Intentionality and Perception a Study of John Searle’S Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Intentionality and Perception a Study of John Searle’S Philosophy Intentionality and Perception A Study of John Searle’s Philosophy Inauguraldissertation Zur Erlangung der Doktorwürde der Philosophischen Fakultät der Ruprecht-Karls-Universität Heidelberg vorgelegt von: Anar Jafarov Erstgutachter: Prof. Dr. Andreas Kemmerling Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Peter McLaughlin Datum: 05. 02. 2019 TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS………………………………………………………… v ABBREVIATIONS……………………………………………………………….... vi INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER I / General Remarks on Searle’s Notion of Intentionality 5 1. Mind and intentionality……………………………………………………….... 6 2. Intentionality as directedness ………………………………………………...... 9 3. Intrinsic, derived, and as if intentionality……………………………………..... 13 3.1. Dennett’s criticism……………………………………………………….... 14 4. Conclusion……………………………………………………………………… 19 CHAPTER II / The Fundamentals of Searle’s Theory of Intentionality 20 1. Intentionality as representation………………………………………………..... 20 2. Logical analysis and logical properties ………………....………………........... 23 3. Psychological mode and direction of fit ………………………....…………...... 27 3.1 The problems with the notion of direction of fit …………………………... 29 3.2 Back to the relationship between psychological mode and direction of fit ... 32 4. Conditions of Satisfaction and Intentional Content ………………...……….... 34 4.1 Conditions of satisfaction ……………………………………………….... 34 4.2 On the relationship between intentional content and conditions of satisfaction …………………………………………...... 40 5. Conclusion …………………………………………………………………….. 50 CHAPTER III / The Hypothesis of the Background 51 1. Motivations for the idea of the Background ……………..……………...…...... 52 1.1. Motivation from the literal meaning …………………………………….... 52 1.2. Motivation from the notion of Network ………………………………...... 57 1.3. Motivation from the regress argument and from the consideration of physical skills ……………………………. 61 2. Non-representationality of the Background …………………………………… 62 ii 3. The Background as a mental feature ………………………………………….. 63 4. Conclusion …………………………………………………………………….. 67 CHAPTER IV / Arguments for the Intentionality of Perceptual Experiences 69 1. Argument from Basic Features ……………………………………………….. 70 1.1. Intentional content ……………………………………………………….. 70 1.2. Direction of fit …………………………………………………………... 70 1.3. Causal self-referentiality (reflexivity) …………………………………… 71 2. Argument from Transparency ………………………………………………… 72 3. Conditions of satisfaction: The continuation of Argument from Basic Features …………………….…………………….………………... 72 3.1. Dretske’s criticism ………………………………………………………. 74 3.2. Expounding the central theses ………………………………………….... 77 4. Arguments for the propositionality of the content of a visual experience ….... 80 4.1. The first argument ……………………………………………………….. 80 4.2. The syntactical argument ………………………………………………... 83 5. Conclusion ……………………………………………………………………. 85 CHAPTER V / Special Features of Perceptual Intentionality 86 1. Consciousness ………………………………………………………………… 86 2. Direct causation experienced …………………………………………………. 90 3. Presentationality ………………………………………………………………. 92 3.1. Non-detachability and indexicality ……………………………………… 93 3.2. Continuousness and determinacy ………………………………………. 94 4. Hierarchical structuredness …………………………………………………... 95 5. Conclusion ………………………………………………………………….... 96 CHAPTER VI / The Central Thesis of the Theory of Perception Reconsidered 97 1. Searle’s new method ….………………………………………………………. 97 2. Answering the question of how phenomenological features of visual experiences determine conditions of satisfaction ……………………. 102 3. Conditions of satisfaction determined by the phenomenological features of a visual experience ...……………………………………………………….. 103 4. Conclusion …………………………………………………………………….. 106 iii CHAPTER VII / The Background of Visual Experiences 107 1. The examples from INT ……………………………………………………… 107 2. The examples from STT ……………………………………………………… 112 3. Conclusion ……………………………………………………………………. 114 CHAPTER VIII / Naïve Realism 116 1. General features of Searle’s Naïve Realism ...………………………………... 117 2. “The Bad Argument” …………………………………………………………. 119 2.1. On Step Three of the Argument …………………………………………. 121 3. Searle’s objection to the Argument from Illusion …….………………………. 124 4. The classical theories ……………………………………………………....…. 126 4.1. Berkeley …………………………………………………………………. 128 4.2. Ayer ……………………………………………………………………… 129 5. Disjunctivism ………………………………………………………………..... 130 5.1. Stipulation vs. Hypothesis ……………………………………………….. 131 5.2. The central claim of Disjunctivism ……………………………………… 133 5.3. The commonality thesis as a threat to Naïve Realism? ………………….. 136 5.4. Searle’s criticism of Campbell .…………………………………………... 137 6. “The Bad Argument” and intentionality …………………………………….... 139 7. Conclusion ………………………………………………………...…...……... 