Moral Evaluation in Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
MORAL EVALUATION IN ALBERT THE GREAT AND THOMAS AQUINAS A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by David William Zettel December 2018 © 2018 David William Zettel ABSTRACT Moral Evaluation in Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas David William Zettel Cornell University 2018 Two different methods for morally evaluating actions can be found in Albert the Great's works. The first, which I call the stages theory, requires that an act be evaluated in three stages: 1) its generic quality, or type; 2) its circumstances; and 3) whether it proceeds from virtue or vice. According to this theory, an act might be generically good, but done badly, or generically bad, but done well. The second method is an all-or-nothing principle. It requires that an act be good in each of a number of ways in order for it to be good overall. I call it the Dionysian principle, after pseudo-Dionysius, who stated that good is from a single complete cause, while bad is from any particular defect. It is not clear how these two methods go together, and at least one formulation of the Dionysian principle appears to be inconsistent with the stages theory. Thomas Aquinas, who studied under Albert, resolves the tension between the two methods by rejecting the stages theory and embracing the Dionysian principle. I argue that this disagreement between Albert and Aquinas leads them to describe certain hard cases very differently. Albert can maintain that agents in resolvable moral dilemmas perform a bad action, although it is the right action in the circumstances; Aquinas cannot, but rather claims that the agent in an apparent dilemma does not in fact perform the act he appears to perform. Finally, I draw out these differences by comparing both the stages theory and the Dionysian principle to certain Stoic antecedents. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH David Zettel obtained a BA in philosophy from the University of Waterloo in 2006. In 2008 he obtained an MA in philosophy from the University of Ottawa. His master's thesis was on Thomas Aquinas in the virtue of courage. In 2018 he obtained his PhD in philosophy from Cornell University. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS It is with deep gratitude that I wish to acknowledge the people who made this dissertation possible. Scott MacDonald, Charles Brittain, and Tad Brennan generously served as my committee, providing invaluable comments and advice. Andrew Chignell, now at Princeton, was on my committee for most of my time as a student at Cornell, and I am grateful for his comments and guidance, especially at the earlier stages of the project. I am particularly indebted to Bruno Tremblay and David Twetten, who provided crucial suggestions and encouragement. Pamela Hannah in the Cornell philosophy department helped me through the maze of administrative requirements needed to complete my degree. My wife's parents, Ustine and Ophelia, were an enormous help, looking after our family and giving me time to write. My parents, Bob and Monica, have supported me throughout my studies; I would not have made it to this point without them. Clara and Anna, my two young daughters, having filled my life with joy, also inspired me to persevere in my writing. I dedicate this dissertation to my wife, Candida Jane Maria Ustine. Her love, support, and unwavering belief in me are a tremendous and altogether unmerited gift. என் அன்பே, என் மணமகபே, உன் அன்ꯁ 뮿க அழகான鏁. Table of Contents Introduction ......................................................................................................................... 1 Historical Background ........................................................................................................ 6 Albert's Life and Works ...................................................................................................... 9 Chapter 1: Generic Goodness ........................................................................................... 14 1.A Generic Good before Albert ................................................................................... 14 1.B Generic Goodness in the DNB ............................................................................... 24 1.C Generic Goodness in the SDB ................................................................................ 34 1.D Generic Goodness in Albert's Sentences Commentary .......................................... 39 1.E Generic Goodness in Super Ethica and Ethica....................................................... 48 Chapter 2: Moral Circumstances ...................................................................................... 52 2.A Albert's Account of Moral Circumstances in DNB and SDB ................................ 53 2.B The Dionysian Principle in the SDB ...................................................................... 60 2.C Intention in DNB and SDB .................................................................................... 61 2.D Moral Circumstances and Intention in Albert's Sentences Commentary ............... 74 2.E Moral Circumstances in Super Ethica .................................................................. 104 2.F Moral Circumstances in Ethica ............................................................................ 119 2.G Generic Goodness and Moral Circumstances in Summa Theologiae .................. 134 2.H The Dionysian Principle in Summa Theologiae ................................................... 143 Chapter 3. The Stages Theory vs. the Dionysian Principle ............................................ 148 3.A. Comparing the Stages Theory and the Dionysian Principle ............................... 149 3.B Comparing Albert to Thomas Aquinas ................................................................ 162 3.C Generic Goodness and the Dionysian Principle in Aquinas' Sentences Commentary ..................................................................................................................................... 165 3.D Aquinas' Mature Theory ...................................................................................... 171 Interior and Exterior Acts ....................................................................................... 172 Generic Goodness ................................................................................................... 177 Moral Circumstances .............................................................................................. 181 The Dionysian Principle ......................................................................................... 184 Moral Indifference in Albert and Aquinas .............................................................. 190 3.E Revisiting the Judge who Condemns an Innocent Man ....................................... 195 3.F. Stoic Connections ................................................................................................ 205 Conclusion ...................................................................................................................... 218 Bibliography ................................................................................................................... 223 1 Introduction Albert the Great's ethics is an ethics of virtue. In his two earliest ethical treatises, De natura boni (DNB) and Summa de bono (SDB), however, Albert begins by discussing goodness in its widest sense before proceeding to discuss moral goodness, beginning with the features of good and bad actions. This is not accidental; Albert builds his theory of the virtues on his metaphysics of action. As we shall see, Albert thinks that human actions are structured in a particular way, and that the moral evaluation of an action requires taking into account the different parts of that structure. Consider two important questions about the moral act: 1) "What shall I do?" and 2) "Was this action right or wrong?" The first question provides action guidance. The second gives action assessment: was this action right or wrong? Was it praiseworthy? Merely permissible, or supererogatory? Yet these two questions, although related, are distinct. A moral theory might direct an agent to perform an action while denying that the action is right, as for example in the case of a resolvable, self-imposed moral dilemma.1 Now Albert does not distinguish explicitly between action guidance and action assessment. Nevertheless, his treatment of the morality of actions both at the generic level and at the level of circumstances is largely framed in terms of the evaluation or assessment of actions. Albert deals much more explicitly with action guidance in his discussions of prudence, or practical wisdom. There he approaches action from the perspective of the agent's psychology: the practically wise person has a particular kind of 1 See Hursthouse (1999), 49-51. 2 knowledge, Albert thinks, and she deliberates in particular ways. My focus in this dissertation will be primarily on action assessment, or evaluation. In framing my discussion this way I do not mean to imply that Albert's prudens does not take into account the generic quality or the moral circumstances of an action when she deliberates about it. It seems likely that these are exactly the sorts of considerations that will enter her mind, and I find no reason to think Albert would deny it. But he devotes considerable attention to our assessment of actions, and I will follow his lead in focusing on Albert on action assessment or evaluation.2 I contend that Albert