Origins, Philosophy, and Theology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Origins, Philosophy, and Theology University of Kentucky UKnowledge United States History History 12-24-1997 Jefferson's Declaration of Independence: Origins, Philosophy, and Theology Allen Jayne Click here to let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Thanks to the University of Kentucky Libraries and the University Press of Kentucky, this book is freely available to current faculty, students, and staff at the University of Kentucky. Find other University of Kentucky Books at uknowledge.uky.edu/upk. For more information, please contact UKnowledge at [email protected]. Recommended Citation Jayne, Allen, "Jefferson's Declaration of Independence: Origins, Philosophy, and Theology" (1997). United States History. 9. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/upk_united_states_history/9 Jefferson's Declaration of Independence &.0 Jefferson's Declaration of Independence &.o Origins, Philosophy and Theology Allen Jayne THE UNIVJERSITY PRJESS OJF KENTUCKY Publication of this volume was made possible in part by a grant from the National Endowment for the Humanities. Copyright © 1998 by The University Press of Kentucky Scholarly publisher for the Commonwealth, serving Bellarmine University, Berea College, Centre College of I(entucky, Eastern Kentucky University, The Filson Historical Society, Georgetown College, I(entucky Historical Society, Kentucky State University, Morehead State University, Murray State University, Northern I(entucky University, Transylvania University, University of I(entucky, University of Louisville, and Western Kentucky University. All rights reserved. Editorial and Sales Offices: The University Press of Kentucky 663 South Limestone Street, Lexington, Kentucky 40508-4008 www.kentuckypress.com Frontispiece: Thomas jefferson, a photogravure made from the original painting by Mather Brown. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data jayne, Allen. jefferson's Declaration of independence: origins, philosophy, and theology / Allen jayne. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references (p. ) and index. ISBN 0-8131-2017-9 (cloth: acid-free recycled paper) ISBN 0-8131-9003-7 (pbk. : acid-free recycled paper) 1. United States. Declaration of Independence. 1. Title. KF4506.j39 1998 97-33157 973.3'13-dc21 ISBN-13: 978-0-8131-9003-7 (pbk. : acid-free recycled paper) This book is printed on acid-free recycled paper meeting the requirements of the American National Standard for Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials. Manufactured in the United States of America ~......~. ~ Member of the Association of ~~.• American University Presses To Linda, Andrew, and Catherine &.(!) This page intentionally left blank Contents Preface Xl Introduction 1 1. The Theological Context 9 2. Bolingbroke and the Enlightenment 19 3. Locke and the Declaration 41 4. Kames and the Moral Sense 62 5. 0 bstacles to Reason 87 6. Self-Evident Truths 109 7. Religious Freedom 139 Conclusion 168 Appendix: The Declaration of Independence 175 Notes 179 Bibliography 217 Index of Persons 232 Index of Subjects 240 This page intentionally left blank A recollection of our former vassalage in religion and civil government, will unite the zeal of every heart, and the energy of every hand, to preserve that independence in both which, under the favor of Heaven, a disinterested devotion to the public cause first achieved, and a disinterested sacrifice of private interests will now maintain. -Thomas Jefferson, 17 October 1808 This page intentionally left blank Preface This book is based on my work in the history of ideas at Cambridge University. Some of the research, however, was done earlier, when I did not consider its relevance to practical life or intend to pursue gradu­ ate studies. At that time, my love for the study of ideas was particu­ larly keen if they were abstract. Now, I find the material in this book relevant to current life in the United States, and perhaps other places, especially where it concerns the question ofwhether the political power of a government should be used to impose religion on its people. This was a burning issue in jefferson's time, as it is today. Since there are many in the United States who fervently believe we should use gov­ ernmental power in support of religious values, and many who just as fervently believe we should not, the heat from this issue is likely to be felt for some time. If he were here today, jefferson would support the latter group; he was instrumental in the passage of both state and federal laws that kept religion out of politics and politics out of religion. This book explains why he acted as he did and why he believed that all people in the United States, including those who support the use of political power in matters of religion, would benefit from the separation of state and church. I find jefferson's thinking in this respect fundamen­ tally sound. Indeed, I cannot help speculating-given the religious authoritarianism and sectarian bigotry that existed in the colonies in 1776 