A Companion to Rationalism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Companion to Rationalism A Companion to Rationalism i ACTA01 1 14/9/05, 12:03 PM Blackwell Companions to Philosophy This outstanding student reference series offers a comprehensive and authoritative survey of philosophy as a whole. Written by today’s leading philosophers, each volume provides lucid and engaging coverage of the key figures, terms, topics, and problems of the field. Taken together, the volumes provide the ideal basis for course use, representing an unparalleled work of reference for students and specialists alike. Already published in the series: A Companion to Business Ethics Edited by Robert E. Frederick The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, Second Edition A Companion to the Philosophy of Science Edited by Nicholas Bunnin and Eric Edited by W. H. Newton-Smith Tsui-James A Companion to Environmental Philosophy A Companion to Ethics Edited by Dale Jamieson Edited by Peter Singer A Companion to Analytic Philosophy A Companion to Aesthetics Edited by A. P. Martinich and David Sosa Edited by David Cooper A Companion to Genethics A Companion to Epistemology Edited by Justine Burley and John Harris Edited by Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa A Companion to Philosophical Logic A Companion to Contemporary Political Edited by Dale Jacquette Philosophy A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy Edited by Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit Edited by Steven Nadler A Companion to Philosophy of Mind A Companion to Philosophy in the Edited by Samuel Guttenplan Middle Ages A Companion to Metaphysics Edited by Jorge J. E. Gracia and Timothy B. Edited by Jaegwon Kim and Ernest Sosa Noone A Companion to Philosophy of Law and A Companion to African-American Legal Theory Philosophy Edited by Dennis Patterson Edited by Tommy L. Lott and John P. Pittman A Companion to Philosophy of Religion A Companion to Applied Ethics Edited by Philip L. Quinn and Charles Taliaferro Edited by R. G. Frey and Christopher Heath Wellman A Companion to the Philosophy of Language Edited by Bob Hale and Crispin Wright A Companion to the Philosophy of Education Edited by Randall Curren A Companion to World Philosophies Edited by Eliot Deutsch and Ron Bontekoe A Companion to African Philosophy Edited by Kwasi Wiredu A Companion to Continental Philosophy Edited by Simon Critchley and A Companion to Heidegger William Schroeder Edited by Hubert L. Dreyfus and Mark A. Wrathall A Companion to Feminist Philosophy Edited by Alison M. Jaggar and Iris Marion A Companion to Rationalism Young Edited by Alan Nelson A Companion to Cognitive Science A Companion to Ancient Philosophy Edited by William Bechtel and George Graham Edited by Mary Louise Gill and Pierre Pellegrin A Companion to Bioethics A Companion to Pragmatism Edited by Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer Edited by John R. Shook and Joseph Margolis A Companion to the Philosophers A Companion to Nietzsche Edited by Robert L. Arrington Edited by Keith Ansell Pearson ii ACTA01 2 14/9/05, 12:03 PM A Companion to Rationalism Edited by Alan Nelson iii ACTA01 3 14/9/05, 12:03 PM © 2005 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd except for editorial material and organization © 2005 by Alan Nelson blackwell publishing 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148-5020, USA 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK 550 Swanston Street, Carlton, Victoria 3053, Australia The right of Alan Nelson to be identified as the Author of the Editorial Material in this Work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs, and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs, and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher. First published 2005 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd 1 2005 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A companion to rationalism / edited by Alan Nelson. p. cm. – (Blackwell companions to philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN-13: 978-1-4051-0909-3 (alk. paper) ISBN-10: 1-4051-0909-2 (alk. paper) 1. Rationalism. I. Nelson, Alan Jean. II. Series. B833.C66 2006 149′.7–dc22 2005010996 A catalogue record for this title is available from the British Library. Set in 10/12.5pt Photina by Graphicraft Limited, Hong Kong Printed and bound in the United Kingdom by TJ International, Padstow, Cornwall The publisher’s policy is to use permanent paper from mills that operate a sustainable forestry policy, and which has been manufactured from pulp processed using acid-free and elementary chlorine-free practices. Furthermore, the publisher ensures that the