Bacon's Poetry and Shakespeare's

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bacon's Poetry and Shakespeare's No “Idle Fancy:” The Imagination’s Work in Poetry and Natural Philosophy from Sidney to Sprat by Jacqueline L. Cowan Department of English Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Leonard Tennenhouse, Supervisor ___________________________ Andrew Janiak ___________________________ Maureen Quilligan ___________________________ Charlotte Sussman Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English in the Graduate School of Duke University 2015 i v ABSTRACT No “Idle Fancy:” The Imagination’s Work in Poetry and Natural Philosophy from Sidney to Sprat by Jacqueline L. Cowan Department of English Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Leonard Tennenhouse, Supervisor ___________________________ Andrew Janiak ___________________________ Maureen Quilligan ___________________________ Charlotte Sussman An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English in the Graduate School of Duke University 2015 i v Copyright by Jacqueline L. Cowan 2015 Abstract When debating the structure of the cosmos, Raphael delivers to Adam perhaps Milton’s most famous line: “be lowly wise.” With the promise to “justify the ways of God to men,” Milton does not limit man’s knowledge to base matters, but reclaims the heights of “other worlds” for the poet. Over the course of the seventeenth century, the natural philosophers’ material explanations of the natural order were slowly gaining authority over other sources of knowledge, the poets prime among them. My dissertation takes up the competing early modern claims to knowledge that Milton lays down for Adam. I argue that natural philosophy, what today we call “science,” emerged as the dominant authority over knowledge by appropriating the poet’s imagination. The poet’s imagination had long revealed the divine hand that marked nature—a task that, as Sidney put it, merited the poet a “peerlesse” rank among other professions. For Bacon, Galileo, and Royal Society fellows, the poetic imagination revealed material explanations of nature’s order that other orthodox models and methods could not. For the first decades of the seventeenth century, the imagination aligned poetry and natural philosophy as complementary pursuits of knowledge: Sidney’s poet was to imagine a “golden” world that revealed the divine order, the material cause of which Bacon’s natural philosopher was to discover in nature. But as the Royal Society fellows countered the claim that they peddled fancies, they severed ties with the poet. In one ingenious rhetorical move, Royal Society fellows proclaimed themselves to have iv perfected the poet’s imaginative work, securing the imagination for natural philosophy while disavowing poetry as the product of an idle fancy. Such rhetoric proved as powerful then as it does now. For Margaret Cavendish, the poet occupies the supplemental role that “recreate[s] the mind” once it grows tired of the “serious” natural philosophical studies. After the Restoration, then, the important role of the poetic imagination would go largely unrecognized even as it set itself to work in what would become the separate disciplines of literature and science. v Dedication To those who keep my feet grounded and my eyes on the horizon, Kamran Ahmed, Ken Cowan, and Kaila Brown. vi Contents Abstract ......................................................................................................................................... iv Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................... vii Introduction………………………………………………………………………………………1 1. Upon Common Grounds: Bacon’s Poetry and Shakespeare’s Natural Philosophy ...... 16 2. Imagining the Moon in Fact and Fiction…………………………………………………...70 3. “Naked” Prose and its Body of Poetry ............................................................................... 128 4. To be “Lowly Wise” at the Height of Discovery .............................................................. 189 Bibliography .............................................................................................................................. 229 Biography ................................................................................................................................... 