and have not been altogether eradicated today-that without the efforts of jefferson and others, especially Madison, to establish the First Amendment to the Constitution, we could have become an­ other Bosnia, Northern Ireland, or Middle East. In the eighteenth cen­ tury, as a keen student of history, jefferson saw law as a means to prevent sectarian disputes from erupting into persecution, strife, and war as they had done on a massive scale in sixteenth- and seventeenth­ century France and seventeenth-century Germany, where Catholics and Protestants killed masses of people during their sectarian wars. Xli Preface Since Jefferson did more than any other Founding Father to shape and articulate the ideas and ideals upon which American civilization is based, it seems logical to judge him by the positive or negative im­ pact of those ideas and ideals. Yet there are those who argue that we should judge him by his character as a man and by twentieth-century standards of what is good despite the fact that others have written on the injustice and absurdity of judging historical figures by today's stan­ dards. Indeed, there are those who even suggest that we should ignore his ideas or scorn him because he allegedly was too passive in his efforts to eradicate slavery and, to a great extent, isolated in his racist views. The charge of passiveness is ironic. Criticized for this more than any Founding Father, some of whom were completely passive and not criticized, Jefferson was the most active, making several legis­ lative attempts to outlaw slavery in America. Although his efforts were unsuccessful, they did inspire the Northwest Ordinance, which permanently eliminated slavery from half of the United States. More­ over, Jefferson's racist idea of freeing slaves but having them live in separate territory was not confined to him or a few like him but was favored by many late-eighteenth- and nineteenth-century abolition­ ists, including Abraham Lincoln. Yet even if the allegations of these ad hominem and ad tu quoque arguments were true, they have no relation to the truth or goodness ofJefferson's legacy of ideas and ideals. Socrates pointed out this prin­ ciple of logic with a rebuke in Phaedrus: "The men of old ... deemed that if they heard the truth even from 'oak or rock,' it was enough for them; whereas you seem to consider not whether a thing is or is not true, but who the speaker is and from what country the tale comes." I am deeply indebted to three persons in connection with this book. First among these is Bhek Pati Sinha, who has been a close friend of my family for many years. During that time his generosity in sharing his vast knowledge of ideas kindled and sustained my interest in this subject. In fact, it was he who, during a visit to Monticello, when I expressed an interest in the ideas and ideals of the third president of the United States, suggested that I do research on Jefferson. Second among these three is my wife, Linda. She gave me continuous support during this endeavor, which on many occasions meant sacrificing her own pleasure and convenience. The third member of this trinity is Richard Tuck, my Ph.D. supervisor at Cambridge. His suggestions and criticism helped me avoid many errors. I am also indebted to J.R. Preface Xlii Pole of Oxford and Mark Goldie of Cambridge for their helpful com­ ments and criticisms. And to the staff of the rare books reading room of the excellent University Library of Cambridge-where I sometimes found myself reading books by those who influenced Jefferson in the same editions as he owned or recommended-I express my gratitude for their courtesy and efficiency. This page intentionally left blank Introduction Ralph Barton Perry's comment "The history of American democracy is a gradual realization, too slow for some and too rapid for others, of the implications of the Declaration of Independence" illustrates the importance America has ascribed to the Declaration's succinctly ex­ pressed ideals.1 Given that importance, the question arises, What are those ideals, especially as Thomas jefferson, the principal author of the Declaration, intended them to be? Answering this question has proved difficult for scholars, partly because jefferson, by his own ad­ mission, neither originated the ideas and ideals contained in the first American document nor clearly explained where he got them.2 Since knowledge of the source of the ideas jefferson placed in the Declaration is important to understanding its ideals, much has been written on this subject. Yet the images of the Declaration's principles remain confused and blurred, for there have been diverse opinions as to who the thinkers and philosophers were who contributed to the Declaration via jefferson, not to mention different interpretations of particular contributors. So diverse are the opinions of scholars who have written on the political theory of Thomas jefferson and the Dec­ laration of Independence over much of this century that support can be found for virtually every contemporary political ideology within this vast array of literature, as a few samples will show.
