $.15 per copy. Copies have been deposited with the Publications Clearinghouse of the Oklahoma Department of Libraries. DECEMBER 2013. SCIENCE Table of Contents 5-8 Introduction 9 K-5 Overview 10-18 ■ KINDERGARTEN 19-28 ■ 1ST GRADE 29-39 ■ 2ND GRADE 40-54 ■ 3RD GRADE 55-68 ■ 4TH GRADE 69-82 ■ 5TH GRADE 83 6-12 Overview 84-101 ■ 6TH GRADE 102-119 ■ 7TH GRADE 120-137 ■ 8TH GRADE 138-152 ■ PHYSICAL SCIENCE 153-165 ■ CHEMISTRY 166-181 ■ PHYSICS 182-203 ■ BIOLOGY I 204-219 ■ EARTH & SPACE SCIENCE 220-235 ■ ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCE Introduction Science uses observation and experimentation to explain natural phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • A Comprehensive Framework to Reinforce Evidence Synthesis Features in Cloud-Based Systematic Review Tools
    applied sciences Article A Comprehensive Framework to Reinforce Evidence Synthesis Features in Cloud-Based Systematic Review Tools Tatiana Person 1,* , Iván Ruiz-Rube 1 , José Miguel Mota 1 , Manuel Jesús Cobo 1 , Alexey Tselykh 2 and Juan Manuel Dodero 1 1 Department of Informatics Engineering, University of Cadiz, 11519 Puerto Real, Spain; [email protected] (I.R.-R.); [email protected] (J.M.M.); [email protected] (M.J.C.); [email protected] (J.M.D.) 2 Department of Information and Analytical Security Systems, Institute of Computer Technologies and Information Security, Southern Federal University, 347922 Taganrog, Russia; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] Abstract: Systematic reviews are powerful methods used to determine the state-of-the-art in a given field from existing studies and literature. They are critical but time-consuming in research and decision making for various disciplines. When conducting a review, a large volume of data is usually generated from relevant studies. Computer-based tools are often used to manage such data and to support the systematic review process. This paper describes a comprehensive analysis to gather the required features of a systematic review tool, in order to support the complete evidence synthesis process. We propose a framework, elaborated by consulting experts in different knowledge areas, to evaluate significant features and thus reinforce existing tool capabilities. The framework will be used to enhance the currently available functionality of CloudSERA, a cloud-based systematic review Citation: Person, T.; Ruiz-Rube, I.; Mota, J.M.; Cobo, M.J.; Tselykh, A.; tool focused on Computer Science, to implement evidence-based systematic review processes in Dodero, J.M.
    [Show full text]
  • Mothers in Science
    The aim of this book is to illustrate, graphically, that it is perfectly possible to combine a successful and fulfilling career in research science with motherhood, and that there are no rules about how to do this. On each page you will find a timeline showing on one side, the career path of a research group leader in academic science, and on the other side, important events in her family life. Each contributor has also provided a brief text about their research and about how they have combined their career and family commitments. This project was funded by a Rosalind Franklin Award from the Royal Society 1 Foreword It is well known that women are under-represented in careers in These rules are part of a much wider mythology among scientists of science. In academia, considerable attention has been focused on the both genders at the PhD and post-doctoral stages in their careers. paucity of women at lecturer level, and the even more lamentable The myths bubble up from the combination of two aspects of the state of affairs at more senior levels. The academic career path has academic science environment. First, a quick look at the numbers a long apprenticeship. Typically there is an undergraduate degree, immediately shows that there are far fewer lectureship positions followed by a PhD, then some post-doctoral research contracts and than qualified candidates to fill them. Second, the mentors of early research fellowships, and then finally a more stable lectureship or career researchers are academic scientists who have successfully permanent research leader position, with promotion on up the made the transition to lectureships and beyond.