text paper and cover board used have met acceptable environmental accreditation standards. For further information on Blackwell Publishing, visit our website: www.blackwellpublishing.com iv ACTA01 4 14/9/05, 12:03 PM To Linda and Ian with love v ACTA01 5 14/9/05, 12:03 PM Contents List of Contributors ix Acknowledgments xi List of Abbreviations xii Introduction xiv Part I The Core of Rationalism 1 1 The Rationalist Impulse 3 Alan Nelson 2 The Rationalist Conception of Substance 12 Thomas M. Lennon 3 Rationalist Theories of Sense Perception and Mind–Body Relation 31 Gary Hatfield 4 Rationalism and Education 61 David Cunning Part II The Historical Background 83 5 Plato’s Rationalistic Method 85 Hugh H. Benson 6 Rationalism in Jewish Philosophy 100 Steven Nadler 7 Early Modern Critiques of Rationalist Psychology 119 Antonia LoLordo 8 Rationalism and Method 137 Matthew J. Kisner 9 Cartesian Imaginations: The Method and Passions of Imagining 156 Dennis L. Sepper vii ACTA01 7 8/9/05, 2:06 PM contents Part III The Heyday of Rationalism 177 10 Descartes’ Rationalist Epistemology 179 Lex Newman 11 Rationalism and Representation 206 Kurt Smith 12 The Role of the Imagination in Rationalist Philosophies of Mathematics 224 Lawrence Nolan 13 Idealism and Cartesian Motion 250 Alice Sowaal 14 Leibniz on Shape and the Cartesian Conception of Body 262 Timothy Crockett 15 Leibniz on Modality, Cognition, and Expression 282 Alan Nelson 16 Rationalist Moral Philosophy 302 Andrew Youpa 17 Spinoza, Leibniz, and the Rationalist Reconceptions of Imagination 322 Dennis L. Sepper 18 Kant and the Two Dogmas of Rationalism 343 Henry E. Allison Part IV Rationalist Themes in Contemporary Philosophy 361 19 Rationalism in the Phenomenological Tradition 363 David Woodruff Smith 20 Rationalist Elements of Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy 379 Paul Livingston 21 Proust and the Rationalist Conception of the Self 399 Alan Nelson 22 Rationalism in Science 408 David Stump 23 Rational Decision Making: Descriptive, Prescriptive, or Explanatory? 425 Jonathan Michael Kaplan 24 What is a Feminist to do with Rational Choice? 450 Mariam Thalos 25 Rationalism in the Philosophy of Donald Davidson 468 Richard N. Manning Index 488 viii ACTA01 8 8/9/05, 2:06 PM Contributors Henry E. Allison is Research Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Davis. Hugh H. Benson is Professor and Chair of Philosophy at the University of Oklahoma. Timothy Crockett is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Marquette University. David Cunning is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the University of Iowa. Gary Hatfield is the Adam Seybert Professor in Moral and Intellectual Philosophy at the University of Pennsylvania. Jonathan Michael Kaplan is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Oregon State University. Matthew J. Kisner is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the University of South Carolina. Thomas M. Lennon is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Western Ontario. Paul Livingston is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Villanova University. Antonia LoLordo is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the University of Virginia. Richard N. Manning is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Carleton University. Steven Nadler is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Wisconsin-Madison. Alan Nelson is Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Irvine. Lex Newman is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of Utah. Lawrence Nolan is Associate Professor and Chair of Philosophy at California State University, Long Beach. Dennis L. Sepper is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Dallas. David Woodruff Smith is Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Irvine. Kurt Smith is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Bloomsburg University of Pennsylvania. ix ACTA01 9 14/9/05, 12:04 PM contributors Alice Sowaal is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at San Francisco State University. David Stump is Associate Professor and Chair of Philosophy at the University of San Francisco. Mariam Thalos is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Utah. Andrew Youpa is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Southern Illinois University, Carbondale. x ACTA01 10 14/9/05, 12:04 PM Acknowledgments I thank the authors and the editors at Blackwell Publishing for making this volume possible. The final stage of my own editorial contributions was supported by a leave from the University of California, Irvine; and by the hospitality of the Philosophy Department at the University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill, and the Center for Human Science, Chapel Hill. xi ACTA01 11 14/9/05, 12:04 PM Abbreviations Works cited frequently throughout the volume are abbreviated as follows: A Leibniz, Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe (Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschafter, ed.). Darmstadt: Akademie-Verlag, 1923–. Cited by series, volume, and page. AG Leibniz, Philosophical Essays (Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber, trans. and eds.