James Rachels-The Social Contract Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

James Rachels-The Social Contract Theory Confirming Pages T he Elements of Moral Philosophy SEVENTH EDITION James Rachels Editions 5–7 by Stuart Rachels rac38243_fm_i-xii.indd i 10/27/11 7:07 PM Confirming Pages THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY, SEVENTH EDITION Published by McGraw-Hill, a business unit of The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc., 1221 Avenue of the Americas, New York, NY 10020. Copyright © 2012 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. Previous editions © 2010, 2007, and 2003. Printed in the United States of America. No part of this publication may be reproduced or distributed in any form or by any means, or stored in a database or retrieval system, without the prior written consent of The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc., including, but not limited to, in any network or other electronic storage or transmission, or broadcast for distance learning. Some ancillaries, including electronic and print components, may not be available to customers outside the United States. This book is printed on acid-free paper. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0 DOC/ DOC 1 0 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 ISBN 978-0-07-803824-2 MHID 0-07-803824-3 Vice President & Editor-in-Chief: Michael Ryan Vice President & Director of Specialized Publishing: Janice M. Roerig-Blong Sponsoring Editor: Jessica Cannavo Marketing Coordinator: Angela R. FitzPatrick Project Manager: Jolynn Kilburg Design Coordinator: Margarite Reynolds Buyer: Louis Swaim Media Project Manager: Sridevi Palani Compositor: Laserwords Private Limited Typeface: 11/12 New Baskerville Printer: R. R. Donnelley Cover painting: Aleksandr Rodchenko. (Russian, 1891–1956). Non-Objective Painting no. 80 (Black on Black). 1918. Oil on canvas, 32 1/4 3 31 1/4” (81.9 3 79.4 cm). Gift of the artist, through Jay Leyda. The Museum of Modern Art, New York. Digital Image © 2006 The Museum of Modern Art/Licensed by Scala/Art Resource, NY. © Alexander Rodchenko/RAO, Moscow/ VAGA, New York All credits appearing on page or at the end of the book are considered to be an extension of the copyright page. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Rachels, Stuart, 1969– The elements of moral philosophy/James Rachels.—7th ed. by Stuart Rachels. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-07-803824-2 (alk. paper) 1. Ethics—Textbooks. I. Rachels, James, 1941–2003. Elements of moral philosophy. II. Title. BJ1012.R29 2013 170—dc23 2011042104 www.mhhe.com rac38243_fm_i-xii.indd ii 10/27/11 7:07 PM Confirming Pages CHAPTER 6 The Social Contract Theory Wherever law ends, tyranny begins . John Locke, THE SECOND TREATISE OF GOVERNMENT (1690) 6.1. Hobbes’s Argument Suppose we take away all the traditional props for morality. Assume, first, that there is no God to issue commands and reward virtue. Next, suppose that there are no “natural purposes”— objects in nature have no inherent functions or intended uses. Finally, assume that human beings are naturally selfish. Where, then, could morality come from? If we cannot appeal to God, natu- ral purpose, or altruism, is there anything left to base morality on? Thomas Hobbes, the leading British philosopher of the 17th century, tried to show that morality does not depend on any of those things. Instead, morality should be understood as the solution to a practical problem that arises for self-interested human beings. We all want to live as well as possible; but in order to flourish, we need a peaceful, cooperative social order. And we cannot have one without rules. Those rules are the moral rules; morality consists of the precepts we need to follow in order to get the benefits of social living. That—not God, inherent pur- poses, or altruism—is the key to understanding ethics. Hobbes begins by asking what it would be like if there were no way to enforce social rules. Suppose there were no gov- ernment institutions—no laws, no police, and no courts. In this situation, each of us would be free to do as we pleased. Hobbes called this “the state of nature.” What would it be like? Hobbes thought it would be dreadful. In the state of nature, he says, there would be no place for industry, because the fruit thereof is uncertain: and consequently no culture of 82 rac38243_ch06_082-097.indd 82 10/24/11 10:19 PM Confirming Pages THE SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY 83 the earth; no navigation, nor use of the commodities that may be imported by sea; no commodious building; no instruments of moving, and removing, such things as require much force; no knowledge of the face of the earth; no account of time; no arts; no letters; no society; and