140 CONCLUSION 142 REFERENCES 147 iv ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Many thanks to Andreas Kemmerling for his helpful comments and to those who participated in his Monday colloquiums which took place at Heidelberg University. I have benefited greatly from discussing this material with them. I also want to thank Thomas Fuchs and Christian Tewes. A portion of this dissertation was discussed in a colloquium organised by them. Special thanks to Peter McLaughlin for the consent he gave to assess my dissertation. In addition, my thanks are due to my family members. I am very grateful for the unconditional love and care which they provided me with in writing this dissertation. v ABBREVIATIONS The following abbreviations of the names of Searle's works are employed throughout. INT Intentionality: an Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, New York: Cambridge, Cambridge University Press 1983. RM The Rediscovery of the Mind, Cambridge: The MIT Press 1992. STT Seeing Things as They Are: A Theory of Perception, Oxford: Oxford University Press 2015. vi INTRODUCTION In this PhD dissertation, I undertake to study the theory of intentionality and perception developed in the works of the American philosopher John Searle. The term ‘intentionality’ derives from the Latin word intentio, which is the noun form of the verb intendere. It literally means being directed towards some target or thing.1 In philosophy, however, ‘intentionality’ is used as a technical term. Therefore, its literal meaning should not be confused with its philosophical meaning. Intentionality, philosophers say, is the property of mental states that they are about objects and states of affairs in the world. Most events and states of the mental lives of human beings or other higher cognitive mammals – perception, belief, desire, hope, love, hate, fear, etc. – exhibit this important feature. What unifies such mental states is that they all are about something other than themselves. For example, when I see a tree, my perceptual experience is about a tree; when I have a belief that my pen is in my bag, my belief is about the state of affairs that my pen is in my bag; and so on. In this dissertation, I especially focus on the intentionality of perception. Peter Strawson once wrote that “a philosopher’s views on [perception] are a key to his theory of knowledge and to his metaphysics”.2 I want to add that this is true for a theory of intentionality as well. Perception, as Searle puts it, is the primary medium by virtue of which subjects are related to the world. Therefore, questions on perception (such as “What is perception?”, “Does perception give us direct access to the world?”, “Does perception represent the world in the way beliefs or desires do?”, “How can an account of perceptual intentionality fit into a broader account of intentionality?”, etc.) have never drifted far from philosophical attention. Most philosophers who have developed theories of intentionality have also taken great pains to examine perception as well. John Rogers Searle (born 1932) is not an exception in that sense. He is a well-known philosopher of our period,3 who synthesised his theory of intentionality with his theory of 1 Cf. Jacob (2014). 2 Strawson (1979), 41. 3 Searle pursued his graduate degrees at Oxford. At the University of Oxford, he got to know John Austin and Peter Strawson and was raised under the influence of their philosophical ideas. In 1959, Searle began to work at 1 perception. Generally speaking, Searle’s research interest embraces a variety of topics which belong to a range of different areas of philosophical interest. He has written a number of different books on philosophy of mind, social philosophy, and philosophy of science. Nevertheless, Searle’s magnum opus, Speech Acts (1969), was devoted to the problems of philosophy of language, which stood at the center of his early philosophical inquiry. Since his focus of research line in Speech Acts was also continued in Expression and Meaning (1979), and since this work has greatly motivated Searle’s theory of intentionality, in this introduction I deem it useful to briefly consider its main topic. In Speech Acts, Searle focuses on how speech acts – the minimal units of language – work.4 However, he soon realises that, to better understand how speech acts function, he has to consider intentions. The reason for this is that, when people communicate, they do it intentionally. So Searle comes to the idea that the analysis of speech acts involves the concept of intention. According to this analysis, when the speaker says something to the hearer, he issues a speech act with the intention of letting the hearer to know what he (the speaker) says. For example, when I say to my friend “It is raining”, I issue a speech act with the intention of letting my friend to know what the weather is.5 There is
Recommended publications
  • European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, IV-2 | 2012 Darwinized Hegelianism Or Hegelianized Darwinism? 2