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1989. AL Bacon, The Advancement of Learning. In Brian Vickers (ed.), Francis Bacon: A Critical Edition of the Major Works. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996. Cited by page. Ar Aristotle, De Anima (J. A. Smith, trans.). In J. Barnes (ed.), Complete Works of Aristotle, 2 vols. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984. Cited by the standard page and line numbers for Aristotle’s works (Bekker numbers). AT Descartes, Oeuvres de Descartes, 11 vols.
Recommended publications
  • Origins, Philosophy, and Theology
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge United States History History 12-24-1997 Jefferson's Declaration of Independence: Origins, Philosophy, and Theology Allen Jayne Click here to let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Thanks to the University of Kentucky Libraries and the University Press of Kentucky, this book is freely available to current faculty, students, and staff at the University of Kentucky. Find other University of Kentucky Books at uknowledge.uky.edu/upk. For more information, please contact UKnowledge at [email protected]. Recommended Citation Jayne, Allen, "Jefferson's Declaration of Independence: Origins, Philosophy, and Theology" (1997). United States History. 9. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/upk_united_states_history/9 Jefferson's Declaration of Independence &.0 Jefferson's Declaration of Independence &.o Origins, Philosophy and Theology Allen Jayne THE UNIVJERSITY PRJESS OJF KENTUCKY Publication of this volume was made possible in part by a grant from the National Endowment for the Humanities. Copyright © 1998 by The University Press of Kentucky Scholarly publisher for the Commonwealth, serving Bellarmine University, Berea College, Centre College of I(entucky, Eastern Kentucky University, The Filson Historical Society, Georgetown College, I(entucky Historical Society, Kentucky State University, Morehead State University, Murray State University, Northern I(entucky University, Transylvania University, University of I(entucky, University of Louisville, and Western Kentucky University. All rights reserved. Editorial and Sales Offices: The University Press of Kentucky 663 South Limestone Street, Lexington, Kentucky 40508-4008 www.kentuckypress.com Frontispiece: Thomas jefferson, a photogravure made from the original painting by Mather Brown. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data jayne, Allen.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Suspend Judging?∗ Jane Friedman [email protected] | 06/2017
    Why Suspend Judging?∗ Jane Friedman [email protected] j 06/2017 1 Introduction Even though philosophers have been thinking about suspension of judgment for nearly as long as they’ve been thinking about anything, and contemporary discussions have it placed as traditional epistemology’s other doxastic attitude, there is only limited consensus about the nature of the state and generally very little said about its point or purpose or role in our doxastic lives (at least in com- parison to its obviously far more charming doxastic bedfellow, belief). In this paper I want to try to say a little bit on these matters by providing a framework within which we can begin to answer the titular question here. The framework will tell us more both about the nature and function of suspension of judgment as well as give us some guidance as to its “normative profile” (when we should suspend, have reason to suspend, are justified in suspending and so on). The general thought is that suspension of judgment is closely tied to inquiry. In fact I want to argue that one is inquiring into some matter if and only if one is suspended on the matter.1 Tying suspension of judgment to inquiry in this way brings us back to some of the earliest views of the state. One of the thoughts that emerges in the work of both Sextus Empiricus and Descartes is that suspension of judgment is closely connected to inquiry and perhaps even that suspending is itself a way of being in an inquiring mode or frame of mind.2 The thought that suspending might ∗Please cite final version: Friedman, J.