Recommended publications
  • View / Download
    ELECTRYONE ΗΛΕΚΤΡΥΩΝΗ Xenophanes of Colophon and the Problem of Distinguishing Between Skepticism and Negative Dogmatism Dariusz Kubok University of Silesia in Katowice [email protected] ABSTRACT: Sextus Empiricus in Pyr. (I, 224, cf Diog. IX, 18) describes Xenophanes of Colophon as hupatuphos, which is to mean that he was a skeptic who did not entirely free himself of dogmatic assertions. In this paper I will try to demonstrate an alternative way of understanding hupatuphos in relation to Xenophanes. In my opinion, the interpretation according to which passages can be found in Xenophanes' writings expressing both a skeptical and negative dogmatic position is possible. Thus, this thinker may be described with the adjective hupatuphos not because he did not manage to free himself of positive dogmatism, but rather because he did not free himself of negative dogmatism. KEY-WORDS: skepticism, dogmatism, knowledge, truth, opinion, Xenophanes of Colophon In his Outlines of Pyrrhonism (PH I, 224, cf Diog. IX, 18), Sextus Empiricus invokes the opinion of Timon of Phlius describing Xenophanes of Colophon as hupatuphos ("not entirely free of tuphos,"1 "partly free of conceit,"2 "semi-free of 1 Lesher (1992) 215, n. 53. 2 Lesher (1992) 215. Xenophanes of Colophon and the Problem of Distinguishing Between Skepticism and Negative Dogmatism vanity"3), referring to the fact that both dogmatic and skeptical elements can be found in his views. Among the dogmatic elements are the belief that everything is one and the passages implying the existence of a positive (constructive) theology. Based on Sextus’ opinion some scholars see conflict in Xenophanes’ philosophy between positive dogmatic theology and skepticism.4 In this article, I will try to show that it is possible to seriously weaken this conflict, if not to do away with it entirely, and that an epistemological reading of Xenophanes may lead to more fruitful conclusions.
    [Show full text]
  • The New Organon: Or True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature
    The New Organon: or True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature Francis Bacon Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported between brackets in normal-sized type.—‘Organon’ is the conventional title for the collection of logical works by Aristotle, a body of doctrine that Bacon aimed to replace. His title Novum Organum could mean ‘The New Organon’ or more modestly ‘A New Organon’; the tone of the writing in this work points to the definite article. First launched: January 2005 The New Organon Francis Bacon Contents PREFACE 1 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 1–774 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 78–130 24 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 1–25 48 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 26–43 75 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 44–52 102 The New Organon Francis Bacon PREFACE PREFACE Those who have taken it on themselves to lay down the thinking and continuous mental effort. law of nature as something that has already been discovered My method is hard to practice but easy to explain.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Cicero's Eclectic Probabilism
    Revista Archai ISSN: 1984-249X Universidade de Brasília Skvirsky, Alexandre Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Revista Archai, no. 27, e02705, 2019 Universidade de Brasília DOI: https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=586161659005 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System Redalyc More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America and the Caribbean, Spain and Journal's webpage in redalyc.org Portugal Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative AS ORIGENS DO PENSAMENTO OCIDENTAL THE ORIGINS OF WESTERN THOUGHT ARTIGO I ARTICLE Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica Alexandre Skvirsky i https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9508-1023 [email protected] i Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio de Janeiro – Rio de Janeiro – RJ – Brasil SKVIRSKY, A. (2019). Doubt and dogmatism in Cicero’s Academica. Archai 27, e02705. Abstract: The objective is to show the peculiar way in which Cicero’s philosophical thinking is original and distances itself from the main representatives of the New Academy: the Roman thinker does not practice epoche, nor does he assign any special role to it in his thought. Instead, Cicero introduces the concept of doubt to characterize his own way of thinking. Keywords: Cicero, epoche, doubt, skepticism, probabilism. https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_27_5 [1] 2 Rev. Archai, n. 27, Brasília, 2019, e02705. Cicero’s philosophical contributions have often been downplayed, even by himself. His importance as a translator and divulger of philosophy among the Romans frequently overshadows his originality as a philosopher.