240 vii Acknowledgements First and foremost, I am indebted to my team of committed and brilliant advisors. Maureen Quilligan brought life to old materials and taught me how to see the best in all things, not the least this dissertation. Charlotte Sussman provided an exemplary model of kindness and grace under pressure. Her guidance has eased the many challenges that have transpired over the last six years. When confronted with dense philosophical material, Andrew Janiak rendered complex ideas accessible, lucid, and exciting. His enthusiasm for natural philosophy continues to affirm my own. Special thanks to Leonard Tennenhouse, who kept me afloat with his keen wit, pragmatic advice, and more than a little of his patience. His tireless dedication to this project and my academic development has made a world of difference. I could not have imagined a better dissertation director and I have been made all the stronger for his stellar advising. I am also grateful to Clinton Smith, Leslie Thomson, Colin Hill, Mari Ruti, Alexandra Gillespie, Tyler Tokaryk, and, especially, Igor Djordjevic for building the confidence I needed to start this journey in the first place. This dissertation has received generous support from the Social Science and Humanities Research Council of Canada and the Myra and William Waldo Boone Fellowship. I am also grateful for the helpful feedback from the editors at Studies in viii Philology; their comments added strength and scope to many of my arguments and ideas. Finally, I would like to acknowledge my beloved family and friends. Many heartfelt thanks are in order to: Linda and Royce, who have both provided sustenance, support, and love; to my grandfather, whose enthusiasm for life lifts me to new heights; to the Pawlowskis, who have cared for me; to Clare Callahan, George Vahamikos, and Whitney Trettien, who have all been instrumental in my growth as an academic and as a person; to Kamran Ahmed, who has been a pillar of support, a brilliant source of inspiration, and the truest companion; to Theia, whose stoic, yet sweet, disposition offers me endless comfort; and to Cameron Christou, who knows how to put a smile on my face, whatever the circumstance. ix Introduction “The cosmos is all that is, or ever was, or ever will be. Our contemplation of the cosmos stirs us .… We know we are approaching the grandest of mysteries.” In these opening lines to the popular 1980s television show Cosmos: A Personal Voyage (lines repeated in the hugely successful 2014 reboot, no less), Carl Sagan waxes poetic about the world revealed to us by science. Scientists often make recourse to the language of poets to defend science, arguing that science can uncover nature’s most hidden wonders. For the last twenty years, Richard Dawkins has gone to great lengths to champion this line of scientific rhetoric. His Unweaving the Rainbow: Science, Delusion, and the Appetite for Wonder (1998) is a riposte against the claim that science denudes the world of meaning beyond its material substrates.1 Far from a means to disenchant the world or, as Keat’s put it, “unweave a rainbow,”2 Dawkins argues that science whets the “imagination” (16), drives us to seek new knowledge of nature, and ultimately reveals a wondrous world worthy of awe. “The feeling of awed wonder that science can give us,” he writes, “is one of the highest experiences of which the human psyche is capable. It is a deep aesthetic passion to rank with the finest that music and poetry can deliver” (x). 1 Richard Dawkins, Unweaving the Rainbow: Science, Delusion, and the Appetite for Wonder (New York: First Mariner Books, 1998). Hereafter cited parenthetically by page number(s). 2 John Keats, “Lamia,” in John Keats Selected Poems, ed. John Barnard (London: Penhuin Books, 2007), line 237. 