which is worst of all, continual fear, and danger of violent death; and the life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short. The state of nature would be awful, Hobbes thought, due to four basic facts about human life: • There is equality of need. Each of us needs the same basic things in order to survive—food, clothing, shelter, and so on. Although we may differ in some of our needs (diabetics need insulin, others don’t), we are all essen- tially alike. • There is scarcity. We do not live in the Garden of Eden, where milk flows in streams and every tree hangs heavy with fruit. The world is a hard, inhospitable place, where the things we need do not come in abundance. We have to work hard to produce them, and even then they may be in short supply. • There is the essential equality of human power. Who will get the scarce goods? No one can simply take what she wants. Even though some people are smarter and tougher than others, even the strongest can be brought down when those who are less strong act together. • Finally, there is limited altruism. If we cannot prevail by our own strength, what hope do we have? Can we rely on the goodwill of others? We cannot. Even if people are not wholly selfish, they care most about themselves, and we cannot assume that they will step aside when their interests conflict with ours. Together, these facts paint a grim picture. We all need the same basic things, and there aren’t enough of them to go around. Therefore, we will have to compete for them. But no one can prevail in this competition, and no one—or almost no one—will look after the needs of his neighbors. The result, as Hobbes puts it, is a “constant state of war, of one with all.” And it is a war no one can win. Whoever wants to survive will try to seize what he needs and prepare to defend it from attack. rac38243_ch06_082-097.indd 83 10/24/11 10:19 PM Confirming Pages 84 THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY Meanwhile, others will be doing the same thing. Life in the state of nature would be intolerable. Hobbes did not think this was mere speculation. He pointed out that this is what actually happens when govern- ments collapse during civil uprisings. People hoard food, arm themselves, and lock out their neighbors. Moreover, nations themselves behave like this when international law is weak. Without a strong, overarching authority to maintain the peace, countries guard their borders, build up their armies, and feed their own people first. To escape the state of nature, we must find a way to work together. In a stable and cooperative society, we can produce more essential goods and distribute them in a rational way. But establishing such a society is not easy. People must agree on rules to govern their interactions. They must agree, for exam- ple, not to harm one another and not to break their promises. Hobbes calls such an agreement “the social contract.” As a soci- ety, we follow certain rules, and we have ways to enforce them. Some of those ways involve the law—if you assault someone, the police may arrest you. Other ways involve “the court of pub- lic opinion”—if you get a reputation for lying, then people may turn their backs on you. All of these rules, taken together, form the social contract. It is only within the context of the social contract that we can become beneficent beings, because the contract creates the conditions under which we can afford to care about oth- ers. In the state of nature, it is every man for himself; it would be foolish for anyone to look out for others and put his own interests in jeopardy. But in society, altruism becomes possible. By releasing us from “the continual fear of violent death,” the social contract frees us to take heed of others. Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) went so far as to say that we become different kinds of creatures when we enter civilized relations with others. In The Social Contract (1762), he writes: The passage from the state of nature to the civil state produces a very remarkable change in man. Then only, when the voice of duty takes the place of physi- cal impulses . does man, who so far had considered only himself, find that he is forced to act on different principles, and to consult his reason before listening to his inclinations. His faculties are so stimulated and rac38243_ch06_082-097.indd 84 10/24/11 10:19 PM Confirming Pages THE SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY 85 developed, . his feelings so ennobled, and his whole soul so uplifted, that, did not the abuses of this new condition often degrade him below that which he left, he would be bound to bless continually the happy moment which took him from it forever, and, instead of a stupid and unimagi- native animal, made him an intelligent being and a man.