    [Show full text]
  • View / Download
    ELECTRYONE ΗΛΕΚΤΡΥΩΝΗ Xenophanes of Colophon and the Problem of Distinguishing Between Skepticism and Negative Dogmatism Dariusz Kubok University of Silesia in Katowice [email protected] ABSTRACT: Sextus Empiricus in Pyr. (I, 224, cf Diog. IX, 18) describes Xenophanes of Colophon as hupatuphos, which is to mean that he was a skeptic who did not entirely free himself of dogmatic assertions. In this paper I will try to demonstrate an alternative way of understanding hupatuphos in relation to Xenophanes. In my opinion, the interpretation according to which passages can be found in Xenophanes' writings expressing both a skeptical and negative dogmatic position is possible. Thus, this thinker may be described with the adjective hupatuphos not because he did not manage to free himself of positive dogmatism, but rather because he did not free himself of negative dogmatism. KEY-WORDS: skepticism, dogmatism, knowledge, truth, opinion, Xenophanes of Colophon In his Outlines of Pyrrhonism (PH I, 224, cf Diog. IX, 18), Sextus Empiricus invokes the opinion of Timon of Phlius describing Xenophanes of Colophon as hupatuphos ("not entirely free of tuphos,"1 "partly free of conceit,"2 "semi-free of 1 Lesher (1992) 215, n. 53. 2 Lesher (1992) 215. Xenophanes of Colophon and the Problem of Distinguishing Between Skepticism and Negative Dogmatism vanity"3), referring to the fact that both dogmatic and skeptical elements can be found in his views. Among the dogmatic elements are the belief that everything is one and the passages implying the existence of a positive (constructive) theology. Based on Sextus’ opinion some scholars see conflict in Xenophanes’ philosophy between positive dogmatic theology and skepticism.4 In this article, I will try to show that it is possible to seriously weaken this conflict, if not to do away with it entirely, and that an epistemological reading of Xenophanes may lead to more fruitful conclusions.
    [Show full text]
  • Agrippan Pyrrhonism and the Challenge of Disagreement
    Journal of Philosophical Research Volume 40 2015 pp. 23–39 AGRIPPAN PYRRHONISM AND THE CHALLENGE OF DISAGREEMENT DIEGO E. MACHUCA CONICET ABSTRACT: This paper argues for the following three claims. First, the Agrippan mode from disagreement does not play a secondary role in inducing suspension of judgment. Second, the Pyrrhonist is not committed to the criteria of justification underlying the Five Modes of Agrippa, which nonetheless does not prevent him from non-doxastically assenting to them. And third, some recent objec- tions to Agrippan Pyrrhonism raised by analytic epistemologists and experimental philosophers fail to appreciate the Pyrrhonist’s ad hominem style of argumentation and the real challenge posed by the mode from disagreement. I. INTRODUCTION The subject of this essay is the set of arguments known as the Five Modes of Agrippa, which are the most powerful weapons of the Pyrrhonian argumentative arsenal found in Sextus Empiricus’s extant works. My purpose is to offer an interpretation both of certain aspects of the challenge posed by these modes and of the Pyrrhonist’s attitude towards them. More precisely, I propose to show: (i) that the mode from disagreement does not play a secondary role in inducing suspension of judgment; (ii) that the Pyrrhonist is not committed to the criteria of justification underlying the Agrippan modes, which nonethe- less does not prevent him from assenting to them in a weak, non-doxastic way; and (iii) that some recent objections to Agrippan Pyrrhonism raised by analytic epistemologists and experimental philosophers fail to appreciate the Pyrrhonist’s ad hominem style of argumentation and the real challenge posed by the mode from disagreement.