1 Dawkins advocates a closer relationship between the poets, whom he considers the traditional source of wonder and enchantment, and scientists, whose understanding of the material world he thinks should merit aesthetic appreciation. Dawkins summarizes his vision for poets and scientists without sparing alliteration: It is my thesis that poets could better use the inspiration provided by science and that at the same time scientists must reach out to the constituency that I am identifying with, for lack of a better word, poets. It is not, of course, that science should be declaimed in verse. Simple, sober clarity will do nicely, letting the facts and the ideas speak for themselves. The poetry is in the science. (17-18) Dawkins’ “thesis,” however, is over three hundred years old. In 1667, Thomas Sprat, a founding fellow of the Royal Society, made the same argument in an attempt to establish its natural philosophy, what today we would consider “science,” as the dominant authority over knowledge of nature. Because modern science is widely acknowledged as the only reliable source for knowledge of the natural world, it is easy to forget that “science” once struggled to validate its practices in various circles of orthodox authority. Scholastics criticised Society fellows
Recommended publications
  • Selfish Gene
    THE SELFISH GENE Richard Dawkins is Charles Simonyi Professor for the Public Understanding of Science at Oxford University. Born in Nairobi of British parents, he was educated at Oxford and did his doctorate under the Nobel-prizewinning ethologist Niko Tin- bergen. From 1967 to 1969 he was an Assistant Professor at the University of California at Berkeley, returning as University Lecturer and later Reader in /oology at New College, Oxford, before becoming the first holder of the Simonyi Chair in 1995. He is a fellow of New College. The Selfish Gene (1976; second edition 1989) catapulted Richard Dawkins to fame, and remains his most famous and widely read work. It was followed by a string of bestselling books: The Extended Phenolype (1982), The Blind Watchmaker (1986), River Out of Eden (1995), Climbing Mount Improbable (1996), Unweaving the Rainbow (1998), and The Ancestor's Tale (2004). A Devil's Chaplain, a collection of his shorter writings, was published in 2003. Dawkins is a Fellow of both the Royal Society and the Royal Society of Literature. He is the recipient of numerous honours and awards, including the 1987 Royal Society of Literature Award, the Los Angeles Times Literary Prize of the same year, the 1990 Michael Faraday Award of the Royal Society, the 1994 Nakayama Prize, the 1997 International Cosmos Prize for Achievement in Human Science, the Kistler Prize in 2001, and the Shakespeare Prize in 2005. This page intentionally left blank THE SELFISH GENE RICHARD DAWKINS OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS You scratch my back, I'll ride on yours 185 better than the suckers.
    [Show full text]
  • Origins, Philosophy, and Theology
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge United States History History 12-24-1997 Jefferson's Declaration of Independence: Origins, Philosophy, and Theology Allen Jayne Click here to let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Thanks to the University of Kentucky Libraries and the University Press of Kentucky, this book is freely available to current faculty, students, and staff at the University of Kentucky. Find other University of Kentucky Books at uknowledge.uky.edu/upk. For more information, please contact UKnowledge at [email protected]. Recommended Citation Jayne, Allen, "Jefferson's Declaration of Independence: Origins, Philosophy, and Theology" (1997). United States History. 9. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/upk_united_states_history/9 Jefferson's Declaration of Independence &.0 Jefferson's Declaration of Independence &.o Origins, Philosophy and Theology Allen Jayne THE UNIVJERSITY PRJESS OJF KENTUCKY Publication of this volume was made possible in part by a grant from the National Endowment for the Humanities. Copyright © 1998 by The University Press of Kentucky Scholarly publisher for the Commonwealth, serving Bellarmine University, Berea College, Centre College of I(entucky, Eastern Kentucky University, The Filson Historical Society, Georgetown College, I(entucky Historical Society, Kentucky State University, Morehead State University, Murray State University, Northern I(entucky University, Transylvania University, University of I(entucky, University of Louisville, and Western Kentucky University. All rights reserved. Editorial and Sales Offices: The University Press of Kentucky 663 South Limestone Street, Lexington, Kentucky 40508-4008 www.kentuckypress.com Frontispiece: Thomas jefferson, a photogravure made from the original painting by Mather Brown. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data jayne, Allen.
