A Defense of Pure Connectionism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Defense of Pure Connectionism City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 2-2019 A Defense of Pure Connectionism Alex B. Kiefer The Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/3036 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] A DEFENSE OF PURE CONNECTIONISM by ALEXANDER B. KIEFER A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2019 © 2019 ALEXANDER B. KIEFER All Rights Reserved ii A Defense of Pure Connectionism By Alexander B. Kiefer This manuscript has been read and accepted by the Graduate Faculty in Philosophy in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. _________________________ _________________________________________ 1/22/2019 Eric Mandelbaum Chair of Examining Committee _________________________ _________________________________________ 1/22/2019 Nickolas Pappas Executive Officer Supervisory Committee: David Rosenthal Jakob Hohwy Eric Mandelbaum THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii ABSTRACT A Defense of Pure Connectionism by Alexander B. Kiefer Advisor: David M. Rosenthal Connectionism is an approach to neural-networks-based cognitive modeling that encompasses the recent deep learning movement in artificial intelligence. It came of age in the 1980s, with its roots in cybernetics and earlier attempts to model the brain as a system of simple parallel processors. Connectionist models center on statistical inference within neural networks with empirically learnable parameters, which can be represented as graphical models. More recent approaches focus on learning and inference within hierarchical generative models. Contra influential and ongoing critiques, I argue in this dissertation that the connectionist approach to cognitive science possesses in principle (and, as is becoming increasingly clear, in practice) the resources to model even the most rich and distinctly human cognitive capacities, such as abstract, conceptual thought and natural language comprehension and production. Consonant with much previous philosophical work on connectionism, I argue that a core principle—that proximal representations in a vector space have similar semantic values—is the key to a successful connectionist account of the systematicity and productivity of thought, language, and other core cognitive phenomena. My work here differs from preceding work in philosophy in several respects: (1) I compare a wide variety of connectionist responses to the systematicity challenge and isolate two main strands that are both historically important and reflected in ongoing work today: (a) vector symbolic architectures and (b) (compositional) vector space semantic models; (2) I consider very recent applications of these approaches, including iv their deployment on large-scale machine learning tasks such as machine translation; (3) I argue, again on the basis mostly of recent developments, for a continuity in representation and processing across natural language, image processing and other domains; (4) I explicitly link broad, abstract features of connectionist representation to recent proposals in cognitive science similar in spirit, such as hierarchical Bayesian and free energy minimization approaches, and offer a single rebuttal of criticisms of these related paradigms; (5) I critique recent alternative proposals that argue for a hybrid Classical (i.e. serial symbolic)/statistical model of mind; (6) I argue that defending the most plausible form of a connectionist cognitive architecture requires rethinking certain distinctions that have figured prominently in the history of the philosophy of mind and language, such as that between word-, phrase-, and sentence-level semantic content, and between inference and association. v Acknowledgements This dissertation is dedicated to my daughter Evelyn Stelmak Kiefer, who was born just before it was. I’m not sure what she would need it for, but it’s hers. Thanks to my partner Natallia Stelmak Schabner for her patience, love and inspiration during the writing of this work, and to her daughter Sophia. I am deeply grateful to my