Recommended publications
  • Moral Implications of Darwinian Evolution for Human Reference
    Andrews University Digital Commons @ Andrews University Dissertations Graduate Research 2006 Moral Implications of Darwinian Evolution for Human Reference Based in Christian Ethics: a Critical Analysis and Response to the "Moral Individualism" of James Rachels Stephen Bauer Andrews University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.andrews.edu/dissertations Part of the Christianity Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, Evolution Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Bauer, Stephen, "Moral Implications of Darwinian Evolution for Human Reference Based in Christian Ethics: a Critical Analysis and Response to the "Moral Individualism" of James Rachels" (2006). Dissertations. 16. https://digitalcommons.andrews.edu/dissertations/16 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Research at Digital Commons @ Andrews University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Andrews University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Thank you for your interest in the Andrews University Digital Library of Dissertations and Theses. Please honor the copyright of this document by not duplicating or distributing additional copies in any form without the author’s express written permission. Thanks for your cooperation. Andrews University Seventh-day Adventist Theological Seminary MORAL IMPLICATIONS OF DARWINIAN EVOLUTION FOR HUMAN PREFERENCE BASED IN CHRISTIAN ETHICS: A CRITICAL ANALYSIS AND RESPONSE TO THE “MORAL INDIVIDUALISM” OF JAMES RACHELS A Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy by Stephen Bauer November 2006 Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission. UMI Number: 3248152 Copyright 2006 by Bauer, Stephen All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Vegetarianism and Virtue: Does Consequentialism Demand Too Little?
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 1-2002 Vegetarianism and Virtue: Does Consequentialism Demand Too Little? Nathan Nobis University of Rochester Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/acwp_aafhh Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Other Anthropology Commons, and the Other Nutrition Commons Recommended Citation Nobis, N. (2002). Vegetarianism and Virtue: Does consequentialism Demand Too Little?. Social Theory & Practice, 28(1), 135-156. This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Vegetarianism and Virtue: Does Consequentialism Demand Too Little? Nathan Nobis Department of Philosophy, University of Rochester I will argue that each of us personally ought to be a vegetarian.1 Actually, the conclusion I will attempt to defend concerns more than one's eating habits in that I will argue that we should be "vegans." Not only should we not buy and eat meat, but we should also not purchase fur coats, stoles, and hats, or leather shoes, belts, jackets, purses and wallets, furniture, car interiors, and other traditionally animal-based products for which there are readily available plant-based or synthetic alternatives. (Usually these are cheaper and work just as well, or better, anyway.) I will argue that buying and eating most eggs and dairy products are immoral as well. (Since it's much easier
    [Show full text]
  • “Human Being” a Moral Concept?
    QQ version – Oct. 26, 2010 Is “Human Being” a Moral Concept? Douglas MacLean Is “human being” a moral concept? I believe it is, which makes me a speciesist. Speciesism violates a moral principle of equality. Peter Singer defines it as “a prejudice or attitude of bias toward the interests of members of one’s own species and against those of members of other species.” He compares it to racism. My goal in this essay is to defend a speciesist attitude or outlook on morality. This defense consists in little more than sympathetically describing certain intuitions and exploring some of their implications. I have no further argument to show that this view is true or correct; in fact, I don’t know what such an argument would look like. As I see it, each side in debates about speciesism reveals different assumptions or begs different questions about the foundation of ethics. Critics of speciesism see ethics as grounded in status-conferring individual properties that generate agent-neutral reasons. The outlook I will describe is based on a conviction that ethics is inextricably tied to practices that define what it is to live a human life. The most general reasons in this conception of morality are human reasons. They are norms for creatures like us, but not necessarily for gods, intelligent aliens, or other possible agents. They are not agent-neutral. By defending a speciesist outlook on morality I do not mean to suggest that animal suffering has no moral significance. A decent human life takes seriously things like cruelty, callousness, or indifference to the natural world.