    [Show full text]
  • The God Delusion: a Worldview Analysis Bill Martin Cornerstone Church of Lakewood Ranch - August 6, 2008
    The God Delusion: A Worldview Analysis Bill Martin Cornerstone Church of Lakewood Ranch - August 6, 2008 Richard Dawkins, Charles Simonyi Professor of the Public Understanding of Science at Oxford University “The God Delusion really marked the point where Dawkins transformed from the professor holding the Charles Simonyi Chair for the Public Understanding of Science to the celebrity fundamentalist atheist.” - Carl Packman, “An Evangelical Atheist” in New Statesman, 8.5.08 The Selfish Gene, Oxford University Press, 1976 The Extended Phenotype, Oxford University Press, 1982 The Blind Watchmaker, W. W. Norton & Company, 1986 River out of Eden, Basic Books, 1995 Climbing Mount Improbable, New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1996 Unweaving the Rainbow, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1998 A Devil's Chaplain, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2003 The Ancestor's Tale, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2004 The God Delusion, Bantam Books, 2006 / Bill’s edition: Mariner Books; 1 edition (January 16, 2008) Ad hominem - attacking an opponent's character rather than answering his argument Outline of Bill’s Talking Points 1. General Summary 2. Two Worldview Presuppositions 3. Personal Reflections and Lessons Resources: Books and Journals Aikman, David. The Delusion of Disbelief. Nashville: Tyndale House, 2008. McGrath, Alister. The Dawkins Delusion? Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2007. _______. Dawkins’ God: Genes, Memes and the Meaning of Life. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2005. Ganssle, Gregory E. “Dawkins’s Best Argument: The Case against God in The God Delusion,” Philosophia Christi , 2008,Volume 10, Number 1, pp. 39-56. Plantinga, Alvin. “The Dawkins Confusion,” Books & Culture, March/April 2007, Vol. 13, No. 2, Page 21. The Duomo Pieta (Florence, Italy) Reviews of The God Delusion “dogmatic, rambling and self-contradictory” - Andrew Brown in Prospect “he risks destroying a larger target”- Jim Holt in The New York Times “I'm forced, after reading his new book, to conclude he's actually more an amateur.” - H.
    [Show full text]
  • View / Download
    ELECTRYONE ΗΛΕΚΤΡΥΩΝΗ Xenophanes of Colophon and the Problem of Distinguishing Between Skepticism and Negative Dogmatism Dariusz Kubok University of Silesia in Katowice [email protected] ABSTRACT: Sextus Empiricus in Pyr. (I, 224, cf Diog. IX, 18) describes Xenophanes of Colophon as hupatuphos, which is to mean that he was a skeptic who did not entirely free himself of dogmatic assertions. In this paper I will try to demonstrate an alternative way of understanding hupatuphos in relation to Xenophanes. In my opinion, the interpretation according to which passages can be found in Xenophanes' writings expressing both a skeptical and negative dogmatic position is possible. Thus, this thinker may be described with the adjective hupatuphos not because he did not manage to free himself of positive dogmatism, but rather because he did not free himself of negative dogmatism. KEY-WORDS: skepticism, dogmatism, knowledge, truth, opinion, Xenophanes of Colophon In his Outlines of Pyrrhonism (PH I, 224, cf Diog. IX, 18), Sextus Empiricus invokes the opinion of Timon of Phlius describing Xenophanes of Colophon as hupatuphos ("not entirely free of tuphos,"1 "partly free of conceit,"2 "semi-free of 1 Lesher (1992) 215, n. 53. 2 Lesher (1992) 215. Xenophanes of Colophon and the Problem of Distinguishing Between Skepticism and Negative Dogmatism vanity"3), referring to the fact that both dogmatic and skeptical elements can be found in his views. Among the dogmatic elements are the belief that everything is one and the passages implying the existence of a positive (constructive) theology. Based on Sextus’ opinion some scholars see conflict in Xenophanes’ philosophy between positive dogmatic theology and skepticism.4 In this article, I will try to show that it is possible to seriously weaken this conflict, if not to do away with it entirely, and that an epistemological reading of Xenophanes may lead to more fruitful conclusions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolution of Landscape in Venetian Painting, 1475-1525
    THE EVOLUTION OF LANDSCAPE IN VENETIAN PAINTING, 1475-1525 by James Reynolds Jewitt BA in Art History, Hartwick College, 2006 BA in English, Hartwick College, 2006 MA, University of Pittsburgh, 2009 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of The Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2014 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH KENNETH P. DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by James Reynolds Jewitt It was defended on April 7, 2014 and approved by C. Drew Armstrong, Associate Professor, History of Art and Architecture Kirk Savage, Professor, History of Art and Architecture Jennifer Waldron, Associate Professor, Department of English Dissertation Advisor: Ann Sutherland Harris, Professor Emerita, History of Art and Architecture ii Copyright © by James Reynolds Jewitt 2014 iii THE EVOLUTION OF LANDSCAPE IN VENETIAN PAINTING, 1475-1525 James R. Jewitt, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2014 Landscape painting assumed a new prominence in Venetian painting between the late fifteenth to early sixteenth century: this study aims to understand why and how this happened. It begins by redefining the conception of landscape in Renaissance Italy and then examines several ambitious easel paintings produced by major Venetian painters, beginning with Giovanni Bellini’s (c.1431- 36-1516) St. Francis in the Desert (c.1475), that give landscape a far more significant role than previously seen in comparable commissions by their peers, or even in their own work. After an introductory chapter reconsidering all previous hypotheses regarding Venetian painters’ reputations as accomplished landscape painters, it is divided into four chronologically arranged case study chapters.