family (all of you, truly—I won’t name names here in case there’s some cousin I forgot about) for the same, and for believing in my potential since probably before I was born in many cases. The list of friends that I have to thank for accompanying me through life and sustaining my very existence is long, but I wish to thank here those who have specifically encouraged and inspired my work in philosophy over the years: Andrew, Ian, Rose, Rachel, Richard, Hakwan, and Pete. I am also grateful to the chiptune crew and other friends in music and the arts (particularly Jeff, Kira, Haeyoung, Jamie, Chris, Tamara, Josh, Dok, Amy, Pietro, and Jeremy) for being the truest of friends and for informing my work in oblique but essential ways. If I’ve forgotten anyone, get in touch and I’ll put you in the dedication when I write a book. Thanks to my advisor David Rosenthal and the members of my dissertation committee, Jakob Hohwy, Eric Mandelbaum, Richard Brown, and Gary Ostertag, for helpful feedback on drafts of this work. I’d additionally like to thank my advisor for introducing me to cognitive science, for expert and dedicated guidance over the years, for serving as an exemplar and inspiration, and for his patience in helping me work through many iterations of these ideas (and many others). I would like to thank Jakob Hohwy for taking an early interest in my work, for encouraging me to develop its most promising aspects, and for generously sharing his insight and enthusiasm. Thanks to Richard Brown and Gary Ostertag for their support over the years, and for being involved with this project since the prospectus days. And additional thanks to Eric Mandelbaum for posing the stiffest challenges to my work in the sincere hope of improving it. vi I am also grateful to teachers, friends and fellow graduate students, including Pete Mandik, Josh Weisberg, Kenneth Williford, Hakwan Lau, Graham Priest, Janet Fodor, David Pereplyotchik, Jake Quilty-Dunn, Zoe Jenkin, Grace Helton, Jona Vance, Ryan DeChant, Jesse Atencio, Kate Pendoley, Jacob Berger, Henry Shevlin, Kate Storrs, Eric Leonardis, Hudson Cooper, and the cognitive science group at the CUNY Graduate Center, for indispensable exchanges that have informed my thinking. Thanks also to Geoffrey Hinton for kindly replying to my two brash and overly familiar emails. It was more inspiring than you know. And not least to Jerry Fodor, for his love of the philosophy of mind and for goading the connectionists on back when their success seemed less than certain. vii A Defense of Pure Connectionism - Contents Chapter 1: Preliminaries on Connectionism and Systematicity Introduction………………………………………………………………………………………1 1.1 Systematicity, productivity and compositionality……………………………………….. 10 1.2 Fodor and Pylyshyn’s challenge to connectionism…………………………………….. 14 1.3 Systematicity and vector spaces………………………………………………………… 19 Chapter 2: Vector Symbolic Architectures 2.1 Smolensky architectures………………………………………………………………….. 26 2.2 Smolensky’s take on Smolensky architectures………………………………………… 32 2.3 Fodor’s take on Smolensky architectures………………………………………………. 36 2.4 McLaughlin’s take on Smolensky architectures……………………………………….. 42 2.5 Holographic Reduced Representations…………………………………………………. 48 2.6 Processing in Vector Symbolic Architectures………………………………………….. 52 2.7 Compositional VS combinatorial systems………………………………………………. 56 2.8 Inferential systematicity…………………………………………………………………… 62 2.9 Some problems for VSAs……………………………………………………………….... 67 Chapter 3: Neural Vector Space Models 3.1 Distributional semantics………………………………………………………………….. 76 3.2 Vector space models in semantics………………………………………………………. 81 3.3 Neural language models and vector space embeddings……………………………… 85 3.4 GloVe vectors……………………………………………………………………………….92 viii 3.5 Collobert et al’s model: syntax from distribution………………………………………. 97 3.6 Compositionality in vector space semantic models…………………………………….104 Chapter 4: Parsing in Connectionist Networks 4.1 The RAAM system and autoencoders………………………………………………….. 110 4.2 Discovering parse trees……………………………………………………………………117 4.3 More powerful tree-shaped models……………………………………………………… 122 4.4 Applying computer vision techniques to language…………………………………….. 