    [Show full text]
  • How Science Works
    PB 1 How science works The Scientific Method is traditionally presented in the first chapter of science text- books as a simple recipe for performing scientific investigations. Though many use- ful points are embodied in this method, it can easily be misinterpreted as linear and “cookbook”: pull a problem off the shelf, throw in an observation, mix in a few ques- tions, sprinkle on a hypothesis, put the whole mixture into a 350° experiment—and voila, 50 minutes later you’ll be pulling a conclusion out of the oven! That might work if science were like Hamburger Helper®, but science is complex and cannot be re- duced to a single, prepackaged recipe. The linear, stepwise representation of the process of science is simplified, but it does get at least one thing right. It captures the core logic of science: testing ideas with evidence. However, this version of the scientific method is so simplified and rigid that it fails to accurately portray how real science works. It more accurately describes how science is summarized after the fact—in textbooks and journal articles—than how sci- ence is actually done. The simplified, linear scientific method implies that scientific studies follow an unvarying, linear recipe. But in reality, in their work, scientists engage in many different activities in many different sequences. Scientific investigations often involve repeating the same steps many times to account for new information and ideas. The simplified, linear scientific method implies that science is done by individual scientists working through these steps in isolation. But in reality, science depends on interactions within the scientific community.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Science Reading List
    Philosophy of Science Area Comprehensive Exam Reading List Revised September 2011 Exam Format: Students will have four hours to write answers to four questions, chosen from a list of approximately 20-30 questions organized according to topic: I. General Philosophy of Science II. History of Philosophy of Science III. Special Topics a. Philosophy of Physics b. Philosophy of Biology c. Philosophy of Mind / Cognitive Science d. Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Students are required to answer a total of three questions from sections I and II (at least one from each section), and one question from section III. For each section, we have provided a list of core readings—mostly journal articles and book chapters—that are representative of the material with which we expect you to be familiar. Many of these readings will already be familiar to you from your coursework and other reading. Use this as a guide to filling in areas in which you are less well- prepared. Please note, however, that these readings do not constitute necessary or sufficient background to pass the comp. The Philosophy of Science area committee assumes that anyone who plans to write this exam has a good general background in the area acquired through previous coursework and independent reading. Some anthologies There are several good anthologies of Philosophy of Science that will be useful for further background (many of the articles listed below are anthologized; references included in the list below). Richard Boyd, Philip Gasper, and J.D. Trout, eds., The Philosophy of Science (MIT Press, 991). Martin Curd and J.
    [Show full text]
  • PDF Download Starting with Science Strategies for Introducing Young Children to Inquiry 1St Edition Ebook
    STARTING WITH SCIENCE STRATEGIES FOR INTRODUCING YOUNG CHILDREN TO INQUIRY 1ST EDITION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Marcia Talhelm Edson | 9781571108074 | | | | | Starting with Science Strategies for Introducing Young Children to Inquiry 1st edition PDF Book The presentation of the material is as good as the material utilizing star trek analogies, ancient wisdom and literature and so much more. Using Multivariate Statistics. Michael Gramling examines the impact of policy on practice in early childhood education. Part of a series on. Schauble and colleagues , for example, found that fifth grade students designed better experiments after instruction about the purpose of experimentation. For example, some suggest that learning about NoS enables children to understand the tentative and developmental NoS and science as a human activity, which makes science more interesting for children to learn Abd-El-Khalick a ; Driver et al. Research on teaching and learning of nature of science. The authors begin with theory in a cultural context as a foundation. What makes professional development effective? Frequently, the term NoS is utilised when considering matters about science. This book is a documentary account of a young intern who worked in the Reggio system in Italy and how she brought this pedagogy home to her school in St. Taking Science to School answers such questions as:. The content of the inquiries in science in the professional development programme was based on the different strands of the primary science curriculum, namely Living Things, Energy and Forces, Materials and Environmental Awareness and Care DES Exit interview. Begin to address the necessity of understanding other usually peer positions before they can discuss or comment on those positions.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Science and History of Technology (Class Q, R, S, T, and Applicable Z)