    [Show full text]
  • DAWKINS: the GOD DELUSION the Criticism of Religion Which Has Become a Polemic Without Limits
    DAWKINS: THE GOD DELUSION The Criticism of Religion which has Become a Polemic Without Limits JAVIER MONSERRAT Universidad Autónoma de Madrid Dawkins bases his criticism of the religious on the consideration that Darwinism eliminates all rationality regarding the belief in God. Another grand contemporary biologist, Michael Ruse, considers that Darwinism and Christianity are compatible. In his book, «Can a Darwinist be a Christian?», he responds affirmatively and offers us the following characterisation of the radicalism of Dawkins, from whom he differs radically, «He is a man who takes his atheism seriously, so much so that, in contrast, the grand Scottish philosopher of the XVIII century, David Hume (who was described memorably as “the greatest gift of God to the unbelievers”), seems moderate». The biologist Richard Dawkins holds the Charles Simonyi Chair for the «Public Knowl- edge of Science», at the University of Oxford. He studied zoology at Oxford and, after accessing academic life, he soon began to stand out within the framework of Evolution- ary Biology. His fundamental contribution consisted of contributing to the theoretical interpretation of the genes in evolutionary selection, through what we could call a «gene- tic» reading of traditional Darwinism. These ideas can be followed through the books of reference: The Selfish Gene (1976) and The Extended Phenotype (1982). For Dawkins the genetic-evolutionary mechanism is interactive with the environment as the medium are the «genes». Among other things, he introduced the concept of «meme» for the first time, therefore, the idea of «memetics» (see Breaking the Spell by Daniel Dennett). Apart from his contributions to Theoretical Biology, Dawkins became famous for his work in the scientific divulgation of Darwinism and as a critic of religion.
    [Show full text]
  • Meme (French Mème, German Mem), a Term Coined by Richard Dawkins
    This is my (slightly revised) English translation of my article “Mem”, which appeared in: J. Mittelstraß (ed.), Enzyklopädie Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie, 2nd edn, vol. 5, Stuttgart/Weimar 2013, pp. 318–24. C.v.B. Meme (French mème, German Mem), a term coined by Richard Dawkins in analogy to “gene”, intended to desig- nate pieces of culture (‘units of cultural transmission’ or ‘units of imitation’; Dawkins 1976, p. 206) which are subject to a Darwinian process of evolution. 2 In The Selfish Gene (1976, 1989), Dawkins tries among Dawkins: Generalized theory of evolution other things to give a general characterization of the phe- nomenon of evolution by natural selection. This charac- terization is intended to be general in the sense that it is independent of particular ‘substrates’ like, say, organic molecules or (populations of) organisms. What is essential for the evolution of complex struc- Replicators tures by natural selection, according to Dawkins, is the existence of ‘replicators’, i.e., objects which (in a suitable environment) generate copies of themselves. Replicators which are better able to multiply than others consequently spread more strongly than these do. In view of the result- ing exponential growth (and the more so as the available resources of space, energy, materials etc. will ordinarily be limited) better replicators will, in the course of not too many copying-‘generations’, drive worse ones to numerical marginality or even obliteration. If such displacement of old variants by superior new ones takes place again and again over a protracted period of time, eventually replica- tors with extremely sophisticated mechanisms of action will hold the stage.