    [Show full text]
  • Facts & Figures 2015-2016
    1 FACTS & FIGURES 2015-2016 Thirty-sixth Edition June 2016 Office of Institutional Effectiveness and Analysis UNIVERSITY OF ALABAMA AT BIRMINGHAM Birmingham, Alabama 35294-0104 (205) 934-2384 www.uab.edu/institutionaleffectiveness 2 FOREWORD The Office of Institutional Effectiveness and Analysis is pleased to present Facts & Figures 2015-2016. This is the 36th edition of the UAB factbook, the seventeenth edition available electronically on the web. Facts & Figures is compiled by the Office of Institutional Effectiveness and Analysis but reflects contributions from offices all over campus. We remain grateful for our contributors’ continued assistance. Facts & Figures can be easily accessed electronically via the Office of Institutional Effectiveness and Analysis web site (www.uab.edu/institutionaleffectiveness). Our objective with this factbook is to produce a useful and usable resource for a variety of information needs. Therefore, we welcome and appreciate your comments and suggestions to [email protected] about the content of Facts & Figures. 3 TABLE OF CONTENTS GENERAL INFORMATION UAB’s Strategic Plan ................................................................................................................................... 7 The Board of Trustees ................................................................................................................................ 8 Administration ............................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Relational Personhood Jonathan Herring*
    Keele Law Review, Volume 1 (2020), 24-41 24 ISSN 2732-5679 Relational Personhood Jonathan Herring* Abstract This article discusses the basis on which it is determined that something or someone has moral personhood. It rejects mainstream approaches which rely on intellectual attributes or membership of the human species as the markers of personhood. An approach based on intellectual abilities leads to a denial of the moral status of those with cognitive impairments. The emphasis on membership of the human species struggles to explain why such membership in itself generates moral status. Instead this article promotes the view that moral values is found in caring relationships. It argues that this better captures what we regard as morally valuable and reflects the true nature of what it is to be human. This approach is potentially very significant for lawyers because the law tends to promote the rights and well-being of individuals, considered in isolation. Instead we should be designing our legal system around the promotion of caring relationships. I. Introduction Debates over personhood raise some fundamental questions for lawyers. Is a fetus a person and so deserving of a right to life? Is it appropriate to switch off the life support machine of someone in a persistent vegetative state? What should be the legal status of people with profound mental impairments? These questions are of even greater significance than they originally imply because they go to the heart of what makes human living good and valuable. This article will start with a brief discussion of the nature of personhood.1 It will then set out the two most prominent schools of thought on what a person is and concludes that neither of these is satisfactory.
    [Show full text]
  • Care Ethics and Politcal Theory
    OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/6/2015, SPi Care Ethics and Political Theory OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/6/2015, SPi OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/6/2015, SPi Care Ethics and Political Theory Edited by Daniel Engster and Maurice Hamington 1 OUP CORRECTED PROOF – FINAL, 23/6/2015, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries # Oxford University Press 2015 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2015 Impression: 1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2015932776 ISBN 978–0–19–871634–1 Printed and bound by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Tom Regan, the Case for Animal Rights, in James Rachels (Ed.), The
    210 IMMANUEL KANT 11? CjtwV ” // !l THE CASE FOR ANIMAL RIGHTS 211 we have no direct duties. Animals are not self-conscious and are who use living animals for their experiments, certainly act cruelly, there merely as a means to an end. That end is man. We can ask, although their aim is praiseworthy, and they can justify their cruelty, “Why do animals exist?” But to ask, “Why does man exist?” is a since animals must be regarded as man’s instruments; but any such meaningless question. Our duties towards animals are merely indi­ cruelty for sport cannot be justified. ;Amaster who turns out his ass' rect duties towards humanity. Animal nature has analogies to or his dog because the animal can no longer earn its keep manifests? human nature, and by doing our duties to animals in respect of a small mindrjbe Greeks’ ideas in this respect were high-minded, manifestations which correspond to manifestations of human na- as can be seen from the fable of the ass and the bell of ingratitude. ! ture, we indirectly do our duty towards humanity. Thus, if a dog has (] ^ Our duties towards animals, then, are indirect duties towards man­ served his master long and faithfully, his service, on the analogy of ^ kind. £ human service, deserves reward, and when the dog has grown too old to serve, his master ought to keep him until he dies. Such action \ helps to support us imQur duties towards human beings, where they , Suggestions for Further Reading "“are bounden duties/lf then any acts of animals are analogous to \ / human acts and sprthg from the same principles, we have duties |/ See page 225.