129 4.5 Hinton’s critique of CNNs…………………………………………………………………. 134 4.6 The capsules approach…………………………………………………………………… 139 Chapter 5: Concepts and Translation 5.1 Concepts and propositions……………………………………………………………….. 148 5.2 Words as regions, concepts as operators………………………………………………. 155 5.3 The prototype theory of concepts revisited…………………………………………….. 162 5.4 Machine translation and the language of thought……………………………………... 168 5.5 Multimodal connectionist nets……………………………………………………………. 175 5.6 Larger-scale multimodal models…………………………………………………………. 182 Chapter 6: Reasoning 6.1 Inference, association and vector spaces……………………………………………… 189 6.2 Induction and semantic entailment………………………………………………………. 197 6.3 Inductive reasoning in connectionist systems………………………………………….. 204 6.4 Deductive reasoning in connectionist systems………………………………………… 211 6.5 The PLoT
Recommended publications
  • Warren Mcculloch and the British Cyberneticians
    Warren McCulloch and the British cyberneticians Article (Accepted Version) Husbands, Phil and Holland, Owen (2012) Warren McCulloch and the British cyberneticians. Interdisciplinary Science Reviews, 37 (3). pp. 237-253. ISSN 0308-0188 This version is available from Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/43089/ This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies and may differ from the published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to consult the publisher’s version. Please see the URL above for details on accessing the published version. Copyright and reuse: Sussex Research Online is a digital repository of the research output of the University. Copyright and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable, the material made available in SRO has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full text items generally can be reproduced, displayed or performed and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk Warren McCulloch and the British Cyberneticians1 Phil Husbands and Owen Holland Dept. Informatics, University of Sussex Abstract Warren McCulloch was a significant influence on a number of British cyberneticians, as some British pioneers in this area were on him.
    [Show full text]
  • Kybernetik in Urbana
    Kybernetik in Urbana Ein Gespräch zwischen Paul Weston, Jan Müggenburg und James Andrew Hutchinson1 Paul Ernest Weston was born on February 3rd 1935 in Garland, Maine. After stu- dying physics at Wesleyan University in Middletown (Connecticut), 1952 through 1956, Paul Weston came to the University of Illinois in summer 1956, receiving his M.S. in August 1958. The following autumn, as a graduate student of physics, he attended a seminar led by Heinz von Foerster under the promising title „Cyberne- tics“.2 In June 1959 Paul joins the newly founded Biological Computer Laboratory (BCL) as a half time research assistant employed by the Electrical Engineering Department. Through roughly 1962, Weston’s primary emphasis was upon simulation of the processes of perception, with work in neuron models and pattern recognition. Together with Murray Babcock, Weston was one of the most prominent creators of prototypes built at the BCL. Already in 1961 Weston becomes widely known as the inventor of the NumaRete, a parallel operated pattern recognition machine, which played an important role in the public perception of the BCL through out the fol- lowing years.3 After 1964 Weston continues his research at BCL on the basis of a full position as a research assistant and starts to focus on information processing, particularly inte- rested in problems associated with natural-language interaction with machine. As a member of the Committee for Cognitive Studies Weston is also increasingly interes- ted in the potentials of how the new information technologies could shape society. In June 1970 Weston receives his PhD for developing a new and more efficient data structure called CYLINDER.4 After the BCL was closed in 1975 Weston continued to work as a Research Associate at the Department of Electrical Engineering and the Coordinated Science Laboratory of the University of Illinois.