    [Show full text]
  • The New Organon: Or True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature
    The New Organon: or True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature Francis Bacon Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported between brackets in normal-sized type.—‘Organon’ is the conventional title for the collection of logical works by Aristotle, a body of doctrine that Bacon aimed to replace. His title Novum Organum could mean ‘The New Organon’ or more modestly ‘A New Organon’; the tone of the writing in this work points to the definite article. First launched: January 2005 The New Organon Francis Bacon Contents PREFACE 1 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 1–774 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 78–130 24 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 1–25 48 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 26–43 75 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 44–52 102 The New Organon Francis Bacon PREFACE PREFACE Those who have taken it on themselves to lay down the thinking and continuous mental effort. law of nature as something that has already been discovered My method is hard to practice but easy to explain.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Cicero's Eclectic Probabilism
    Revista Archai ISSN: 1984-249X Universidade de Brasília Skvirsky, Alexandre Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Revista Archai, no. 27, e02705, 2019 Universidade de Brasília DOI: https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=586161659005 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System Redalyc More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America and the Caribbean, Spain and Journal's webpage in redalyc.org Portugal Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative AS ORIGENS DO PENSAMENTO OCIDENTAL THE ORIGINS OF WESTERN THOUGHT ARTIGO I ARTICLE Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Alexandre Skvirsky i https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9508-1023 [email protected] i Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio de Janeiro – Rio de Janeiro – RJ – Brasil SKVIRSKY, A. (2019). Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica. Archai 27, e02705. Abstract: The objective is to show the peculiar way in which Cicero’s philosophical thinking is original and distances itself from the main representatives of the New Academy: the Roman thinker does not practice epoche, nor does he assign any special role to it in his thought. Instead, Cicero introduces the concept of doubt to characterize his own way of thinking. Keywords: Cicero, epoche, doubt, skepticism, probabilism. https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 [1] 2 Rev. Archai, n. 27, Brasília, 2019, e02705. Cicero’s philosophical contributions have often been downplayed, even by himself. His importance as a translator and divulger of philosophy among the Romans frequently overshadows his originality as a philosopher.
    [Show full text]
  • Color for Philosophers: Unweaving the Rainbow
    c o N T E N T 5 Foreword by Arthur Danto ix xv Preface xix Introduction I Color Perception and Science The physical causes of color 1 The camera and the eye 7 Perceiving lightness and darkness 19 26 Chromatic vision Chromatic response 36 The structure of phenomenal hues 40 Object metamerism, adaptation, and contrast 45 Some mechanisms of chromatic perception 52 II The Ontology of Color Objectivism 59 Standard conditions 67 Normal observers 76 Constancy and crudity 82 Ch romatic democracy 91 Sense data as color bearers 96 Materialist reduction and the illusion of color 109 III Phenomenology and Physiology THE RELATlONS OF COLORS TO EACH OTHER 113 T he resemblances of colors 113 The incompatibilities of colors 121 Deeper problems 127 OTHER MINDS 134 Spectral inversions and asymmetries 134 vii CONTENTS I nternalism and externalism 142 Other colors, other minds 145 COLOR LANGUAGE 155 Foci 155 The evolution of color categories 165 Boundaries and indeterminacy 169 Establishing boundaries 182 Color Plates following page 88 Appendix: Land's Retinex Theory of Color Vision 187 Notes 195 Glossary of Technical Terms 209 Further Reading 216 Bibliography 217 Acknowledgments 234 Indexes 237 viii F o R E w o R D Very few today still believe that philosophy is a disease of language and that its deliverances, due to disturbances of the grammatical un­ conscious, are neither true nor false but nonsense. But the fact re­ mains that, very often, philosophical theory stands to positive knowledge roughly in the relationship in which hysteria is said to stand to anatomical truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Biology Transition to a Level