    LIBRARY OF CONGRESS COLLECTIONS POLICY STATEMENTS History of Science and History of Technology (Class Q, R, S, T, and applicable Z) Contents I. Scope II. Research strengths III. General collecting policy IV. Best editions and preferred formats V. Acquisitions sources: current and future VI. Collecting levels I. Scope This Collections Policy Statement covers all of the subclasses of Science and Technology and treats the history of these disciplines together. In a certain sense, most of the materials in Q, R, S, and T are part of the history of science and technology. The Library has extensive resources in the history of medicine and agriculture, but many years ago a decision was made that the Library should not intensively collect materials in clinical medicine and technical agriculture, as they are subject specialties of the National Library of Medicine and the National Agricultural Library, respectively. In addition, some of the numerous abstracting and indexing services, catalogs of other scientific and technical collections and libraries, specialized bibliographies, and finding aids for the history of science and technology are maintained in class Z. See the list of finding aids online: http://findingaids.loc.gov/. II. Research strengths 1. General The Library’s collections are robust in both the history of science and the history of technology. Both collections comprise two major elements: the seminal works of science and technology themselves, and historiographies on notable scientific and technological works. The former comprise the original classic works of science and technology as they were composed by the men and women who ushered in the era of modern science and invention.
    [Show full text]
  • Multidisciplinary Design Project Engineering Dictionary Version 0.0.2
    Multidisciplinary Design Project Engineering Dictionary Version 0.0.2 February 15, 2006 . DRAFT Cambridge-MIT Institute Multidisciplinary Design Project This Dictionary/Glossary of Engineering terms has been compiled to compliment the work developed as part of the Multi-disciplinary Design Project (MDP), which is a programme to develop teaching material and kits to aid the running of mechtronics projects in Universities and Schools. The project is being carried out with support from the Cambridge-MIT Institute undergraduate teaching programe. For more information about the project please visit the MDP website at http://www-mdp.eng.cam.ac.uk or contact Dr. Peter Long Prof. Alex Slocum Cambridge University Engineering Department Massachusetts Institute of Technology Trumpington Street, 77 Massachusetts Ave. Cambridge. Cambridge MA 02139-4307 CB2 1PZ. USA e-mail: [email protected] e-mail: [email protected] tel: +44 (0) 1223 332779 tel: +1 617 253 0012 For information about the CMI initiative please see Cambridge-MIT Institute website :- http://www.cambridge-mit.org CMI CMI, University of Cambridge Massachusetts Institute of Technology 10 Miller’s Yard, 77 Massachusetts Ave. Mill Lane, Cambridge MA 02139-4307 Cambridge. CB2 1RQ. USA tel: +44 (0) 1223 327207 tel. +1 617 253 7732 fax: +44 (0) 1223 765891 fax. +1 617 258 8539 . DRAFT 2 CMI-MDP Programme 1 Introduction This dictionary/glossary has not been developed as a definative work but as a useful reference book for engi- neering students to search when looking for the meaning of a word/phrase. It has been compiled from a number of existing glossaries together with a number of local additions.
    [Show full text]
  • Sacred Rhetorical Invention in the String Theory Movement
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Communication Studies Theses, Dissertations, and Student Research Communication Studies, Department of Spring 4-12-2011 Secular Salvation: Sacred Rhetorical Invention in the String Theory Movement Brent Yergensen University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/commstuddiss Part of the Speech and Rhetorical Studies Commons Yergensen, Brent, "Secular Salvation: Sacred Rhetorical Invention in the String Theory Movement" (2011). Communication Studies Theses, Dissertations, and Student Research. 6. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/commstuddiss/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Communication Studies, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Communication Studies Theses, Dissertations, and Student Research by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. SECULAR SALVATION: SACRED RHETORICAL INVENTION IN THE STRING THEORY MOVEMENT by Brent Yergensen A DISSERTATION Presented to the Faculty of The Graduate College at the University of Nebraska In Partial Fulfillment of Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Major: Communication Studies Under the Supervision of Dr. Ronald Lee Lincoln, Nebraska April, 2011 ii SECULAR SALVATION: SACRED RHETORICAL INVENTION IN THE STRING THEORY MOVEMENT Brent Yergensen, Ph.D. University of Nebraska, 2011 Advisor: Ronald Lee String theory is argued by its proponents to be the Theory of Everything. It achieves this status in physics because it provides unification for contradictory laws of physics, namely quantum mechanics and general relativity. While based on advanced theoretical mathematics, its public discourse is growing in prevalence and its rhetorical power is leading to a scientific revolution, even among the public.