    [Show full text]
  • ETHICS and INTUITIONS in One of His Many Fine Essays, Jim Rachels
    PETER SINGER ETHICS AND INTUITIONS (Received 25 January 2005; accepted 26 January 2005) ABSTRACT. For millennia, philosophers have speculated about the origins of ethics. Recent research in evolutionary psychology and the neurosciences has shed light on that question. But this research also has normative significance. A standard way of arguing against a normative ethical theory is to show that in some circum- stances the theory leads to judgments that are contrary to our common moral intuitions. If, however, these moral intuitions are the biological residue of our evo- lutionary history, it is not clear why we should regard them as having any normative force. Research in the neurosciences should therefore lead us to reconsider the role of intuitions in normative ethics. KEY WORDS: brain imaging, David Hume, ethics, evolutionary psychology, Henry Sidgwick, Immanuel Kant, intuitions, James Rachels, John Rawls, Jonathan Haidt, Joshua D. Greene, neuroscience, trolley problem, utilitarianism 1. INTRODUCTION In one of his many fine essays, Jim Rachels criticized philosophers who ‘‘shoot from the hip.’’ As he put it: The telephone rings, and a reporter rattles off a few ‘‘facts’’ about something somebody is supposed to have done. Ethical issues are involved – something alarming is said to have taken place – and so the ‘‘ethicist’’ is asked for a com- ment to be included in the next day’s story, which may be the first report the public will have seen about the events in question.1 In these circumstances, Rachels noted, the reporters want a short pithy quote, preferably one that says that the events described are bad. The philosopher makes a snap judgment, and the result is 1 James Rachels, ‘‘When Philosophers Shoot from the Hip,’’ in Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer (eds.), Bioethics: An Anthology (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1999), p.
    [Show full text]
  • Vegetarianism
    Vegetarianism 1. Animal Cruelty Industrial farming is abusive to animals. Pigs. In America, nine out of ten of pregnant sows live in “gestation crates.” These pens are so small that the pigs can hardly move. When the sows are first crated, they flail around, as if they’re trying to escape from the crate. But soon they give up. The pigs often show signs of depression: they engage in meaningless, repetitive behavior, like chewing the air or biting the bars of the stall. The animals live in these conditions for four months. Gestation crates will be phased out in Europe by the end of 2012, but they will still be used in America.1 In nature, pigs nurse their young for about thirteen weeks. But in industrial farms, piglets are taken from their mothers after a couple of weeks. Because the piglets are weaned prematurely, they have a strong desire to suck and chew. But the farmers don’t want them sucking and chewing on other pigs’ tails. So the farmers routinely snip off (or “dock”) the tails of all their pigs. They do this with a pair of pliers and no anesthetic. However, the whole tail is not removed; a tender stump remains. The point is to render the area sensitive, so the pigs being chewed on will fight back.2 Over 113 million pigs are slaughtered each year in America.3 Typically, these pigs are castrated, their needle teeth are clipped, and one of their ears is notched for identification —all without pain relief.4 In nature, pigs spend up to three quarters of their waking hours foraging and exploring their environment.5 But in the factory farms, “tens of thousands of hogs spend their entire lives ignorant of earth or straw or sunshine, crowded together beneath a metal roof standing on metal slats suspended over a septic tank.”6 Bored, and in constant pain, the pigs must perpetually inhale the fumes of their own waste.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Ethics Summer 2019 Instructor: Lauren Lyons Office Hours (Online): by Appointment Email: [email protected]