    [Show full text]
  • 1011 Neurons } 1014 Synapses the Cybernetics Group
    History 329/SI 311/RCSSCI 360 Computers and the Internet: A global history Week 6: Computing and Cybernetics in the Soviet Union Today } Review } Cybernetics: minds, brains, and machines } Soviet computing and cybernetics } Soviet economic planning } Next time Review: SAGE } Origin: Whirlwind digital computer project, MIT } SAGE = Semi-Automatic Ground Environment } Computer-controlled air defense of lower 48 states } Networked over telephone lines } Duplexed (two computers for high reliability) } Tube-based central processors made by IBM } Magnetic core memory } First truly large software development } Served as a pattern for many subsequent military projects } Major factor in US and IBM dominance of commercial computer markets by late1950s Cybernetics: minds, brains, and machines Key figures } Norbert Wiener } cybernetics } Warren McCulloch & Walter Pitts } neural nets } John von Neumann } brain modeling, cellular automata, biological metaphors } Frank Rosenblatt } perceptrons The Cybernetics Group } Norbert Wiener, MIT } WWII anti-aircraft problems } Servo/organism analogies } “Behavior, Purpose, and Teleology” (1943) } Information as measurable quantity } Feedback: circular self-corrective cycles BEHAVIOR, PURPOSE AND TELEOLOGY 21 Examples of predictions of higher order are shooting with a sling or with a bow and arrow. Predictive behavior requires the discrimination of at least two coordinates, a temporal and at least one spatial axis. Prediction will be more effective and flexible, however, if the behaving object can respond to changes in more than one spatial coordinate. The sensory receptors of an organism, or the corresponding elements of a machine, may therefore limit the predictive behavior. Thus, a bloodhound follows a trail, that is, it does not show any predictive behavior in trailing, because a chemical, olfactory input reports only spatial information: distance, as indicated by intensity.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Sociocybernetics
    JOURNAL OF SOCIOCYBERNETICS _________________________________________________________________ Volume 3 Number 1 Spring/Summer 2002 Official Journal of the Research Committee on Sociocybernetics (RC51) of the International Sociological Association JOURNAL OF SOCIOCYBERNETICS www.unizar.es/sociocybernetics/ Editor Richard E. Lee Newsletter Cor Van Dijkum Felix Geyer Editorial Board Mike Byron Tessaleno Devezas Jorge González Bernd R. Hornung Chaime Marcuello Vessela Misheva Philip Nikolopoulos Bernard Scott Mike Terpstra ____________________________________________________________________________ The JOURNAL OF SOCIOCYBERNETICS (ISSN 1607-8667) is an electronic journal published biannually--Spring/Summer and Fall/Winter--by the Research Committee on Sociocybernetics of the International Sociological Association. MANUSCRIPT submissions should be sent electronically (in MSWord or Rich Text File format) to each of the editors: Richard E. Lee [email protected], Felix Geyer, [email protected], and Cor van Dijkum, [email protected]. In general, please follow the Chicago Manuel of Style; citations and bibliography should follow the current journal style (APA). Normally, articles should be original texts of no more than 6000 words, although longer articles will be considered in exceptional circumstances. The Journal looks for submissions that are innovative and apply principles of General Systems Theory and Cybernetics to the social sciences, broadly conceived. COPYRIGHT remains the property of authors. Permission to reprint must be obtained from the authors and the contents of JoS cannot be copied for commercial purposes. JoS does, however, reserve the right to future reproduction of articles in hard copy, portable document format (.pdf), or HTML editions of JoS. iii SOCIOCYBERNETICS traces its intellectual roots to the rise of a panoply of new approaches to scientific inquiry beginning in the 1940's.
    [Show full text]
  • Intelligence Without Representation: a Historical Perspective
    systems Commentary Intelligence without Representation: A Historical Perspective Anna Jordanous School of Computing, University of Kent, Chatham Maritime, Kent ME4 4AG, UK; [email protected] Received: 30 June 2020; Accepted: 10 September 2020; Published: 15 September 2020 Abstract: This paper reflects on a seminal work in the history of AI and representation: Rodney Brooks’ 1991 paper Intelligence without representation. Brooks advocated the removal of explicit representations and engineered environments from the domain of his robotic intelligence experimentation, in favour of an evolutionary-inspired approach using layers of reactive behaviour that operated independently of each other. Brooks criticised the current progress in AI research and believed that removing complex representation from AI would help address problematic areas in modelling the mind. His belief was that we should develop artificial intelligence by being guided by the evolutionary development of our own intelligence and that his approach mirrored how our own intelligence functions. Thus, the field of behaviour-based robotics emerged. This paper offers a historical analysis of Brooks’ behaviour-based robotics approach and its impact on artificial intelligence and cognitive theory at the time, as well as on modern-day approaches to AI. Keywords: behaviour-based robotics; representation; adaptive behaviour; evolutionary robotics 1. Introduction In 1991, Rodney Brooks published the paper Intelligence without representation, a seminal work on behaviour-based robotics [1]. This paper influenced many aspects of research into artificial intelligence and cognitive theory. In Intelligence without representation, Brooks described his behaviour-based robotics approach to artificial intelligence. He highlighted a number of points that he considers fundamental in modelling intelligence.