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy IV-2 | 2012 Wittgenstein and Pragmatism Darwinized Hegelianism or Hegelianized Darwinism? Mathias Girel Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/736 DOI: 10.4000/ejpap.736 ISSN: 2036-4091 Publisher Associazione Pragma Electronic reference Mathias Girel, « Darwinized Hegelianism or Hegelianized Darwinism? », European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy [Online], IV-2 | 2012, Online since 24 December 2012, connection on 21 April 2019. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ejpap/736 ; DOI : 10.4000/ejpap.736 This text was automatically generated on 21 April 2019. Author retains copyright and grants the European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Darwinized Hegelianism or Hegelianized Darwinism? 1 Darwinized Hegelianism or Hegelianized Darwinism? Mathias Girel 1 It has been said that Peirce was literally talking “with the rifle rather than with the shot gun or water hose” (Perry 1935, vol. 2: 109). Readers of his review of James’s Principles can easily understand why. In some respects, the same might be true of the series of four books Joseph Margolis has been devoting to pragmatism since 2000. One of the first targets of Margolis’s rereading was the very idea of a ‘revival’ of pragmatism (a ‘revival’ of something that never was, in some ways), and, with it, the idea that the long quarrel between Rorty and Putnam was really a quarrel over pragmatism (that is was a pragmatist revival, in some ways). The uncanny thing is that, the more one read the savory chapters of the four books, the more one feels that the hunting season is open, but that the game is not of the usual kind and looks more like zombies, so to speak.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 1
    Philosophy 1 PHILOSOPHY VISITING FACULTY Doing philosophy means reasoning about questions that are of basic importance to the human experience—questions like, What is a good life? What is reality? Aileen Baek How are knowledge and understanding possible? What should we believe? BA, Yonsei University; MA, Yonsei University; PHD, Yonsei University What norms should govern our societies, our relationships, and our activities? Visiting Associate Professor of Philosophy; Visiting Scholar in Philosophy Philosophers critically analyze ideas and practices that often are assumed without reflection. Wesleyan’s philosophy faculty draws on multiple traditions of Alessandra Buccella inquiry, offering a wide variety of perspectives and methods for addressing these BA, Universitagrave; degli Studi di Milano; MA, Universitagrave; degli Studi di questions. Milano; MA, Universidad de Barcelona; PHD, University of Pittsburgh Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy William Paris BA, Susquehanna University; MA, New York University; PHD, Pennsylvania State FACULTY University Stephen Angle Frank B. Weeks Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy BA, Yale University; PHD, University of Michigan Mansfield Freeman Professor of East Asian Studies; Professor of Philosophy; Director, Center for Global Studies; Professor, East Asian Studies EMERITI Lori Gruen Brian C. Fay BA, University of Colorado Boulder; PHD, University of Colorado Boulder BA, Loyola Marymount University; DPHIL, Oxford University; MA, Oxford William Griffin Professor of Philosophy; Professor
    [Show full text]
  • “The Sixth Sense”: Towards a History of Muscular Sensation
    Gesnerus 68/1 (2011) 218–71 “The Sixth Sense”: Towards a History of Muscular Sensation Roger Smith* Summary This paper outlines the history of knowledge about the muscular sense and provides a bibliographic resource for further research. A range of different topics, questions and approaches have interrelated throughout this history, and the discussion clarifies this rather than presenting detailed research in any one area. Part I relates the origin of belief in a muscular sense to empiricist accounts of the contribution of the senses to knowledge from Locke, via the idéologues and other authors, to the second half of the nine- teenth century. Analysis paid much attention to touch, first in the context of the theory of vision and then in its own right, which led to naming a distinct muscular sense. From 1800 to the present, there was much debate, the main lines of which this paper introduces, about the nature and function of what turned out to be a complex sense. A number of influential psycho-physiolo- gists, notably Alexander Bain and Herbert Spencer, thought this sense the most primitive and primary of all, the origin of knowledge of world, causa- tion and self as an active subject. Part II relates accounts of the muscular sense to the development of nervous physiology and of psychology. In the decades before 1900, the developing separation of philosophy, psychology and physiology as specialised disciplines divided up questions which earlier writers had discussed under the umbrella heading of muscular * The stimulus for writing up this paper, which I had long put off because I hoped to do some- thing more rounded, came from the participants, and especially from the organisers, Vincent Barras and Guillemette Bolens, of a project ‘L’intelligence kinesthésique et le savoir sensori- moteur: entre arts et sciences’, at a conference of World Knowledge Dialogue, ‘Interdisci- plinarity in action: a p ractical experience of interdisciplinary research’, Villars-sur-Ollon, Switzerland, 10–14 October 2010.