    [Show full text]
  • Disagreeing with the Pyrrhonist? 25 2
    2 Disagreeing with the Pyrrhonist? Otávio Bueno 1. INTRODUCTION For the Pyrrhonian skeptic, disagreement is an integral part of the skepti- cal way of inquiry (see Pyrrhonian Outlines I 165).1 The fact that there is undecidable disagreement about a given issue makes the Pyrrhonian skeptic unable to decide that issue, and suspension of judgment emerges. But is sus- pension of judgment the appropriate response in this case? In this paper, I address two related topics. In the bulk of the paper, I exam- ine critically Jonathan Barnes’ contention to the effect that disagreement alone is not enough to yield suspension of judgment; additional Agrippa’s modes need to be invoked as well (Barnes 1990: ch. 1). I argue that noth- ing prevents the Pyrrhonian skeptic from suspending judgment only due to disagreement. In fact, that is exactly what Sextus himself points out: “And because of the dispute [that is, the undecidable disagreement over a certain issue] we cannot choose or reject anything, and so end in suspension of judg- ment” (PH I 165; see Barnes 1990: 17). But does any form of disagreement yield suspension of judgment? To answer this question I consider recent debates about the epistemol- ogy of disagreement (see, e.g., Feldman & Warfield 2010). According to the Total Evidence View, what is reasonable for us to believe depends on the total evidence available to us.2 I argue that this view clearly provides a sufficient condition for the Pyrrhonian skeptic to suspend judgment due to disagreement alone. If the total evidence available to us—including the Pyrrhonian skeptic—does not favor any side of an issue over which there is disagreement, suspension of judgment is the natural outcome.
    [Show full text]
  • The New Organon: Or True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature
    The New Organon: or True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature Francis Bacon Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported between brackets in normal-sized type.—‘Organon’ is the conventional title for the collection of logical works by Aristotle, a body of doctrine that Bacon aimed to replace. His title Novum Organum could mean ‘The New Organon’ or more modestly ‘A New Organon’; the tone of the writing in this work points to the definite article. First launched: January 2005 The New Organon Francis Bacon Contents PREFACE 1 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 1–774 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 78–130 24 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 1–25 48 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 26–43 75 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 44–52 102 The New Organon Francis Bacon PREFACE PREFACE Those who have taken it on themselves to lay down the thinking and continuous mental effort. law of nature as something that has already been discovered My method is hard to practice but easy to explain.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reliabilist Strategy for Solving the Problem of Induction by Fergus
    A Reliabilist Strategy for Solving the Problem of Induction By Fergus Dale Prien ORCID: 0000-0002-0940-9676 Dissertation Submitted in Total Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Research in Philosophy In the School of Historical and Philosophical Studies At the University of Melbourne Melbourne November 2019 Student Name: Fergus Prien Student Number: 588353 Acknowledgements There are a number of people and institutions that must be thanked for having made it possible for me to undertake this research project, and now complete it. I thank the Australian Government for supporting my research training at the University of Melbourne through the Research Training Program (RTP). I also thank the University of Melbourne and the School of Historical and Philosophical Studies in general for the opportunity to study at a great institution with learned academics who care about both the intellectual formation and general wellbeing of their students. More specifically, I would like to thank my primary supervisor, Howard Sankey, for the great multitude of hours that he has put in to both reviewing the various iterations of this dissertation (many far different from this one) and patiently helping me to think and write more critically. I