    [Show full text]
  • THE INTELLECTUAL ORIGINS of the Mcculloch
    JHBS—WILEY RIGHT BATCH Top of ID Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 38(1), 3–25 Winter 2002 ᭧ 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. (PHYSIO)LOGICAL CIRCUITS: THE INTELLECTUAL ORIGINS OF THE Base of 1st McCULLOCH–PITTS NEURAL NETWORKS line of ART TARA H. ABRAHAM This article examines the intellectual and institutional factors that contributed to the col- laboration of neuropsychiatrist Warren McCulloch and mathematician Walter Pitts on the logic of neural networks, which culminated in their 1943 publication, “A Logical Calculus of the Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity.” Historians and scientists alike often refer to the McCulloch–Pitts paper as a landmark event in the history of cybernetics, and funda- mental to the development of cognitive science and artificial intelligence. This article seeks to bring some historical context to the McCulloch–Pitts collaboration itself, namely, their intellectual and scientific orientations and backgrounds, the key concepts that contributed to their paper, and the institutional context in which their collaboration was made. Al- though they were almost a generation apart and had dissimilar scientific backgrounds, McCulloch and Pitts had similar intellectual concerns, simultaneously motivated by issues in philosophy, neurology, and mathematics. This article demonstrates how these issues converged and found resonance in their model of neural networks. By examining the intellectual backgrounds of McCulloch and Pitts as individuals, it will be shown that besides being an important event in the history of cybernetics proper, the McCulloch– Pitts collaboration was an important result of early twentieth-century efforts to apply mathematics to neurological phenomena. ᭧ 2002 John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Systems Theory?
    What is Systems Theory? Systems theory is an interdisciplinary theory about the nature of complex systems in nature, society, and science, and is a framework by which one can investigate and/or describe any group of objects that work together to produce some result. This could be a single organism, any organization or society, or any electro-mechanical or informational artifact. As a technical and general academic area of study it predominantly refers to the science of systems that resulted from Bertalanffy's General System Theory (GST), among others, in initiating what became a project of systems research and practice. Systems theoretical approaches were later appropriated in other fields, such as in the structural functionalist sociology of Talcott Parsons and Niklas Luhmann . Contents - 1 Overview - 2 History - 3 Developments in system theories - 3.1 General systems research and systems inquiry - 3.2 Cybernetics - 3.3 Complex adaptive systems - 4 Applications of system theories - 4.1 Living systems theory - 4.2 Organizational theory - 4.3 Software and computing - 4.4 Sociology and Sociocybernetics - 4.5 System dynamics - 4.6 Systems engineering - 4.7 Systems psychology - 5 See also - 6 References - 7 Further reading - 8 External links - 9 Organisations // Overview 1 / 20 What is Systems Theory? Margaret Mead was an influential figure in systems theory. Contemporary ideas from systems theory have grown with diversified areas, exemplified by the work of Béla H. Bánáthy, ecological systems with Howard T. Odum, Eugene Odum and Fritj of Capra , organizational theory and management with individuals such as Peter Senge , interdisciplinary study with areas like Human Resource Development from the work of Richard A.