    [Show full text]
  • Merleau-Ponty and the Transcendental Problem of Bodily Agency
    Merleau-Ponty and the Transcendental Problem of Bodily Agency Rasmus Thybo Jensen In Merleau-Ponty’s early works he draws attention to a problem concerning bodily agency which he presents as analogous to the problem of perception that is his primary concern. The analogy between the two problems is implicitly recognized when Merleau-Ponty in his first book The Structure of Behavior (1942) writes: Our intentions find their natural clothing or their embodiment in movements and are expressed in them as the thing is expressed in its perspectival aspects. (SC 1983, p. 188/ 1990, p. 203)1 In both cases the initial problem is to recognize the sui generis character of the intentionality that characterize the phenomena in question. For Merleau-Ponty the basic problem concerning perception consists in understanding how perception, as the occurrence in our subjective life it is, can constitute an openness to the world that confronts us with the object itself in person rather than a mere proxy which remains at a distance from reality itself. What I suggest in the following is that there exists an analogous problem concerning how we can regard the objective occur- rence of a bodily movement in the life an organism, as the bodily presence and direct intervention of a mind in the objective world rather than as a mere emissary of the mind. My aim is to flesh out this parallel problem concerning bodily agency and to show that it is in fact a problem that is more or less explicitly articulated in Merleau-Ponty’s early works exactly via an analogy to what he explicitly calls the problem of perception.
    [Show full text]
  • Reflexive Monism
    Reflexive Monism Max Velmans, Goldsmiths, University of London; email [email protected]; http://www.goldsmiths.ac.uk/psychology/staff/velmans.php Journal of Consciousness Studies (2008), 15(2), 5-50. Abstract. Reflexive monism is, in essence, an ancient view of how consciousness relates to the material world that has, in recent decades, been resurrected in modern form. In this paper I discuss how some of its basic features differ from both dualism and variants of physicalist and functionalist reductionism, focusing on those aspects of the theory that challenge deeply rooted presuppositions in current Western thought. I pay particular attention to the ontological status and seeming “out- thereness” of the phenomenal world and to how the “phenomenal world” relates to the “physical world”, the “world itself”, and processing in the brain. In order to place the theory within the context of current thought and debate, I address questions that have been raised about reflexive monism in recent commentaries and also evaluate competing accounts of the same issues offered by “transparency theory” and by “biological naturalism”. I argue that, of the competing views on offer, reflexive monism most closely follows the contours of ordinary experience, the findings of science, and common sense. Key words: Consciousness, reflexive, monism, dualism, reductionism, physicalism, functionalism, transparency, biological naturalism, phenomenal world, physical world, world itself, universe itself, brain, perceptual projection, phenomenal space, measured space, physical space, space perception, information, virtual reality, hologram, phenomenological internalism, phenomenological externalism, first person, third person, complementary What is Reflexive Monism? Monism is the view that the universe, at the deepest level of analysis, is one thing, or composed of one fundamental kind of stuff.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Perception As a Guide to Aesthetics
    OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Fri Jan 31 2014, NEWGEN 5 Philosophy of Perception as a Guide to Aesthetics Bence Nanay 5.1 The Provocative Claim The aim of this paper is to argue for a provocative claim: that many, maybe even most traditional problems in aesthetics are in fact about philosophy of perception and can, as a result, be fruitfully addressed with the help of the conceptual apparatus of the philosophy of perception. I will spend much of the paper clarifying and qualifying this claim, which after all the qualifications may not sound so provocative after all. I need to clarify the following aspects of this claim: (a) What is meant by aesthetics. (b) What is meant by philosophy of perception. (c) Why should we accept that it is a promising avenue of research to consider prob- lems in aesthetics to be really about the philosophy of perception. I will take these in turn. But before we begin, it needs to be emphasized that on the face of it, the claim I make does not sound crazy, at least if we consider the etymology of the term ‘aesthetics’. The Greek word ‘aesthemi’ means perception and when Alexander Baumgarten introduced the concept of ‘aesthetics’ in 1750, what he meant by it was precisely the philosophy of perception: the study of sense perception (scientia cogni- tionis sensitivae). My claim is that, regardless of etymology, this connection can also be made today. It is important that my aim is not to argue that aesthetics should be a subdiscipline of philosophy of perception or that any approach that does not consider aesthetics to be philosophy of perception is doomed or should be considered inferior.