have certainly grown in my scholarly ability and passion for philosophy under his supervision. I want to thank Brennan McDavid for her contribution to the supervision of my dissertation during her time at the University of Melbourne, as well as Greg Restall for agreeing to be my secondary supervisor quite late in this project. I also want to thank Brian Ellis, James Franklin, Callan Ledsham, Andrew Mullins, Xavier Symons, Brother Reginald Mary Chua, Fernando Jativa, and my fellow graduate philosophy students at the University of Melbourne who attended both or either of my seminar presentations – the feedback that I received from these people at specific points in my research certainly contributed to how I have formulated the thesis that I defend in this dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius
    SAPERE Scripta Antiquitatis Posterioris ad Ethicam REligionemque pertinentia Schriften der späteren Antike zu ethischen und religiösen Fragen Herausgegeben von Rainer Hirsch-Luipold, Reinhard Feldmeier und Heinz-Günther Nesselrath unter der Mitarbeit von Natalia Pedrique und Andrea Villani Band XXV Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius Introduction, Text, Translation, Commentary and Interpretative Essays by Katja Maria Vogt, Richard Bett, Lorenzo Corti, Tiziano Dorandi, Christiana M. M. Olfert, Elisabeth Scharffenberger, David Sedley, and James Warren edited by Katja Maria Vogt Mohr Siebeck SAPERE is a Project of the Göttingen Academy of Sciences and Humanities within the programme of the Union of the German Academies funded by the Federal Republic of Germany and the State of Lower Saxony. e-ISBN PDF 978-3-16-156430-7 ISBN 978-3-16-153336-5 The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Natio nal- bibliographie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http:// dnb.dnb.de. © 2015 by Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, Germany. www.mohr.de This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This ap- plies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and pro- cessing in electronic systems. This book was supervised by Heinz-Günther Nesselrath (representing the SAPERE Editors) and typeset by Magdalena Albrecht, Janjenka Szillat and Andrea Villani at the SAPERE Research Institute, Göttingen. Printed by Gulde Druck in Tübin- gen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Spinner in Ottersweier. Printed in Germany. SAPERE Greek and Latin texts of Later Antiquity (1st–4th centuries AD) have for a long time been overshadowed by those dating back to so-called ‘classi- cal’ times.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Cicero's Eclectic Probabilism
    Revista Archai ISSN: 1984-249X Universidade de Brasília Skvirsky, Alexandre Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Revista Archai, no. 27, e02705, 2019 Universidade de Brasília DOI: https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=586161659005 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System Redalyc More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America and the Caribbean, Spain and Journal's webpage in redalyc.org Portugal Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative AS ORIGENS DO PENSAMENTO OCIDENTAL THE ORIGINS OF WESTERN THOUGHT ARTIGO I ARTICLE Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Alexandre Skvirsky i https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9508-1023 [email protected] i Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio de Janeiro – Rio de Janeiro – RJ – Brasil SKVIRSKY, A. (2019). Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica. Archai 27, e02705. Abstract: The objective is to show the peculiar way in which Cicero’s philosophical thinking is original and distances itself from the main representatives of the New Academy: the Roman thinker does not practice epoche, nor does he assign any special role to it in his thought. Instead, Cicero introduces the concept of doubt to characterize his own way of thinking. Keywords: Cicero, epoche, doubt, skepticism, probabilism. https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 [1] 2 Rev. Archai, n. 27, Brasília, 2019, e02705. Cicero’s philosophical contributions have often been downplayed, even by himself. His importance as a translator and divulger of philosophy among the Romans frequently overshadows his originality as a philosopher.