    [Show full text]
  • Bacon's Poetry and Shakespeare's
    No “Idle Fancy:” The Imagination’s Work in Poetry and Natural Philosophy from Sidney to Sprat by Jacqueline L. Cowan Department of English Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Leonard Tennenhouse, Supervisor ___________________________ Andrew Janiak ___________________________ Maureen Quilligan ___________________________ Charlotte Sussman Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English in the Graduate School of Duke University 2015 i v ABSTRACT No “Idle Fancy:” The Imagination’s Work in Poetry and Natural Philosophy from Sidney to Sprat by Jacqueline L. Cowan Department of English Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Leonard Tennenhouse, Supervisor ___________________________ Andrew Janiak ___________________________ Maureen Quilligan ___________________________ Charlotte Sussman An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English in the Graduate School of Duke University 2015 i v Copyright by Jacqueline L. Cowan 2015 Abstract When debating the structure of the cosmos, Raphael delivers to Adam perhaps Milton’s most famous line: “be lowly wise.” With the promise to “justify the ways of God to men,” Milton does not limit man’s knowledge to base matters, but reclaims the heights of “other worlds” for the poet. Over the course of the seventeenth century, the natural philosophers’ material explanations of the natural order were slowly gaining authority over other sources of knowledge, the poets prime among them. My dissertation takes up the competing early modern claims to knowledge that Milton lays down for Adam. I argue that natural philosophy, what today we call “science,” emerged as the dominant authority over knowledge by appropriating the poet’s imagination.
    [Show full text]
  • A Companion to Rationalism
    A Companion to Rationalism i ACTA01 1 14/9/05, 12:03 PM Blackwell Companions to Philosophy This outstanding student reference series offers a comprehensive and authoritative survey of philosophy as a whole. Written by today’s leading philosophers, each volume provides lucid and engaging coverage of the key figures, terms, topics, and problems of the field. Taken together, the volumes provide the ideal basis for course use, representing an unparalleled work of reference for students and specialists alike. Already published in the series: A Companion to Business Ethics Edited by Robert E. Frederick The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, Second Edition A Companion to the Philosophy of Science Edited by Nicholas Bunnin and Eric Edited by W. H. Newton-Smith Tsui-James A Companion to Environmental Philosophy A Companion to Ethics Edited by Dale Jamieson Edited by Peter Singer A Companion to Analytic Philosophy A Companion to Aesthetics Edited by A. P. Martinich and David Sosa Edited by David Cooper A Companion to Genethics A Companion to Epistemology Edited by Justine Burley and John Harris Edited by Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa A Companion to Philosophical Logic A Companion to Contemporary Political Edited by Dale Jacquette Philosophy A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy Edited by Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit Edited by Steven Nadler A Companion to Philosophy of Mind A Companion to Philosophy in the Edited by Samuel Guttenplan Middle Ages A Companion to Metaphysics Edited by Jorge J. E. Gracia and Timothy B. Edited by Jaegwon Kim and Ernest Sosa Noone A Companion to Philosophy of Law and A Companion to African-American Legal Theory Philosophy Edited by Dennis Patterson Edited by Tommy L.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 for the Various Models of Scientific Method See Mcmullin,E., 'The
    ISSN 2045-5577 ORDER: GOD’S, MAN’S AND NATURE’S Ordering Knowledge by Methodical Doubt: Francis Bacon's Constructive Scepticism Eleonora Montuschi Methodical doubt is usually associated with Descartes. However, it is with Francis Bacon that its function and scope are first recognized – as a preliminary stage in the attainment of knowledge, and as an epistemological tool (a rule) for achieving true knowledge. In this paper, I follow the various steps of construction and use of Baconian doubt as it appears in the first book of the New Organon. I will argue that Bacon - in distancing himself from traditional scepticism – will come to conceive methodical doubt not only as a procedure for renovating knowledge, but more specifically as a prescriptive condition for identifying what 'mind' is required to pursue the aim of renovating knowledge. 1. The new idea of scientific method The model for methodical procedure from Aristotle to Descartes, was demonstration.1 In a demonstration a conclusion proceeds from premises by means of deductive rules of inference. The truth of the premises can be given, as in Aristotle, by 'intuition' (epagogé); and the truth of the conclusion derives by necessity (deductive inference) from the truth of the premises. It is this conception of method, which had dominated scientific knowledge for almost two thousand years, that Bacon and the nascent experimental tradition of the seventeenth century made the target of their fiercest criticism. The new methodologists retained the view that a good method must make use of a compelling technique for assessing truth. They also agreed that nothing was more compelling than logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Education from Montaigne´S Perspective Within the Renaissance Context