    [Show full text]
  • Analysis of Artificial Intelligence Hypothesis from the Perspective of Philosophy
    2019 4th International Social Sciences and Education Conference (ISSEC 2019) Analysis of Artificial Intelligence Hypothesis from the Perspective of Philosophy Zhang Yanan Yinchuan University of Energy, Yinchuan, 750000, China Keywords: Artificial intelligence; Philosophy of artificial intelligence; Formal; Intentionality Abstract: Artificial intelligence is closely related to philosophy, algorithms in artificial intelligence are closely related to logic, intentionality of intelligent machines is closely related to philosophy of mind and so on. However, the beginners of the development of artificial intelligence are concerned about technical problems, and are weak in philosophical thinking. With the development of artificial intelligence, it is necessary to think deeply about its philosophical problems to clarify its philosophical basis and clear away the technical obstacles of the development of artificial intelligence, so as to be conducive to the development of artificial intelligence technology and promote the progress of philosophical research. 1. Introduction In 1950 Alan Turing opened his classic book Computing Machinery and Intelligence by asking: can machines think? But he did not think such questions were worth discussing, for it was difficult to define thinking precisely, so Turing proposed his imitation game, the Turing test[1]. At the heart of the Turing test is whether a computer can behave in a way indistinguishable from a human, the first time that humans have thought behavioristically about the intelligence of a robot. John McCarthy in 19556 for the first time to use “AI (Artificial Intelligence, or AI, for short)” concept, he thought that Human Intelligence, Human Intelligence) as Artificial Intelligence concept to determine the premise, the ultimate goal is to make the computer program control simulating Human ability to solve problems of Artificial Intelligence, was born a to study how to use the machine to simulate the emerging discipline of Human Intelligence.
    [Show full text]
  • Connectionist Models of Cognition Michael S. C. Thomas and James L
    Connectionist models of cognition Michael S. C. Thomas and James L. McClelland 1 1. Introduction In this chapter, we review computer models of cognition that have focused on the use of neural networks. These architectures were inspired by research into how computation works in the brain and subsequent work has produced models of cognition with a distinctive flavor. Processing is characterized by patterns of activation across simple processing units connected together into complex networks. Knowledge is stored in the strength of the connections between units. It is for this reason that this approach to understanding cognition has gained the name of connectionism. 2. Background Over the last twenty years, connectionist modeling has formed an influential approach to the computational study of cognition. It is distinguished by its appeal to principles of neural computation to inspire the primitives that are included in its cognitive level models. Also known as artificial neural network (ANN) or parallel distributed processing (PDP) models, connectionism has been applied to a diverse range of cognitive abilities, including models of memory, attention, perception, action, language, concept formation, and reasoning (see, e.g., Houghton, 2005). While many of these models seek to capture adult function, connectionism places an emphasis on learning internal representations. This has led to an increasing focus on developmental phenomena and the origins of knowledge. Although, at its heart, connectionism comprises a set of computational formalisms,
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1 Chapter 2
    Notes Chapter 1 1. These are my translations of Pascal’s self-produced pamphlet, the original of which can be seen here: http://history-computer. com/Library/PascalLettreToChancelier.pdf with a transcrip- tion here: http://www.fourmilab.ch/babbage/pascal.html Chapter 2 1. Of course, this glosses over some important metaphysical questions that have only recently arisen in conjunction with computer science; what is it to talk of ‘identity’ when concerning the entities – programs, files, folders, sub-routines etc. – of computer science? In what sense is a later revision of ‘mybook.doc’ the same file as an earlier draft? For some discussion of these deep issues, see Smith (1996). 