    [Show full text]
  • Bacon's Poetry and Shakespeare's
    No “Idle Fancy:” The Imagination’s Work in Poetry and Natural Philosophy from Sidney to Sprat by Jacqueline L. Cowan Department of English Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Leonard Tennenhouse, Supervisor ___________________________ Andrew Janiak ___________________________ Maureen Quilligan ___________________________ Charlotte Sussman Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English in the Graduate School of Duke University 2015 i v ABSTRACT No “Idle Fancy:” The Imagination’s Work in Poetry and Natural Philosophy from Sidney to Sprat by Jacqueline L. Cowan Department of English Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Leonard Tennenhouse, Supervisor ___________________________ Andrew Janiak ___________________________ Maureen Quilligan ___________________________ Charlotte Sussman An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English in the Graduate School of Duke University 2015 i v Copyright by Jacqueline L. Cowan 2015 Abstract When debating the structure of the cosmos, Raphael delivers to Adam perhaps Milton’s most famous line: “be lowly wise.” With the promise to “justify the ways of God to men,” Milton does not limit man’s knowledge to base matters, but reclaims the heights of “other worlds” for the poet. Over the course of the seventeenth century, the natural philosophers’ material explanations of the natural order were slowly gaining authority over other sources of knowledge, the poets prime among them. My dissertation takes up the competing early modern claims to knowledge that Milton lays down for Adam. I argue that natural philosophy, what today we call “science,” emerged as the dominant authority over knowledge by appropriating the poet’s imagination.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Skepticism: Pyrrhonism Diego E
    Philosophy Compass 6/4 (2011): 246–258, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00391.x Ancient Skepticism: Pyrrhonism Diego E. Machuca* Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Cientı´ficas y Te´cnicas Abstract Pyrrhonism was one of the two main ancient skeptical traditions. In this second paper of the three-part series devoted to ancient skepticism, I present and discuss some of the issues on Pyrrho- nian skepticism which have been the focus of much attention in the recent literature. The topics to be addressed concern the outlooks of Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Sextus Empiricus. In the first paper of this three-part series on ancient skepticism, I offered a general pre- sentation of the ancient skeptical traditions as well as an overview of recent translations and general studies. With this framework in place, the present paper deals with some vexed questions concerning the stances of Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Sextus Empiricus. For reasons of space, the discussion will be selective and it will not always be possible to go into detail about the issues tackled. 1. Pyrrho Most recent scholarship on Pyrrho of Elis (360–270 BC) continues to divide between two main interpretations of his outlook, which may be called ‘practical’ and ‘theoretical’. The first interpretation affirms that Pyrrho’s motivation was exclusively or mainly ethi- cal.1 This view finds support in some passages in Diogenes Laertius and particularly in Cicero, who does not refer to Pyrrho as a skeptic, but invariably portrays him as a moral- ist – as someone who considered virtue as the only good and who was admired for his lifestyle (Academica II 130; On Moral Ends III 11–2, IV 43, 49, 60; On Duties I 6).
    [Show full text]
  • Motivations for Relativism As a Solution to Disagreements
    Motivations for Relativism as a Solution to Disagreements STEVEN D. HALES Abstract There are five basic ways to resolve disagreements: keep arguing until capitulation, compromise, locate an ambiguity or contextual factors, accept Pyrrhonian skepti- cism, and adopt relativism. Relativism is perhaps the most radical and least popular solution to a disagreement, and its defenders generally think the best moti- vator for relativism is to be found in disputes over predicates of personal taste. I argue that taste predicates do not adequately motivate relativism over the other possible sol- utions, and argue that relativism looks like the most promising approach when dis- putants cannot even agree on the meta-evidence for a contested proposition. Relativism is a way to resolve disagreements. Given that there are several ways to address disagreements, what is sufficient motivation to adopt the relativist approach? In this paper I lay out the case for what kinds of epistemic clashes offer the strongest motivation to vote for relativism. I argue that the most promising candidate on the relativist ticket is that of disputes involving irreconcilable differ- ences. Genuine irreconcilable differences are scarce, and I argue that the usual proposals of relativism-motivators, such as predicates of personal taste, fail to generate them. I then argue that irreconcilable differences are to be located at the level of independent methods of generating noninferential beliefs which are then used as basic data for building theories that one holds in reflective equilibrium. There are many ways to resolve disagreements besides relativism. Given that these other methods are often very appealing, or at least have their own partisans, it is incumbent on relativists to show what cases of disagreements are not plausibly addressed by competi- tor strategies.
    [Show full text]