    Acta Scientiarum http://www.uem.br/acta ISSN printed: 2178-5198 ISSN on-line: 2178-5201 Doi: 10.4025/actascieduc.v38i4.26518 , Education from montaigne´s perspective within the renaissance context Gustavo Araújo Batista Universidade de Uberaba, Av. Nenê Sabino, 1801, 38055-500, Bairro Universitário, Uberaba, Minas Gerais, Brazil. *Author for correspondence. E-mail: [email protected] ABSTRACT. Michel Eyquem de Montaigne’s (1533-1592) philosophy foregrounds a pedagogy based on intellectual skepticism and moral stoicism. Since the acquisition of definitive or unquestionable knowledge is impossible, there would be the unending search for something that would be somewhat more reliable or probable. Similarly, it would be mandatory to educate the subject within a virtuous conduct to do one´s duty. Current article is an attempt to approach philosophy and education and brings to the fore Montaigne´s main topics within a review of his philosophy and his ideas on education, within the historical context (Renaissance) and his most relevant work (Essays). Results show that Montaigne´s intellectual skepticism and moral stoicism ward off possible mistakes, misconceptions, errors and illusions caused by concepts that do not question to what extent knowledge is reliable and ignore the importance of the formation of human behavior. It is expected that these considerations on Montaigne’s philosophical and educational ideas may trigger discussions on the theoretical foundation of education . Keywords: Skepticism, Stoicism, Philosophy, Education. A educação segundo a perspectiva de montaigne no âmbito do renascimento RESUMO. A filosofia de Michel Eyquem de Montaigne (1533-1592) oferece a possibilidade de uma pedagogia pautada no ceticismo intelectual e no estoicismo moral, pois, segundo ele, sendo impossível a aquisição do conhecimento definitivo ou inquestionável, restaria apenas a busca incessante por algo que seja, ao menos, um pouco mais confiável ou provável, da mesma forma que seria imperativo educar o indivíduo para uma conduta virtuosa e implacável no cumprimento do dever.
    [Show full text]
  • The New Organon Or: True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature
    The New Organon or: True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature Francis Bacon Copyright ©2010–2015 All rights reserved. Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Any four-point ellipsis. indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported between brackets in normal-sized type. ‘Organon’ is the conventional title for the collection of logical works by Aristotle, a body of doctrine that Bacon aimed to replace. His title Novum Organum could mean ‘The New Organon’ or more modestly ‘A New Organon’; the tone of the writing in this work points to the definite article. First launched: January 2005 Last amended: May 2007 Contents PREFACE 1 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 1–774 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 78–130 24 The New Organon Francis Bacon PREFACE PREFACE Those who have taken it on themselves to lay down the thinking and continuous mental effort. law of nature as something that has already been discovered My method is hard to practice but easy to explain. I and understood, whether they have spoken in simple confi- propose to •establish degrees of certainty, to •retain ·the dence or in a spirit of professional posturing, have done great evidence of· the senses subject to certain constraints, but harm to philosophy and the sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Jameses at Play: a Tractation on the Comparison of Laws†
    PIERRE LEGRAND* Jameses at Play: A Tractation on the Comparison of Laws† Withstanding trendyism and its abrupt brevities, shunning the contemporary’s brisk cadences, this Article compares two salient com- parativisms-at-law. While it argues that these models are epistemi- cally irreconcilable in significant respects—and that one approach is emphatically more interpretively empowering than the other—it also claims that neither strategy is able to escape the play of the text. The inevitability of comparativism as play means that every enunciation of foreign law and every comparison-at-law must stand as the compara- tivist’s invention, as an exercise in self-portraiture also, as an egotrope. “The world is utterly, thoroughly legal, as you may not know it.” —Thomas Bernhard1 “Let us grant the freedom to trace.” —Roland Barthes2 “And, no doubt, that is reading: to rewrite the text of the work directly from the text of our life.” —Roland Barthes3 Beyond the fact that it answers a desire for personal emancipation or déniaisement,4 that it provides primordial terms “enabl[ing] [one] to ask vital questions,” and that, allowing for manifestations of insur- mountable ethnocentrism, it “dislodge[s] and liberate[s] one from one’s * Professor of Law at the Sorbonne, Paris; Visiting Professor, Northwestern University Pritzker School of Law, Chicago; Distinguished Visiting Professor, University of San Diego School of Law. † http://dx.doi/org/10.1093/ajcl/avx018 1. THOMAS BERNHARD, Ist es eine Komödie? Ist es eine Tragödie? (1967), reprinted in ERZÄHLUNGEN 74 (2001). 2. ROLAND BARTHES, LE BRUISSEMENT DE LA LANGUE 57 (1984).