    [Show full text]
  • What Scientific Theories Could Not Be Author(S): Hans Halvorson Reviewed Work(S): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol
    What Scientific Theories Could Not Be Author(s): Hans Halvorson Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol. 79, No. 2 (April 2012), pp. 183-206 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/664745 . Accessed: 03/12/2012 10:32 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press and Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.52.67 on Mon, 3 Dec 2012 10:32:52 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions What Scientific Theories Could Not Be* Hans Halvorson†‡ According to the semantic view of scientific theories, theories are classes of models. I show that this view—if taken literally—leads to absurdities. In particular, this view equates theories that are distinct, and it distinguishes theories that are equivalent. Furthermore, the semantic view lacks the resources to explicate interesting theoretical relations, such as embeddability of one theory into another.
    [Show full text]
  • Science Academic Standards Over the Course of the Cyclical Review Process and Their Efforts and Input Are Appreciated
    SOUTH CAROLINA ACADEMIC STANDARDS AND PERFORMANCE INDICATORS FOR SCIENCE Mick Zais, Ph.D. State Superintendent of Education South Carolina Department of Education Columbia, South Carolina This document approved by Education Oversight Committee and State Board of Education Contents Acknowledgements ........................................................................................................................ iii Introduction .................................................................................................................................... 1 Academic Standards and Performance Indicators for Science Kindergarten .................................................................................................................................... 5 Grade 1 .......................................................................................................................................... 11 Grade 2 .......................................................................................................................................... 18 Grade 3 .......................................................................................................................................... 25 Grade 4 .......................................................................................................................................... 32 Grade 5 .......................................................................................................................................... 39 Grade 6 .........................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Causes As Explanations: a Critique*
    JAEGWON KIM CAUSES AS EXPLANATIONS: A CRITIQUE* Causes certainly are connected with effects; but this is because our theories connect them, not because the world is held together by cosmic glue. 1 Norwood Russell Hanson ABSTRACT. This paper offers a critique of the view that causation can be analyzed in terms of explanation. In particular, the following points are argued: (1) a genuine explanatory analysis of causation must make use of a fully epistemological-psychological notion of explanation; (2) it is unlikely that the relatively clear-cut structure of the causal relation can be captured by the relatively unstructured relation of explanation; (3) the explanatory relation does not always parallel the direction of causation; (4) certain difficulties arise for any attempt to construct a nonrelativistic relation of caus- ation from the essentially relativistic relation of explanation; and (5) to analyze causation as explanation is to embrace a form of "causal idealism", the view that causal connec- tions are not among the objective features of the world. The paper closes with a brief discussion of the contrast between the two fundamentally opposed viewpoints about causality, namely causal idealism and causal realism. It is little more than a truism to say that causes explain their effects, or that to ask for the cause of an event is to ask for an explanation of why or how the event occurred. This close association between causation and explanation is amply mirrored in language: we answer 'why'-questions with 'becuase'- statements, and surely there is more than an orthographic resemblance between 'cause' and 'because'. The association is also ancient: it goes back to Aristotle, who characterized true, scientific knowledge as knowledge of the 'why' of things, that is, knowledge of the cause that makes a thing what it is and not something else.
    [Show full text]