    Philosophy 107: Introduction to Ethics Summer 2019 Instructor: Lauren Lyons Office Hours (Online): By appointment Email: [email protected] Course Description and Learning Objectives Ethics is the study of what we ought to do and how we ought to live. This course invites students to ponder these central questions by offering an introduction to normative theory and applied ethics. The course begins with a broad overview to ethics as a discipline and to philosophical writing and methodology. Then, we will study and analyze some central theories normative ethics– ways of approaching questions of what we ought to do, and how we ought to live. We will examine utilitarianism, deontology, and virtue ethics. Following, using that theoretical background, we will grapple with a series of contemporary moral issues, including abortion; the ethics of eating animals; the death penalty; poverty and altruism; gender and oppression; and racial inequality and racial justice. The course has three objectives: 1. To introduce students to the essential tools of philosophical methodology and writing, including reconstructing and evaluating arguments, clearly articulating philosophical ideas, and engaging in respectful and constructive philosophical debates. 2. To familiarize students with the domain of moral philosophy, including central theories, concepts, figures, and questions, enabling them also to consider how conversations in the history of moral philosophy bear on present social moral and social issues. 3. (And, most importantly) To spark curiosity about (what I take to be!) exciting normative questions and enable students to think critically about their responses to them, and about moral issues in the world more broadly. Course Structure We will have two course sessions each week, each of which will be accompanied by an online video lecture on the topic.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal-Industrial Complex‟ – a Concept & Method for Critical Animal Studies? Richard Twine
    ISSN: 1948-352X Volume 10 Issue 1 2012 Journal for Critical Animal Studies ISSN: 1948-352X Volume 10 Issue 1 2012 EDITORAL BOARD Dr. Richard J White Chief Editor [email protected] Dr. Nicole Pallotta Associate Editor [email protected] Dr. Lindgren Johnson Associate Editor [email protected] ___________________________________________________________________________ Laura Shields Associate Editor [email protected] Dr. Susan Thomas Associate Editor [email protected] ___________________________________________________________________________ Dr. Richard Twine Book Review Editor [email protected] Vasile Stanescu Book Review Editor [email protected] ___________________________________________________________________________ Carol Glasser Film Review Editor [email protected] ___________________________________________________________________________ Adam Weitzenfeld Film Review Editor [email protected] ___________________________________________________________________________ Dr. Matthew Cole Web Manager [email protected] ___________________________________________________________________________ EDITORIAL ADVISORY BOARD For a complete list of the members of the Editorial Advisory Board please see the Journal for Critical Animal Studies website: http://journal.hamline.edu/index.php/jcas/index 1 Journal for Critical Animal Studies, Volume 10, Issue 1, 2012 (ISSN1948-352X) JCAS Volume 10, Issue 1, 2012 EDITORAL BOARD ..............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Questions of Priority and Interspecies Comparisons of Happiness *
    Questions of Priority and Interspecies Comparisons of Happiness * Oscar Horta 1. QUESTIONS OF PRIORITY It is commonly believed that issues of priority arise when we have to choose between improving a certain situation for humans and improving the situation for nonhuman animals (hereafter, ‘nonhumans’). It is virtually universally assumed that humans’ interests are far more important, and thus have priority over, nonhumans’. As a result, in situations where we must choose between benefiting humans and benefiting nonhumans, we almost never choose the latter. Moreover, nonhumans are systematically harmed to benefit humans. This paper intends to examine the assumptions on which this idea is based. Now, there are two ways in which holding that the satisfaction of human interests over those of nonhumans can be defended. First, it is sometimes claimed that humans’ interests count for more simply because they are humans’, no matter how trivial or significant they are. This idea renders unnecessary the weighting of human interests against nonhuman interests. I assess this question in section 2. Second, one might hold that even if humans do not have a higher moral status, their interests nonetheless count more because they lose more than nonhuman animals if their interests are not satisfied, and gain more than nonhuman animals if their interests are satisfied. To examine whether this is so, we must compare the interests which humans and nonhumans have. In order to do this, we need to determine the units or currency in which such comparison can be made. Sections 3 and 4 consider this problem. Once these problems are assessed, we can consider the empirical facts concerning the comparative situation in which humans and nonhumans are.
    [Show full text]