    [Show full text]
  • Peirce Edition Project
    November 2014 Peirce Edition Project Writings of Charles S. Peirce A Chronological Edition COMBINED INDEX: Volumes 1 to 6, and 8 This comprehensive index combines the entries of the seven volumes of the Writings of Charles S. Peirce so far published by the Peirce Edition Project. Main entries have been made to a large extent uniform throughout (especially regarding the spelling of proper names, which sometimes varies in distinct volume indexes). The depth of indexing varies from volume to volume according to the methods of analysis and syntax habits of different indexers. No attempt has been made to improve this state of things, so that there are inevitable inconsistencies. The Peirce Project thanks Eric Herod and Mark Fendry for their assistance in scanning the indexes, cleaning up the result, and combining the indexes. Index combination and layout was done using LiveIndexer 2.0, a versatile and powerful back-of-the-book indexing software created by André De Tienne, Peirce Project Director and General Editor, initially for indexing the volumes of the edition. LiveIndexer 2.0 can be purchased from the Peirce Edition Project (Mac or Windows), all sales proceeds going to the Project. Contact LiveIndexer ([email protected]) for complete information. The index is sorted alphabetically by first meaningful word according to the Chicago Manual of Style’s rules (16th ed.) for letter-by-letter sorting. Page numbers are sorted numerically by volume, and boldfaced volume numbers precede the first instance of their respective volume page numbers. The index of each volume initially covered the introduction and all Peirce texts.
    [Show full text]
  • Bacon's Doctrine of Idols
    Bacon's Doctrine of Idols Author: Jonathan Joseph Rosse Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/bc-ir:104937 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2015 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Political Science BACON’S DOCTRINE OF IDOLS A Thesis By Jonathan Joseph Rosse submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts December 2015 © copyright by JONATHAN JOSEPH ROSSE 2015 Abstract The following sketch attempts to look at the ways in which Francis Bacon helped to bring about the modern age by presenting a system of skepticism, in the form of his doctrine of idols, which initiated the break away from classical philosophy and Christian theology and made room for a new, secular science. By looking at Bacon’s peculiar and esoteric writing style as well as his detractors’ assessments of him, I show not only what they got wrong about Bacon but also and more importantly that many of their criticisms of Bacon’s role in the history of science and philosophy depend on his very success in brining about a reformation of men’s minds. I show how far-reaching his doctrine of the idols is and how it initiated the trend in modern philosophy to create systems of skepticisms that are based on human reason’s self-criticism. Finally, I show how Bacon’s doctrine of idols led to his refutations not only of philosophical doctrines but of Christian theology as well.
    [Show full text]
  • The New Organon: Or True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature
    The New Organon: or True Directions Concerning the Interpretation of Nature Francis Bacon Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported between brackets in normal-sized type.—‘Organon’ is the conventional title for the collection of logical works by Aristotle, a body of doctrine that Bacon aimed to replace. His title Novum Organum could mean ‘The New Organon’ or more modestly ‘A New Organon’; the tone of the writing in this work points to the definite article. First launched: January 2005 The New Organon Francis Bacon Contents PREFACE 1 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 1–774 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 1: 78–130 24 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 1–25 48 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 26–43 75 APHORISMS CONCERNING THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE: BOOK 2: 44–52 102 The New Organon Francis Bacon PREFACE PREFACE Those who have taken it on themselves to lay down the thinking and continuous mental effort. law of nature as something that has already been discovered My method is hard to practice but easy to explain.
    [Show full text]