2. See http://aturingmachine.com/ for this particular device; the video footage there is breathtaking. See also http://legoofdoom. blogspot.com/ for examples of what one can do with this sort of machine. 3. Randall Munroe’s excellent webcomic “xkcd” even has a graphical map of optimal moves for playing the perfect exhaustive game: http:// xkcd.com/832/ 4. Hodges (2008) suggests that this reference to “mistakes” gives Turing a way out of the kinds of Gödel-style objections that we will consider in the next chapter. Indeed, it does; see page 70. 5. For substantial, but accessible, detail on the former, see Campbell et al. (2002), for material on both aspects written by an IBM insider, see Hsu (2002). 6. IBM Deep Blue FAQs: http://www.research.ibm.com/deepblue/ meet/html/d.3.3a.html#ai 7. Ibid. 8. There are many online versions that one can play around with.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructions, Chunking, and Connectionism: the Emergence Of
    Constructions, chunking, and connectionism p. 1 Constructions, chunking, and connectionism: The emergence of second language structure Nick C. Ellis University of Wales, Bangor [email protected] Revised chapter for Doughty & Long (Eds.) Handbook of Second Language Acquisition. Oxford: Blackwell. 11 April, 2001 Acknowledgment: Thanks to the Chester Language Development Group for feedback on a draft of this chapter and for pointing me at the right stuff in the first place. Constructions, chunking, and connectionism p. 2 0. Introduction and Overview Constructivist views of language acquisition hold that simple learning mechanisms operating in and across the human systems for perception, motor-action and cognition as they are exposed to language data as part of a communicatively-rich human social environment by an organism eager to exploit the functionality of language is enough to drive the emergence of complex language representations. The various tribes of constructivism, connectionists (Christiansen & Chater , 2001; Christiansen, Chater & Seidenberg, 1999; McClelland & Rumelhart, 1986; Levy, Bairaktaris, Bullinaria & Cairns, 1995; Plunkett, 1998), functional linguists (Bates & MacWhinney, 1981; MacWhinney & Bates, 1989), emergentists (Elman et al., 1996; MacWhinney 1999a), cognitive linguists (Croft & Cruse, 1999; Lakoff, 1987; Langacker 1987, 1991; Ungerer & Schmid, 1996), constructivist child language researchers (Slobin, 1997; Tomasello, 1992; 1995; 1998a, 2000), applied linguists influenced by chaos/ complexity theory (Larsen-Freeman, 1997), and computational linguists who explore statistical approaches to grammar (Bod, 1998; Jurafsky, 1996), all share a functional- developmental usage-based perspective on language. They emphasize the linguistic sign as a set of mappings between phonological forms and conceptual meanings or communicative intentions; thus their theories of language function, acquisition and neurobiology attempt to unite speakers, syntax and semantics, the signifiers and the signifieds.
    [Show full text]
  • Robots, Cyborgs and Humans: a Futuristic Model of Consumer Behavior in Services
    ROBOTS, CYBORGS AND HUMANS: A FUTURISTIC MODEL OF CONSUMER BEHAVIOR IN SERVICES. AN INTERNATIONAL STUDY IN MEDICAL SERVICES SECTOR Ala' Ali Mohammad Almahameed ADVERTIMENT. L'accés als continguts d'aquesta tesi doctoral i la seva utilització ha de respectar els drets de la persona autora. Pot ser utilitzada per a consulta o estudi personal, així com en activitats o materials d'investigació i docència en els termes establerts a l'art. 32 del Text Refós de la Llei de Propietat Intel·lectual (RDL 1/1996). Per altres utilitzacions es requereix l'autorització prèvia i expressa de la persona autora. En qualsevol cas, en la utilització dels seus continguts caldrà indicar de forma clara el nom i cognoms de la persona autora i el títol de la tesi doctoral. No s'autoritza la seva reproducció o altres formes d'explotació efectuades amb finalitats de lucre ni la seva comunicació pública des d'un lloc aliè al servei TDX. Tampoc s'autoritza la presentació del seu contingut en una finestra o marc aliè a TDX (framing). Aquesta reserva de drets afecta tant als continguts de la tesi com als seus resums i índexs. ADVERTENCIA. El acceso a los contenidos de esta tesis doctoral y su utilización debe respetar los derechos de la persona autora. Puede ser utilizada para consulta o estudio personal, así como en actividades o materiales de investigación y docencia en los términos establecidos en el art. 32 del Texto Refundido de la Ley de Propiedad Intelectual (RDL 1/1996). Para otros usos se requiere la autorización previa y expresa de la persona autora.
    [Show full text]