    [Show full text]
  • Searle's Biological Naturalism and the Argument from Consciousness
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 15 Issue 1 Article 5 1-1-1998 Searle's Biological Naturalism and the Argument from Consciousness J.P. Moreland Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Moreland, J.P. (1998) "Searle's Biological Naturalism and the Argument from Consciousness," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 15 : Iss. 1 , Article 5. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil19981513 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol15/iss1/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. SEARLE'S BIOLOGICAL NATURALISM AND THE ARGUMENT FROM CONSCIOUSNESS J. P. Moreland In recent years, Robert Adams and Richard Swinburne have developed an argument for God's existence from the reality of mental phenomena. Call this the argument from consciousness (AC). My purpose is to develop and defend AC and to use it as a rival paradigm to critique John Searle's biological natural­ ism. The article is developed in three steps. First, two issues relevant to the epistemic task of adjudicating between rival scientific paradigms (basicality and naturalness) are clarified and illustrated. Second, I present a general ver­ sion of AC and identify the premises most likely to come under attack by philosophical naturalists. Third, I use the insights gained in steps one and two to criticize Searle's claim that he has developed an adequate naturalistic theory of the emergence of mental entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Bertrand Russell on Perception and Knowledge (1927 – 59)
    BERTRAND RUSSELL ON PERCEPTION AND KNOWLEDGE (1927 – 59) BERTRAND RUSSELL ON PERCEPTION AND KNOWLEDGE (1927 – 59) By DUSTIN Z. OLSON, B.A. (Hons.) A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Philosophy McMaster University © Copyright by Dustin Z. Olson, August 2011 ii MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY (2011) McMaster University (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: Bertrand Russell on Perception and Knowledge (1927 – 59) AUTHOR: Dustin Z. Olson SUPERVISOR: Nicholas Griffin NUMBER OF PAGES: vii, 154 iii ABSTRACT Bertrand Russell is one of the grandmasters of 20 th Century Analytic Philosophy. It is surprising, then, that his work fell out of fashion later in his career. As a result, very little has been discussed concerning Russell’s work from the period of 1927 – 59. This thesis provides an analysis of Russell’s philosophical work from this era. Our attention here is on Russell’s theory of perception and the underlying metaphysical structure that is developed as a result of his scientific outlook, as Russell’s philosophy during this time focused almost exclusively on perception, knowledge, and the epistemic relationship humans have with the world according to science. And because Russell’s system is in many ways prescient with regards to recent advances made in perception, mind and matter, and knowledge more generally, we also apply his theory to developments in the philosophy of perception since that time. Our initial discussion – Chapters 1 and 2 – is most concerned with an accurate explication of the concepts germane to and conclusions formed from Russell’s theory of perception.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception
    Roger Williams University DOCS@RWU Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation 2019 Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception John S. Hendrix Roger Williams University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp Part of the Architectural History and Criticism Commons, and the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Hendrix, John S., "Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception" (2019). Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications. 41. https://docs.rwu.edu/saahp_fp/41 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation at DOCS@RWU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of DOCS@RWU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Perception John Shannon Hendrix In an early treatise, Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magni- tudes into Philosophy (Versuch, den Begriff der negative Grössen in die Weltweisheit einzuführen, 1763), Immanuel Kant developed a theory about thoughts that are fleeting, negated or cancelled, obscured or darkened. As certain thoughts become clearer, the other thoughts become less clear and more obscured (Verdunkelt). Kant’s concept was influenced by the petites perceptions of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. He invoked Leibniz in establish- ing that only a small portion of the representations which occur in the soul, as the result of sense perception, are clear and enduring.1 Gottfried Leibniz conceived of minute perceptions of objects or ideas which have too little intensity to effect conscious thought. The minute per- ceptions contribute to ordinary perceptions, but they are so small and there are so many of them that they pass unnoticed in the consciousness connected to perception.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Philosophy of Perception
    OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF 1 Philosophy of Perception The New Wave Bence Nanay I Peter Strawson famously wrote more than thirty years ago that “a philoso- pher’s views on [perception] are a key to his theory of knowledge and to his metaphysics” (1979, 41). At that time, this statement probably would have been quite provocative inasmuch as it made perception sound more important than it was assumed to be. Now, thirty years later, Strawson’s claim sounds too weak. A philoso- pher’s views on perception are as important as her theory of knowledge or her metaphysics. Some may even be tempted to say that a philosopher’s views on epistemology or metaphysics are a key to her theory of percep- tion. Perception is no longer seen as an inferior subfi eld of philosophy that may or may not help us to understand the philosophical questions that are supposedly more fundamental. Perception, at present, is as central a philosophical subfi eld as it gets. This change is not only a merely quantitative one. It is true that more philosophers are working on perception and that their output is more sophisticated and nuanced than ever before, but this is not the whole story. What is more relevant, and more interesting from a philosophical point of view, is that the nature of the questions that are being asked about perception has also changed. The aim of this volume is to give a representative sample of this new wave of philosophy of perception. And the aim of this introduction is to outline the questions contemporary philosophers of perception are concerned with and how they differ from the “old” philosophical questions about perception.
    [Show full text]
  • The Value of Perception
    This is a repository copy of The Value of Perception. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/138062/ Version: Published Version Article: Allen, Keith Malcolm orcid.org/0000-0002-3219-2102 (2019) The Value of Perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. pp. 633-656. ISSN 0031-8205 https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12574 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research doi: 10.1111/phpr.12574 © 2019 The Authors. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research published by Wiley Periodicals, Inc. on behalf of Philosophy and Phenonmenological Research Inc. The Value of Perception KEITH ALLEN University of York This paper develops a form of transcendental na€ıve realism. According to na€ıve realism, veridical perceptual experiences are essentially relational. According to transcendental na€ıve realism, the na€ıve realist theory of perception is not just one theory of perception amongst others, to be established as an inference to the best explanation and assessed on the basis of a cost-benefit analysis that weighs performance along a number of different dimensions: for instance, fidelity to appearances, simplicity, systematicity, fit with scientific theo- ries, and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Rationality of Perception
    The Rationality of Perception: Replies to Lord, Railton, and Pautz The Rationality of Perception thesis raises so many questions about the epistemic roles of Susanna Siegel perceptual experience that what’s needed, in my estimation, is a constructive defense of it: Book symposium forthcoming in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research an account of how inference could affect the epistemic powers of perceptual experience. My constructive defense aims to show that it is coherent and plausible that perceptual experience plays epistemic roles that make it rationally susceptible. Introduction The main task of The Rationality of Perception is to construct an epistemology of perception As part of my constructive defense of the Rationality of Perception thesis, I defend an according to which perceptual experiences can be rational or irrational. On this picture, approach to inference according to which inferring is a distinctive way of leveraging experiences are susceptible to rational evaluation. The Rationality of Perception thesis is information one has already into a new informational state. When it is formed via such a that both perceptual experiences and the processes that give rise to them can be rational or response, the new informational state is the conclusion of the act of inferring. I argue that irrational. nothing precludes perceptual experiences from being such conclusions. So part of my defense is a general theory of inferring in general. My target is the kind of inferring the The epistemic roles that I attribute to perceptual experiences are best brought out by a redounds well or poorly on the subject’s rational standing. Many of the low-level processes subclass of cases in which perceptual experiences are heavily shaped by prior outlooks.
    [Show full text]