    Transition to Advanced Level Biology Contents: I. Reading List II. Tasks III. Base Line Test 1 Reading List The books below are all popular science books and great for extending your understanding of Biology. Richard Dawkins: The Selfish Gene The Blind Watchmaker. Unweaving the Rainbow Climbing Mount Improbable The Ancestor’s Tale Steve Jones: Y: The Descent of Men In the Blood: God, Genes and Destiny Almost Like a Whale: The 'Origin of Species' Updated The Language of the genes Matt Ridley: Genome: The Autobiography of a Species in 23 Chapters The Red Queen: Sex and the Evolution of Human Nature The Language of Genes Francis Crick: Discoverer of the Genetic Code Nature Via Nurture: Genes, Experience and What Makes Us Human James Watson: DNA: The Secret of Life The Double Helix: Personal Account of the Discovery of the Structure of DNA Lewis Thomas: The Lives of a Cell: Notes of a Biology Watcher. The Medusa and the Snail: More Notes of a Biology Watcher Barry Gibb: The Rough Guide to the Brain (Rough Guides Reference Titles) Charles Darwin: The origin of species Armand Marie Leroi: Mutants: On the Form, Varieties and Errors of the Human Body David S. Goodsell: The Machinery of Life Ernst Mayr: This Is Biology: The Science of the Living World George C. Williams: Plan and Purpose in Nature Steve Pinker: The Language Instinct Edward O Wilson: The Diversity of Life Richard Leaky: The Origin of Humankind Bill Bryson: A Short History of Nearly Everything Oliver Sachs: The Man Who Mistook His Wife For A Hat Daniel Chamovitz: What A Plant Knows 2 Websites 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Science As Aesthetic Device in Nineteenth-Century American Literature
    SCIENCE AS AESTHETIC DEVICE IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY AMERICAN LITERATURE by CATHERINE Q. FORSA Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of English CASE WESTERN RESERVE UNIVERSITY May, 2016 2 CASE WESTERN RESERVE UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF GRADUATE STUDIES We hereby approve the dissertation of Catherine Q. Forsa candidate for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy* Committee Chair Michael W. Clune Committee Member Athena Vrettos Committee Member William Marling Committee Member Peter Shulman Date of Defense February 12, 2016 *We also certify that written approval has been obtained for any proprietary material contained therein. 3 Table of Contents Acknowledgements…………………………………………………………………… 4 Abstract……………………………………………………………………………….. 5 Introduction Science as Aesthetic Device in Nineteenth-Century American Literature…………… 7 Chapter 1 Poetry after Photography: Poe’s Light Effects………………………………………. 30 Chapter 2 A Formal—Thermal—Feeling Comes: Dickinson’s Poetic Temperatures…………. 57 Chapter 3 Technologies of Vision in Melville’s Fiction………………………………………... 75 Chapter 4 Actual Awakenings and the Science of Sleep in Kate Chopin’s Fiction……………. 103 Conclusion…………………………………………………………………………... 123 Works Cited…………………………………………………………………………. 127 4 Acknowledgements I thank Michael Clune for his guidance throughout my graduate studies. I also thank Athena Vrettos, William Marling, and Peter Shulman for their valuable advice on this project. I thank Kurt Koenigsberger and Kimberly Emmons for their help and guidance. I thank my mother, father, and brothers for all of their love, support, and encouragement. I thank my colleagues and friends for making my time at CWRU a true joy. I am fortunate to have received generous financial support from Case Western Reserve University’s College of Arts and Sciences Dissertation Fellowship and the English Department’s Adrian – Salomon Dissertation Fellowship.
    [Show full text]